Jump to content

Inconsistent triad: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m Replace magic links with templates per local RfC and MediaWiki RfC
m Reverting possible vandalism by 82.19.59.200 to version by HolmKønøman. Report False Positive? Thanks, ClueBot NG. (4309254) (Bot)
 
(35 intermediate revisions by 24 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Three propositions of which at most two can be true}}
{{Refimprove|date=May 2008}}
{{Refimprove|date=May 2008}}


Line 4: Line 5:


# Alice loves me.
# Alice loves me.
# If Alice loves me, then she would have sent flowers.
# Alice sends flowers to people she loves.
# Alice has not sent flowers.
# Alice has not sent me flowers.


If one finds oneself believing all three propositions of an inconsistent triad, then (in order to be rational) one must give up or modify at least one of those beliefs. Maybe Alice doesn't love me, or maybe she wouldn't send flowers to me if she did, or maybe she actually has sent flowers.
If one finds oneself believing all three propositions of an inconsistent triad, then (in order to be rational) one must give up or modify at least one of those beliefs. Maybe Alice doesn't love me, or maybe she wouldn't send flowers to me if she did, or maybe she actually has sent flowers.


Any inconsistent triad {{math|{A, B, C}}} gives rise to a [[trilemma]] {{math|{{A, B}, {B, C}, {C, A}}}}.
Any inconsistent triad {{math|{A, B, C}}} gives rise to a [[trilemma]] {{math|{{A, B}, {B, C}, {C, A}}}}.

== Perception and objects ==
The dialectical framework for the whole discussion of the problem in the philosophy of perception and the theoretical conception of perceptual experience is set out as an inconsistent triad.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199260256.001.0001/acprof-9780199260256|title=Perception and its Objects|last=Brewer|first=Bill|date=2011-03-01|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=9780191725470|language=en-US|doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199260256.001.0001}}</ref>

# Physical objects are mind-independent.
# Physical objects are the direct objects of perception.
# The direct objects of perception are mind-dependent.

The first proposition is defended by [[Philosophical realism|realists]], while being rejected by [[Anti-realism|anti-realists]] or [[Idealism|idealists]].


== The problem of evil ==
== The problem of evil ==
{{Main article|Problem of evil}}
{{Main article|Problem of evil}}


The problem of evil is often given in the form of an inconsistent triad. For example, [[J. L. Mackie]] gave the following three propositions:
The [[problem of evil]] is often given in the form of an inconsistent triad. For example, [[J. L. Mackie]] gave the following three propositions:


# God is omnipotent
# God is [[Omnipotence|omnipotent]]
# God is omnibenevolent
# God is [[Omnibenevolence|omnibenevolent]]
# Evil exists
#[[Evil]] exists


Mackie argued that these propositions were inconsistent, and thus, that at least one of these propositions must be false. Either:
Mackie argued that these propositions were inconsistent, and thus, that at least one of these propositions must be false. Either:
Line 25: Line 35:
* God is omnibenevolent, but not omnipotent; thus, evil exists, but it is not within God's power to stop it (at least not instantaneously).
* God is omnibenevolent, but not omnipotent; thus, evil exists, but it is not within God's power to stop it (at least not instantaneously).


[[Problem of evil#Answers and theodicies|Many responses]] have been made to the problem of evil, including the proposition that evil exists as a consequence of a greater good, such as free will; that evil is an illusion; and that evil is necessary for spiritual growth.
[[Problem of evil#Responses, defences and theodicies|Many responses]] have been made to the problem of evil, including the proposition that evil exists as a consequence of a greater good, such as free will; that evil is an illusion; and that evil is necessary for spiritual growth.


== See also ==
== See also ==
* [[Trilemma]]
* [[Reductio ad absurdum]]
* [[Reductio ad absurdum]]
* [[Trilemma]]
* [[CAP theorem]]


== References ==
== References ==
Line 36: Line 47:
* Howard-Snyder, F., Howard-Snyder, D., & Wasserman, R. (2009). ''[http://catalogs.mhhe.com/mhhe/viewProductDetails.do?isbn=0073407372 The Power of Logic]'' (4th Edition). New York: McGraw-Hill. (p.&nbsp;336) {{ISBN|978-0-07-340737-1}}
* Howard-Snyder, F., Howard-Snyder, D., & Wasserman, R. (2009). ''[http://catalogs.mhhe.com/mhhe/viewProductDetails.do?isbn=0073407372 The Power of Logic]'' (4th Edition). New York: McGraw-Hill. (p.&nbsp;336) {{ISBN|978-0-07-340737-1}}


[[Category:Logical fallacies]]
[[Category:Syllogistic fallacies]]
[[Category:Problem of evil]]
[[Category:Theodicy]]

Latest revision as of 21:55, 20 March 2024

An inconsistent triad consists of three propositions of which at most two can be true. For example:

  1. Alice loves me.
  2. Alice sends flowers to people she loves.
  3. Alice has not sent me flowers.

If one finds oneself believing all three propositions of an inconsistent triad, then (in order to be rational) one must give up or modify at least one of those beliefs. Maybe Alice doesn't love me, or maybe she wouldn't send flowers to me if she did, or maybe she actually has sent flowers.

Any inconsistent triad {A, B, C} gives rise to a trilemma {{A, B}, {B, C}, {C, A}}.

Perception and objects

[edit]

The dialectical framework for the whole discussion of the problem in the philosophy of perception and the theoretical conception of perceptual experience is set out as an inconsistent triad.[1]

  1. Physical objects are mind-independent.
  2. Physical objects are the direct objects of perception.
  3. The direct objects of perception are mind-dependent.

The first proposition is defended by realists, while being rejected by anti-realists or idealists.

The problem of evil

[edit]

The problem of evil is often given in the form of an inconsistent triad. For example, J. L. Mackie gave the following three propositions:

  1. God is omnipotent
  2. God is omnibenevolent
  3. Evil exists

Mackie argued that these propositions were inconsistent, and thus, that at least one of these propositions must be false. Either:

  • God is omnipotent and omnibenevolent, and evil does not exist.
  • God is omnipotent, but not omnibenevolent; thus, evil exists by God's will.
  • God is omnibenevolent, but not omnipotent; thus, evil exists, but it is not within God's power to stop it (at least not instantaneously).

Many responses have been made to the problem of evil, including the proposition that evil exists as a consequence of a greater good, such as free will; that evil is an illusion; and that evil is necessary for spiritual growth.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Brewer, Bill (2011-03-01). Perception and its Objects. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199260256.001.0001. ISBN 9780191725470.