Ping-pong lemma: Difference between revisions
No edit summary |
Citation bot (talk | contribs) Misc citation tidying. | Use this bot. Report bugs. | Suggested by AManWithNoPlan | #UCB_CommandLine |
||
(45 intermediate revisions by 35 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
In [[mathematics]], the '''ping-pong lemma''', or '''table-tennis lemma''', is any of several mathematical statements that ensure that several elements in a group [[group action|acting]] on a set freely [[Generating set of a group|generates]] a [[free group|free]] [[subgroup]] of that group. |
In [[mathematics]], the '''ping-pong lemma''', or '''table-tennis lemma''', is any of several mathematical statements that ensure that several elements in a [[group (mathematics)|group]] [[group action|acting]] on a set freely [[Generating set of a group|generates]] a [[free group|free]] [[subgroup]] of that group. |
||
==History== |
==History== |
||
The ping-pong argument goes back to late 19th century and is commonly attributed<ref name="DH"/> to [[Felix Klein]] who used it to study subgroups of [[Kleinian group]]s, that is, of discrete groups of isometries of the [[hyperbolic 3-space]] or, equivalently [[Möbius transformation]]s of the [[Riemann sphere]]. The ping-pong lemma was a key tool used by [[Jacques Tits]] in his 1972 paper<ref name="T">J. Tits. [ |
The ping-pong argument goes back to the late 19th century and is commonly attributed<ref name="DH"/> to [[Felix Klein]] who used it to study subgroups of [[Kleinian group]]s, that is, of discrete groups of [[isometry|isometries]] of the [[hyperbolic 3-space]] or, equivalently [[Möbius transformation]]s of the [[Riemann sphere]]. The ping-pong lemma was a key tool used by [[Jacques Tits]] in his 1972 paper<ref name="T">J. Tits. [https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/0021869372900580 ''Free subgroups in linear groups.''] [[Journal of Algebra]], vol. 20 (1972), pp. 250–270</ref> containing the [[mathematical proof|proof]] of a famous result now known as the [[Tits alternative]]. The result states that a [[finitely generated group|finitely generated]] [[linear group]] is either [[virtually]] [[solvable group|solvable]] or contains a free subgroup of [[free group|rank]] two. The ping-pong lemma and its variations are widely used in [[geometric topology]] and [[geometric group theory]]. |
||
Modern versions of the ping-pong lemma can be found in many books such as Lyndon&Schupp<ref name="LS">[[Roger Lyndon|Roger C. Lyndon]] and Paul E. Schupp. ''Combinatorial Group Theory.'' Springer-Verlag, New York, 2001. "Classics in Mathematics" series, reprint of the 1977 edition. |
Modern versions of the ping-pong lemma can be found in many books such as Lyndon & Schupp,<ref name="LS">[[Roger Lyndon|Roger C. Lyndon]] and Paul E. Schupp. ''Combinatorial Group Theory.'' Springer-Verlag, New York, 2001. "Classics in Mathematics" series, reprint of the 1977 edition. {{isbn|978-3-540-41158-1}}; Ch II, Section 12, pp. 167–169</ref> de la Harpe,<ref name="DH">Pierre de la Harpe. [https://books.google.com/books?id=cRT01C5ADroC&dq=ping+pong+lemma+group+theory&pg=PA25 ''Topics in geometric group theory.''] Chicago Lectures in Mathematics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. {{isbn|0-226-31719-6}}; Ch. II.B "The table-Tennis Lemma (Klein's criterion) and examples of free products"; pp. 25–41.</ref> Bridson & Haefliger<ref name="BH">Martin R. Bridson, and André Haefliger. [https://books.google.com/books?id=3DjaqB08AwAC&q=Martin+R.+Bridson,+and+Andr%C3%A9+Haefliger.+%22Metric+spaces+of+non-positive+curvature%22 ''Metric spaces of non-positive curvature.''] Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften [Fundamental Principles of Mathematical Sciences], 319. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1999. {{isbn|3-540-64324-9}}; Ch.III.Γ, pp. 467–468</ref> and others. |
||
==Formal statements== |
==Formal statements== |
||
Line 11: | Line 11: | ||
===Ping-pong lemma for several subgroups=== |
===Ping-pong lemma for several subgroups=== |
||
This version of the ping-pong lemma ensures that several |
This version of the ping-pong lemma ensures that several subgroups of a group [[group action|acting]] on a set generate a [[free product]]. The following statement appears in Olijnyk and Suchchansky (2004),<ref>Andrij Olijnyk and Vitaly Suchchansky. [http://www.worldscinet.com/cgi-bin/details.cgi?id=pii:S0218196704001931&type=html Representations of free products by infinite unitriangular matrices over finite fields.] International Journal of Algebra and Computation. Vol. 14 (2004), no. 5–6, pp. 741–749; Lemma 2.1</ref> and the proof is from de la Harpe (2000).<ref name="DH"/> |
||
Let ''G'' be a group acting on a set ''X'' and let ''H''<sub>1</sub>, ''H''<sub>2</sub>, ..., ''H''<sub>''k''</sub> be subgroups of ''G'' where ''k'' ≥ 2, such that at least one of these subgroups has [[order (group theory)|order]] greater than 2. |
|||
⚫ | |||
*For any {{math|''i'' ≠ ''s''}} and for any {{math|''h''}} in {{math|''H''<sub>''i''</sub>}}, {{math|''h'' ≠ 1}} we have {{math|''h''(''X''<sub>''s''</sub>) ⊆ ''X''<sub>''i''</sub>}}. |
|||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
*For any ''i''≠''j'' and for any ''h''∈''H''<sub>''i''</sub>, ''h''≠1 we have ''h''(''X''<sub>''j''</sub>)⊆''X''<sub>''i''</sub>. |
|||
Then |
|||
⚫ | |||
====Proof==== |
====Proof==== |
||
By the definition of free product, it suffices to check that a given (nonempty) reduced word represents a nontrivial element of <math>G</math>. Let <math>w</math> be such a word of length <math>m\geq 2</math>, and let <math display="block">w = \prod_{i=1}^m w_i,</math> where <math display="inline">w_i \in H_{\alpha_i}</math> for some <math display="inline">\alpha_i \in \{1,\dots,k\}</math>. Since <math display="inline">w</math> is reduced, we have <math>\alpha_i \neq \alpha_{i+1}</math> for any <math>i = 1, \dots, m-1</math> and each <math>w_i</math> is distinct from the [[identity element]] of <math>H_{\alpha_i}</math>. We then let <math>w</math> [[group action|act]] on an element of one of the sets <math display="inline">X_i</math>. As we assume that at least one subgroup <math>H_i</math> has order at least 3, [[without loss of generality]] we may assume that <math>H_1</math> has order at least 3. We first make the assumption that <math>\alpha_1</math>and <math>\alpha_m</math> are both 1 (which implies <math>m \geq 3</math>). From here we consider <math>w</math> acting on <math>X_2</math>. We get the following chain of containments: |
|||
By the definition of free product, it suffices to check that a given reduced word is nontrivial. Let ''w'' be such a word, and let |
|||
⚫ | |||
By the assumption that different <math>X_i</math>'s are disjoint, we conclude that <math>w</math> acts nontrivially on some element of <math>X_2</math>, thus <math>w</math> represents a nontrivial element of <math>G</math>. |
|||
:<math> w= \prod_{i=1}^m w_{\alpha_i,\beta_i}. </math> |
|||
⚫ | |||
Where ''w''<sub>''j'',''β''<sub>''k''</sub></sub>∈ ''H''<sub>''j''</sub> for all such ''β''<sub>''k''</sub>, and since ''w'' is fully reduced ''α''<sub>''i''</sub>≠ α<sub>''i''+1 </sub> for any ''i''. We then let ''w'' act on an element of one of the sets ''X''<sub>''i''</sub>. As we assume for at least one subgroup ''H''<sub>i</sub> has order at least 3, without loss we may assume that ''H''<sub>1</sub> is at least 3. We first make the assumption that α<sub>1</sub> and α<sub>m</sub> are both 1. From here we consider ''w'' acting on ''X''<sub>2</sub>. We get the following chain of containments and note that since the ''X''<sub>i</sub> are disjoint that ''w'' acts nontrivially and is thus not the identity element. |
|||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
In each case, <math>hwh^{-1}</math> after reduction becomes a reduced word with its first and last letter in <math>H_1</math>. Finally, <math>hwh^{-1}</math> represents a nontrivial element of <math>G</math>, and so does <math>w</math>. This proves the claim. |
|||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
In each case, ''hwh''<sup>-1</sup> is a reduced word with ''α''<sub>1</sub>' and ''α''<sub>''m'' '</sub>' both 1, and thus is nontrivial. Finally, ''hwh''<sup>-1</sup> is not 1, and so neither is ''w''. This proves the claim. |
|||
===The Ping-pong lemma for cyclic subgroups=== |
===The Ping-pong lemma for cyclic subgroups=== |
||
Let ''G'' be a group |
Let ''G'' be a group acting on a set ''X''. Let ''a''<sub>1</sub>, ...,''a''<sub>''k''</sub> be elements of ''G'' of infinite [[order (group theory)|order]], where ''k'' ≥ 2. Suppose there exist disjoint nonempty subsets |
||
{{block indent | em = 1.5 | text = {{math|''X''<sub>1</sub><sup>+</sup>, ..., ''X''<sub>''k''</sub><sup>+</sup> and ''X''<sub>1</sub><sup>–</sup>, ..., ''X''<sub>''k''</sub><sup>–</sup>}}}} |
|||
of ''X'' with the following properties: |
of {{math|''X''}} with the following properties: |
||
*''a''<sub>''i''</sub>(''X'' |
*{{math|''a''<sub>''i''</sub>(''X'' − ''X''<sub>''i''</sub><sup>–</sup>) ⊆ ''X''<sub>''i''</sub><sup>+</sup>}} for {{math|1=''i'' = 1, ..., ''k''}}; |
||
*{{math|''a''<sub>''i''</sub><sup>−1</sup>(''X'' − ''X''<sub>''i''</sub><sup>+</sup>) ⊆ ''X''<sub>''i''</sub><sup>–</sup>}} for {{math|1=''i'' = 1, ..., ''k''}}. |
|||
Then the subgroup {{math|1=''H'' = {{angbr|''a''<sub>1</sub>, ..., ''a''<sub>''k''</sub>}} ≤ ''G''}} [[Generating set of a group|generated]] by ''a''<sub>1</sub>, ..., ''a''<sub>''k''</sub> is [[free group|free]] with free basis {{math|{''a''<sub>1</sub>, ..., ''a''<sub>''k''</sub>}<nowiki/>}}. |
|||
Then the subgroup ''H'' = <''a''<sub>1</sub>, ..., ''a''<sub>''k''</sub>> ≤ ''G'' [[Generating set of a group|generated]] by ''a''<sub>1</sub>, ..., ''a''<sub>''k''</sub> is [[free group|free]] with free basis {''a''<sub>1</sub>, ..., ''a''<sub>''k''</sub>}. |
|||
====Proof==== |
====Proof==== |
||
This statement follows as a corollary of the version for general subgroups if we let ''X''<sub>''i''</sub>= ''X''<sub>''i''</sub><sup>+</sup>∪''X''<sub>''i''</sub><sup> |
This statement follows as a [[corollary]] of the version for general subgroups if we let {{math|1=''X''<sub>''i''</sub> = ''X''<sub>''i''</sub><sup>+</sup> ∪ ''X''<sub>''i''</sub><sup>−</sup>}} and let {{math|1=''H''<sub>''i''</sub> = ⟨''a''<sub>''i''</sub>⟩}}. |
||
==Examples== |
==Examples== |
||
=== |
===Special linear group example=== |
||
One can use the ping-pong lemma to prove<ref name="DH"/> that the subgroup ''H'' = |
One can use the ping-pong lemma to prove<ref name="DH"/> that the subgroup {{math|1=''H'' = {{angbr|''A'',''B''}} ≤ [[special linear group|SL]]<sub>2</sub>('''Z''')}}, generated by the [[matrix (mathematics)|matrices]] |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
====Proof==== |
====Proof==== |
||
Indeed, let ''H''<sub>1</sub> = |
Indeed, let {{math|1=''H''<sub>1</sub> = {{angbr|''A''}}}} and {{math|1=''H''<sub>2</sub> = {{angbr|''B''}}}} be [[cyclic subgroup]]s of {{math|SL<sub>2</sub>('''Z''')}} generated by {{math|''A''}} and {{math|''B''}} accordingly. It is not hard to check that {{math|''A''}} and {{math|''B''}} are elements of infinite order in {{math|SL<sub>2</sub>('''Z''')}} and that |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
and |
and |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
and |
and |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | It is not hard to check, using the above explicit descriptions of ''H''<sub>1</sub> and ''H''<sub>2</sub>, that for every nontrivial {{math|''g'' ∈ ''H''<sub>1</sub>}} we have {{math|''g''(''X''<sub>2</sub>) ⊆ ''X''<sub>1</sub>}} and that for every nontrivial {{math|''g'' ∈ ''H''<sub>2</sub>}} we have {{math|''g''(''X''<sub>1</sub>) ⊆ ''X''<sub>2</sub>}}. Using the alternative form of the ping-pong lemma, for two subgroups, given above, we conclude that {{math|1=''H'' = ''H''<sub>1</sub> ∗ ''H''<sub>2</sub>}}. Since the groups {{math|''H''<sub>1</sub>}} and {{math|''H''<sub>2</sub>}} are infinite [[cyclic group|cyclic]], it follows that ''H'' is a [[free group]] of rank two. |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | It is not hard to check, using the above |
||
⚫ | Let {{math|''G''}} be a [[word-hyperbolic group]] which is [[torsion-free group|torsion-free]], that is, with no nonidentity elements of finite [[Order (group theory)|order]]. Let {{math|''g'', ''h'' ∈ ''G''}} be two non-commuting elements, that is such that {{math|''gh'' ≠ ''hg''}}. Then there exists ''M'' ≥ 1 such that for any [[integer]]s {{math|''n'' ≥ ''M''}}, {{math|''m'' ≥ ''M''}} the subgroup {{math|1=H = {{angbr|''g''<sup>''n''</sup>, ''h''<sup>''m''</sup>}} ≤ ''G''}} is free of rank two. |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | Let ''G'' be a [[word-hyperbolic group]] which is [[torsion-free group|torsion-free]], that is, with no |
||
⚫ | The group ''G'' acts on its ''hyperbolic boundary'' ∂''G'' by [[homeomorphism]]s. It is known that if ''a'' in ''G'' is a nonidentity element then ''a'' has exactly two distinct fixed points, {{math|''a''<sup>∞</sup>}} and {{math|''a''<sup>−∞</sup>}} in {{math|∂''G''}} and that {{math|''a''<sup>∞</sup>}} is an [[attracting fixed point]] while {{math|''a''<sup>−∞</sup>}} is a [[Fixed point (mathematics)|repelling fixed point]]. |
||
⚫ | Since {{math|''g''}} and {{math|''h''}} do not commute, basic facts about word-hyperbolic groups imply that {{math|''g''<sup>∞</sup>}}, {{math|''g''<sup>−∞</sup>}}, {{math|''h''<sup>∞</sup>}} and {{math|''h''<sup>−∞</sup>}} are four distinct points in {{math|∂''G''}}. Take disjoint [[Neighbourhood (mathematics)|neighborhoods]] {{math|''U''<sub>+</sub>}}, {{math|''U''<sub>–</sub>}}, {{math|''V''<sub>+</sub>}}, and {{math|''V''<sub>–</sub>}} of {{math|''g''<sup>∞</sup>}}, {{math|''g''<sup>−∞</sup>}}, {{math|''h''<sup>∞</sup>}} and {{math|''h''<sup>−∞</sup>}} in {{math|∂''G''}} respectively. |
||
====Sketch of the proof<ref name="Gromov">M. Gromov. ''Hyperbolic groups.'' Essays in group theory, pp. 75–263, |
|||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | The group ''G'' |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | Since ''g'' and ''h'' do not commute, |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
==Applications of the ping-pong lemma== |
==Applications of the ping-pong lemma== |
||
*The ping-pong lemma is used in [[Kleinian group]]s to study their so-called [[Schottky group|Schottky subgroups]]. In the Kleinian groups context the ping-pong lemma can be used to show that a particular group of isometries of the [[hyperbolic 3-space]] is not just [[free group|free]] but also [[properly discontinuous]] and [[geometrically finite group|geometrically finite]]. |
*The ping-pong lemma is used in [[Kleinian group]]s to study their so-called [[Schottky group|Schottky subgroups]]. In the Kleinian groups context the ping-pong lemma can be used to show that a particular group of isometries of the [[hyperbolic 3-space]] is not just [[free group|free]] but also [[properly discontinuous]] and [[geometrically finite group|geometrically finite]]. |
||
*Similar Schottky-type arguments are widely used in [[geometric group theory]], particularly for subgroups of [[word-hyperbolic group]]s<ref name="Gromov"/> and for automorphism |
*Similar Schottky-type arguments are widely used in [[geometric group theory]], particularly for subgroups of [[word-hyperbolic group]]s<ref name="Gromov"/> and for [[automorphism group]]s of trees.<ref>[[Alexander Lubotzky]]. [https://doi.org/10.1007%2FBF01895641 ''Lattices in rank one Lie groups over local fields.''] [[Geometric and Functional Analysis]], vol. 1 (1991), no. 4, pp. 406–431</ref> |
||
* |
*The ping-pong lemma is also used for studying Schottky-type subgroups of [[mapping class group]]s of [[Riemann surface]]s, where the set on which the mapping class group acts is the Thurston boundary of the [[Teichmüller space]].<ref>Richard P. Kent, and Christopher J. Leininger. ''Subgroups of mapping class groups from the geometrical viewpoint.'' In the tradition of Ahlfors-Bers. IV, pp. 119–141, |
||
Contemporary Mathematics series, 432, [[American Mathematical Society]], Providence, RI, 2007; |
Contemporary Mathematics series, 432, [[American Mathematical Society]], Providence, RI, 2007; {{isbn|978-0-8218-4227-0}}; 0-8218-4227-7</ref> A similar argument is also utilized in the study of subgroups of the [[outer automorphism group]] of a free group.<ref>[[Mladen Bestvina|M. Bestvina]], M. Feighn, and M. Handel. [https://doi.org/10.1007%2FPL00001618 ''Laminations, trees, and irreducible automorphisms of free groups.''] [[Geometric and Functional Analysis]], vol. 7 (1997), no. 2, pp. 215–244.</ref> |
||
*One of the most famous applications of the ping-pong lemma is in the proof of [[Jacques Tits]] of the so-called [[Tits alternative]] for [[linear group]]s. |
*One of the most famous applications of the ping-pong lemma is in the proof of [[Jacques Tits]] of the so-called [[Tits alternative]] for [[linear group]]s.<ref name="T"/> (see also <ref>Pierre de la Harpe. ''Free groups in linear groups.'' L'Enseignement Mathématique (2), vol. 29 (1983), no. 1-2, pp. 129–144</ref> for an overview of Tits' proof and an explanation of the ideas involved, including the use of the ping-pong lemma). |
||
*There are generalizations of the ping-pong lemma that produce not just [[free product]]s but also [[free product with amalgamation|amalgamated free products]] and [[HNN extension]]s<ref name="LS"/> |
*There are generalizations of the ping-pong lemma that produce not just [[free product]]s but also [[free product with amalgamation|amalgamated free products]] and [[HNN extension]]s.<ref name="LS"/> These generalizations are used, in particular, in the proof of [[Maskit's Combination Theorem]] for Kleinian groups.<ref>[[Bernard Maskit]]. |
||
''Kleinian groups.'' Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften [Fundamental Principles of Mathematical Sciences], 287. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1988. |
''Kleinian groups.'' Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften [Fundamental Principles of Mathematical Sciences], 287. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1988. {{isbn|3-540-17746-9}}; Ch. VII.C and Ch. VII.E pp.149–156 and pp. 160–167</ref> |
||
*There are also versions of the ping-pong lemma which guarantee that several elements in a group generate a [[free semigroup]]. Such versions are available both in the general context of a [[group action]] on a set<ref name="DH1">Pierre de la Harpe. [ |
*There are also versions of the ping-pong lemma which guarantee that several elements in a group generate a [[free semigroup]]. Such versions are available both in the general context of a [[group action]] on a set,<ref name="DH1">Pierre de la Harpe. [https://books.google.com/books?id=cRT01C5ADroC&q=semi-group&pg=PA188 ''Topics in geometric group theory.''] Chicago Lectures in Mathematics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. {{isbn|0-226-31719-6}}; Ch. II.B "The table-Tennis Lemma (Klein's criterion) and examples of free products"; pp. 187–188.</ref> and for specific types of actions, e.g. in the context of linear groups,<ref>Alex Eskin, Shahar Mozes and Hee Oh. [https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs00222-004-0378-z On uniform exponential growth for linear groups.] [[Inventiones Mathematicae]]. vol. 60 (2005), no. 1, pp.1432–1297; Lemma 2.2</ref> groups [[Bass–Serre theory|acting on trees]]<ref>Roger C. Alperin and Guennadi A. Noskov. [https://books.google.com/books?id=w7LO6AkB8Y8C&dq=%22ping-pong+lemma%22+semigroup&pg=PA2 Uniform growth, actions on trees and GL<sub>2</sub>.] Computational and Statistical Group Theory:AMS Special Session Geometric Group Theory, April 21–22, 2001, Las Vegas, Nevada, AMS Special Session Computational Group Theory, April 28–29, 2001, Hoboken, New Jersey. (Robert H. Gilman, Vladimir Shpilrain, Alexei G. Myasnikov, editors). [[American Mathematical Society]], 2002. {{isbn|978-0-8218-3158-8}}; page 2, Lemma 3.1</ref> and others.<ref>Yves de Cornulier and Romain Tessera. [http://msp.warwick.ac.uk/gt/2008/12-01/p011.xhtml Quasi-isometrically embedded free sub-semigroups.] ''[[Geometry & Topology]]'', vol. 12 (2008), pp. 461–473; Lemma 2.1</ref> |
||
==References== |
==References== |
||
{{reflist}} |
{{reflist}} |
||
==See also== |
==See also== |
||
Line 123: | Line 107: | ||
*[[Schottky group]] |
*[[Schottky group]] |
||
[[Category: |
[[Category:Lemmas in group theory]] |
||
[[Category:Group theory]] |
|||
[[Category:Discrete groups]] |
[[Category:Discrete groups]] |
||
[[Category:Lie groups]] |
[[Category:Lie groups]] |
||
[[Category:Combinatorics on words]] |
[[Category:Combinatorics on words]] |
||
[[tr:Klein kriteri]] |
Latest revision as of 14:59, 20 March 2023
In mathematics, the ping-pong lemma, or table-tennis lemma, is any of several mathematical statements that ensure that several elements in a group acting on a set freely generates a free subgroup of that group.
History
[edit]The ping-pong argument goes back to the late 19th century and is commonly attributed[1] to Felix Klein who used it to study subgroups of Kleinian groups, that is, of discrete groups of isometries of the hyperbolic 3-space or, equivalently Möbius transformations of the Riemann sphere. The ping-pong lemma was a key tool used by Jacques Tits in his 1972 paper[2] containing the proof of a famous result now known as the Tits alternative. The result states that a finitely generated linear group is either virtually solvable or contains a free subgroup of rank two. The ping-pong lemma and its variations are widely used in geometric topology and geometric group theory.
Modern versions of the ping-pong lemma can be found in many books such as Lyndon & Schupp,[3] de la Harpe,[1] Bridson & Haefliger[4] and others.
Formal statements
[edit]Ping-pong lemma for several subgroups
[edit]This version of the ping-pong lemma ensures that several subgroups of a group acting on a set generate a free product. The following statement appears in Olijnyk and Suchchansky (2004),[5] and the proof is from de la Harpe (2000).[1]
Let G be a group acting on a set X and let H1, H2, ..., Hk be subgroups of G where k ≥ 2, such that at least one of these subgroups has order greater than 2. Suppose there exist pairwise disjoint nonempty subsets X1, X2, ...,Xk of X such that the following holds:
- For any i ≠ s and for any h in Hi, h ≠ 1 we have h(Xs) ⊆ Xi.
Then
Proof
[edit]By the definition of free product, it suffices to check that a given (nonempty) reduced word represents a nontrivial element of . Let be such a word of length , and let where for some . Since is reduced, we have for any and each is distinct from the identity element of . We then let act on an element of one of the sets . As we assume that at least one subgroup has order at least 3, without loss of generality we may assume that has order at least 3. We first make the assumption that and are both 1 (which implies ). From here we consider acting on . We get the following chain of containments:
By the assumption that different 's are disjoint, we conclude that acts nontrivially on some element of , thus represents a nontrivial element of .
To finish the proof we must consider the three cases:
- if , then let (such an exists since by assumption has order at least 3);
- if , then let ;
- and if , then let .
In each case, after reduction becomes a reduced word with its first and last letter in . Finally, represents a nontrivial element of , and so does . This proves the claim.
The Ping-pong lemma for cyclic subgroups
[edit]Let G be a group acting on a set X. Let a1, ...,ak be elements of G of infinite order, where k ≥ 2. Suppose there exist disjoint nonempty subsets
of X with the following properties:
- ai(X − Xi–) ⊆ Xi+ for i = 1, ..., k;
- ai−1(X − Xi+) ⊆ Xi– for i = 1, ..., k.
Then the subgroup H = ⟨a1, ..., ak⟩ ≤ G generated by a1, ..., ak is free with free basis {a1, ..., ak}.
Proof
[edit]This statement follows as a corollary of the version for general subgroups if we let Xi = Xi+ ∪ Xi− and let Hi = ⟨ai⟩.
Examples
[edit]Special linear group example
[edit]One can use the ping-pong lemma to prove[1] that the subgroup H = ⟨A,B⟩ ≤ SL2(Z), generated by the matrices and is free of rank two.
Proof
[edit]Indeed, let H1 = ⟨A⟩ and H2 = ⟨B⟩ be cyclic subgroups of SL2(Z) generated by A and B accordingly. It is not hard to check that A and B are elements of infinite order in SL2(Z) and that and
Consider the standard action of SL2(Z) on R2 by linear transformations. Put and
It is not hard to check, using the above explicit descriptions of H1 and H2, that for every nontrivial g ∈ H1 we have g(X2) ⊆ X1 and that for every nontrivial g ∈ H2 we have g(X1) ⊆ X2. Using the alternative form of the ping-pong lemma, for two subgroups, given above, we conclude that H = H1 ∗ H2. Since the groups H1 and H2 are infinite cyclic, it follows that H is a free group of rank two.
Word-hyperbolic group example
[edit]Let G be a word-hyperbolic group which is torsion-free, that is, with no nonidentity elements of finite order. Let g, h ∈ G be two non-commuting elements, that is such that gh ≠ hg. Then there exists M ≥ 1 such that for any integers n ≥ M, m ≥ M the subgroup H = ⟨gn, hm⟩ ≤ G is free of rank two.
The group G acts on its hyperbolic boundary ∂G by homeomorphisms. It is known that if a in G is a nonidentity element then a has exactly two distinct fixed points, a∞ and a−∞ in ∂G and that a∞ is an attracting fixed point while a−∞ is a repelling fixed point.
Since g and h do not commute, basic facts about word-hyperbolic groups imply that g∞, g−∞, h∞ and h−∞ are four distinct points in ∂G. Take disjoint neighborhoods U+, U–, V+, and V– of g∞, g−∞, h∞ and h−∞ in ∂G respectively. Then the attracting/repelling properties of the fixed points of g and h imply that there exists M ≥ 1 such that for any integers n ≥ M, m ≥ M we have:
- gn(∂G – U–) ⊆ U+
- g−n(∂G – U+) ⊆ U–
- hm(∂G – V–) ⊆ V+
- h−m(∂G – V+) ⊆ V–
The ping-pong lemma now implies that H = ⟨gn, hm⟩ ≤ G is free of rank two.
Applications of the ping-pong lemma
[edit]- The ping-pong lemma is used in Kleinian groups to study their so-called Schottky subgroups. In the Kleinian groups context the ping-pong lemma can be used to show that a particular group of isometries of the hyperbolic 3-space is not just free but also properly discontinuous and geometrically finite.
- Similar Schottky-type arguments are widely used in geometric group theory, particularly for subgroups of word-hyperbolic groups[6] and for automorphism groups of trees.[7]
- The ping-pong lemma is also used for studying Schottky-type subgroups of mapping class groups of Riemann surfaces, where the set on which the mapping class group acts is the Thurston boundary of the Teichmüller space.[8] A similar argument is also utilized in the study of subgroups of the outer automorphism group of a free group.[9]
- One of the most famous applications of the ping-pong lemma is in the proof of Jacques Tits of the so-called Tits alternative for linear groups.[2] (see also [10] for an overview of Tits' proof and an explanation of the ideas involved, including the use of the ping-pong lemma).
- There are generalizations of the ping-pong lemma that produce not just free products but also amalgamated free products and HNN extensions.[3] These generalizations are used, in particular, in the proof of Maskit's Combination Theorem for Kleinian groups.[11]
- There are also versions of the ping-pong lemma which guarantee that several elements in a group generate a free semigroup. Such versions are available both in the general context of a group action on a set,[12] and for specific types of actions, e.g. in the context of linear groups,[13] groups acting on trees[14] and others.[15]
References
[edit]- ^ a b c d Pierre de la Harpe. Topics in geometric group theory. Chicago Lectures in Mathematics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. ISBN 0-226-31719-6; Ch. II.B "The table-Tennis Lemma (Klein's criterion) and examples of free products"; pp. 25–41.
- ^ a b J. Tits. Free subgroups in linear groups. Journal of Algebra, vol. 20 (1972), pp. 250–270
- ^ a b Roger C. Lyndon and Paul E. Schupp. Combinatorial Group Theory. Springer-Verlag, New York, 2001. "Classics in Mathematics" series, reprint of the 1977 edition. ISBN 978-3-540-41158-1; Ch II, Section 12, pp. 167–169
- ^ Martin R. Bridson, and André Haefliger. Metric spaces of non-positive curvature. Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften [Fundamental Principles of Mathematical Sciences], 319. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1999. ISBN 3-540-64324-9; Ch.III.Γ, pp. 467–468
- ^ Andrij Olijnyk and Vitaly Suchchansky. Representations of free products by infinite unitriangular matrices over finite fields. International Journal of Algebra and Computation. Vol. 14 (2004), no. 5–6, pp. 741–749; Lemma 2.1
- ^ a b M. Gromov. Hyperbolic groups. Essays in group theory, pp. 75–263, Mathematical Sciences Research Institute Publications, 8, Springer, New York, 1987; ISBN 0-387-96618-8; Ch. 8.2, pp. 211–219.
- ^ Alexander Lubotzky. Lattices in rank one Lie groups over local fields. Geometric and Functional Analysis, vol. 1 (1991), no. 4, pp. 406–431
- ^ Richard P. Kent, and Christopher J. Leininger. Subgroups of mapping class groups from the geometrical viewpoint. In the tradition of Ahlfors-Bers. IV, pp. 119–141, Contemporary Mathematics series, 432, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2007; ISBN 978-0-8218-4227-0; 0-8218-4227-7
- ^ M. Bestvina, M. Feighn, and M. Handel. Laminations, trees, and irreducible automorphisms of free groups. Geometric and Functional Analysis, vol. 7 (1997), no. 2, pp. 215–244.
- ^ Pierre de la Harpe. Free groups in linear groups. L'Enseignement Mathématique (2), vol. 29 (1983), no. 1-2, pp. 129–144
- ^ Bernard Maskit. Kleinian groups. Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften [Fundamental Principles of Mathematical Sciences], 287. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1988. ISBN 3-540-17746-9; Ch. VII.C and Ch. VII.E pp.149–156 and pp. 160–167
- ^ Pierre de la Harpe. Topics in geometric group theory. Chicago Lectures in Mathematics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. ISBN 0-226-31719-6; Ch. II.B "The table-Tennis Lemma (Klein's criterion) and examples of free products"; pp. 187–188.
- ^ Alex Eskin, Shahar Mozes and Hee Oh. On uniform exponential growth for linear groups. Inventiones Mathematicae. vol. 60 (2005), no. 1, pp.1432–1297; Lemma 2.2
- ^ Roger C. Alperin and Guennadi A. Noskov. Uniform growth, actions on trees and GL2. Computational and Statistical Group Theory:AMS Special Session Geometric Group Theory, April 21–22, 2001, Las Vegas, Nevada, AMS Special Session Computational Group Theory, April 28–29, 2001, Hoboken, New Jersey. (Robert H. Gilman, Vladimir Shpilrain, Alexei G. Myasnikov, editors). American Mathematical Society, 2002. ISBN 978-0-8218-3158-8; page 2, Lemma 3.1
- ^ Yves de Cornulier and Romain Tessera. Quasi-isometrically embedded free sub-semigroups. Geometry & Topology, vol. 12 (2008), pp. 461–473; Lemma 2.1