Jump to content

Suppressed correlative: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Citation bot (talk | contribs)
Add: doi, pages, chapter-url. Removed or converted URL. Removed parameters. Some additions/deletions were parameter name changes. | Use this bot. Report bugs. | Suggested by Abductive | via #UCB_webform 731/975
reword, since skateboard has wheels and sled does notDescription
 
(2 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 11: Line 11:
Alternatively Person 2 can redefine X in way that instead concludes all things are not X.
Alternatively Person 2 can redefine X in way that instead concludes all things are not X.


A simple example based on one by [[Alexander Bain]]:<ref>{{harvnb|Bain|1884|p=56}}</ref>
A simple example based on one by [[Alexander Bain (philosopher)|Alexander Bain]]:<ref>{{harvnb|Bain|1884|p=56}}</ref>


:Person 1: "Things are either mysterious or not mysterious. Exactly when an earthquake will strike is still a mystery, but how blood circulates in the body is not."
:Person 1: "Things are either mysterious or not mysterious. Exactly when an earthquake will strike is still a mystery, but how blood circulates in the body is not."
Line 18: Line 18:
Regardless of whether Person 2's statement about blood circulation is true or not, the redefinition of "mysterious" is so broad that it omits significant contrast in the level of scientific understanding between earthquakes and blood circulation. Bain argues that if we hold the [[origin of the universe]] as equally mysterious against simple equations such as 3×4=12, it seems unimaginable what kind of concepts would be described as ''non''-mysterious. Through redefinition, the word "mysterious" has lost any useful meaning, he says.
Regardless of whether Person 2's statement about blood circulation is true or not, the redefinition of "mysterious" is so broad that it omits significant contrast in the level of scientific understanding between earthquakes and blood circulation. Bain argues that if we hold the [[origin of the universe]] as equally mysterious against simple equations such as 3×4=12, it seems unimaginable what kind of concepts would be described as ''non''-mysterious. Through redefinition, the word "mysterious" has lost any useful meaning, he says.


The redefinition is not always so obvious. At first glance it might appear reasonable to define brakes as "a method to quickly stop a vehicle"; however, this permits all vehicles to be described as having brakes. Any car could be driven into a sturdy barrier to stop it, but to therefore say the car has brakes seems absurd.
The redefinition is not always so obvious. At first glance it might appear reasonable to define brakes as "a method to quickly stop a vehicle"; however, this permits all vehicles to be described as having brakes. A sled could be driven into a sturdy barrier to stop it, but to therefore say the sled has brakes seems absurd.


This type of fallacy is often used in conjunction with one of the [[fallacies of definition]].{{Citation needed|date=April 2011}} It is an [[informal fallacy]].<ref name="Chadwick"/>
This type of fallacy is often used in conjunction with one of the [[fallacies of definition]].{{Citation needed|date=April 2011}} It is an [[informal fallacy]].<ref name="Chadwick"/>
Line 24: Line 24:
==Usage==
==Usage==


The Scottish logician [[Alexander Bain]] discussed the fallacy of suppressed correlative, which he also called the fallacy of suppressed relative, in the 19th century. He provided many example relative pairs where the correlative terms find their meaning through contrast: rest-toil, knowledge-ignorance, silence-speech, and so on.<ref>{{harvnb|Bain|1884|pp=43–46}}</ref> Bain classified this type of error as a fallacy of relativity, which in turn was one of many fallacies of confusion.<ref>{{harvnb|Bain|1870|pp=391}}</ref>
The Scottish logician [[Alexander Bain (philosopher)|Alexander Bain]] discussed the fallacy of suppressed correlative, which he also called the fallacy of suppressed relative, in the 19th century. He provided many example relative pairs where the correlative terms find their meaning through contrast: rest-toil, knowledge-ignorance, silence-speech, and so on.<ref>{{harvnb|Bain|1884|pp=43–46}}</ref> Bain classified this type of error as a fallacy of relativity, which in turn was one of many fallacies of confusion.<ref>{{harvnb|Bain|1870|pp=391}}</ref>


J. Loewenberg rejected a certain definition of [[empirical method]] – one that seemed so broad as to encompass all possible methods – as committing the fallacy of suppressed correlative.<ref>{{harvnb|Martin|1970|p=3}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |first=J. |last=Loewenberg |title=What is Empirical? |journal=Journal of Philosophy |date=May 23, 1940 |volume=XXXVII |number=11 |pages=281–289 |doi=10.2307/2017549 |jstor=2017549}}</ref> This error has been said to be found in the philosophy of some empiricists, including [[Edgar S. Brightman]], sometimes in broadening the meaning of other terms relevant to these arguments, such as "[[perception]]" (when taken to include entirely cognitive processes in addition to ones usually classified as perceptual).<ref>{{harvnb|Martin|1970|p=38}}; {{harvnb|Martin|1970|p=69}}</ref>
J. Loewenberg rejected a certain definition of [[empirical method]] – one that seemed so broad as to encompass all possible methods – as committing the fallacy of suppressed correlative.<ref>{{harvnb|Martin|1970|p=3}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |first=J. |last=Loewenberg |title=What is Empirical? |journal=Journal of Philosophy |date=May 23, 1940 |volume=XXXVII |number=11 |pages=281–289 |doi=10.2307/2017549 |jstor=2017549}}</ref> This error has been said to be found in the philosophy of some empiricists, including [[Edgar S. Brightman]], sometimes in broadening the meaning of other terms relevant to these arguments, such as "[[perception]]" (when taken to include entirely cognitive processes in addition to ones usually classified as perceptual).<ref>{{harvnb|Martin|1970|p=38}}; {{harvnb|Martin|1970|p=69}}</ref>
Line 36: Line 36:
===Notes===
===Notes===
{{Reflist|colwidth=40em}}
{{Reflist|colwidth=40em}}

===Works===
===Works===
*{{cite book |first=Alexander |last=Bain |title=Logic: Part Second: Induction |year=1870 |publisher=Longmans, Green, Reader, & Dyer |url=https://archive.org/details/logic00baingoog|page=[https://archive.org/details/logic00baingoog/page/n419 391] }}
*{{cite book |first=Alexander |last=Bain |title=Logic: Part Second: Induction |year=1870 |publisher=Longmans, Green, Reader, & Dyer |url=https://archive.org/details/logic00baingoog|page=[https://archive.org/details/logic00baingoog/page/n419 391] }}

Latest revision as of 20:34, 15 October 2023

The fallacy of suppressed correlative is a type of argument that tries to redefine a correlative (one of two mutually exclusive options) so that one alternative encompasses the other, i.e. making one alternative impossible.[1] This has also been known as the fallacy of lost contrast[2] and the fallacy of the suppressed relative.[3]

Description

[edit]

A conceptual example:

Person 1: "All things are either X or not X." (The correlatives: X–not X.)
Person 2: "I define X such that all things that you claim are not X are included in X." (The suppressed correlative: not X.)

Alternatively Person 2 can redefine X in way that instead concludes all things are not X.

A simple example based on one by Alexander Bain:[4]

Person 1: "Things are either mysterious or not mysterious. Exactly when an earthquake will strike is still a mystery, but how blood circulates in the body is not."
Person 2: "Everything is mysterious. There are still things to be learned about how blood circulates."

Regardless of whether Person 2's statement about blood circulation is true or not, the redefinition of "mysterious" is so broad that it omits significant contrast in the level of scientific understanding between earthquakes and blood circulation. Bain argues that if we hold the origin of the universe as equally mysterious against simple equations such as 3×4=12, it seems unimaginable what kind of concepts would be described as non-mysterious. Through redefinition, the word "mysterious" has lost any useful meaning, he says.

The redefinition is not always so obvious. At first glance it might appear reasonable to define brakes as "a method to quickly stop a vehicle"; however, this permits all vehicles to be described as having brakes. A sled could be driven into a sturdy barrier to stop it, but to therefore say the sled has brakes seems absurd.

This type of fallacy is often used in conjunction with one of the fallacies of definition.[citation needed] It is an informal fallacy.[2]

Usage

[edit]

The Scottish logician Alexander Bain discussed the fallacy of suppressed correlative, which he also called the fallacy of suppressed relative, in the 19th century. He provided many example relative pairs where the correlative terms find their meaning through contrast: rest-toil, knowledge-ignorance, silence-speech, and so on.[5] Bain classified this type of error as a fallacy of relativity, which in turn was one of many fallacies of confusion.[6]

J. Loewenberg rejected a certain definition of empirical method – one that seemed so broad as to encompass all possible methods – as committing the fallacy of suppressed correlative.[7][8] This error has been said to be found in the philosophy of some empiricists, including Edgar S. Brightman, sometimes in broadening the meaning of other terms relevant to these arguments, such as "perception" (when taken to include entirely cognitive processes in addition to ones usually classified as perceptual).[9]

Critics identify the fallacy in arguments for psychological egoism, which proposes that all actions conducted by individuals are motivated by their own self-interest. Outside of this idea it is believed that sometimes people do things selflessly, such as acts of charitable giving or self-sacrifice. Psychological egoism explains all scenarios entirely in terms of selfish motivations (e.g., that acting for one's own purposes is an act of self-interest); however, critics charge that in doing so they are redefining selfishness to the point where it encompasses all motivated actions and thus makes the term meaningless.[1]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ a b Feinberg, Joel (2007). "Psychological Egoism". In Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.). Ethical Theory: An Anthology. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 193. ISBN 978-1-4051-3320-3.
  2. ^ a b Chadwick, Ruth F., ed. (1998). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics. Vol. 2. Academic Press. p. 559. ISBN 978-0-12-227067-3.
  3. ^ Bain 1884, p. 54
  4. ^ Bain 1884, p. 56
  5. ^ Bain 1884, pp. 43–46
  6. ^ Bain 1870, pp. 391
  7. ^ Martin 1970, p. 3
  8. ^ Loewenberg, J. (May 23, 1940). "What is Empirical?". Journal of Philosophy. XXXVII (11): 281–289. doi:10.2307/2017549. JSTOR 2017549.
  9. ^ Martin 1970, p. 38; Martin 1970, p. 69

Works

[edit]