Jump to content

Pseudorationalism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
m A criticism of "rational absolutism": spelling: adresses → addresses
 
(12 intermediate revisions by 8 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Lead rewrite|date=August 2022|reason=Very difficult to understand what this word means}}
'''Pseudorationalism''' was the label given by economist and philosopher [[Otto Neurath]] to a school of thought that he was heavily critical of, throughout many of his writings but primarily in his 1913 paper "The lost wanderers of Descartes and the auxiliary motive" and later to a lesser extent in his 1935 "Pseudorationalismus der Falsifikation",<ref>{{cite journal
|title=Pseudorationalismus der Falsifikation |author=Otto Neurath |journal=[[Erkenntnis]] |year=1935 |volume=5 |number=1 |pages=353–365 |doi=10.1007/BF00172326}}</ref> a review of and attack on [[Karl Popper|Popper]]'s first book, ''Logik der Forschung'' (''[[The Logic of Scientific Discovery]]''), contrasting this approach with his own view of what [[rationalism]] should properly be.{{sfn|Uebel|2008|p=54}} Neurath aimed his criticism at a [[René Descartes|Cartes]]ian belief that all actions can be subject to rational analysis,{{sfn|Cartwright|Cat|Fleck|Uebel|2008|p=129}}{{sfn|Reisch|2005|p=31}}{{sfn|O'Neill|2008|p=84}} saying that


'''Pseudorationalism''' was the label given by economist and philosopher [[Otto Neurath]] to a school of thought that he was heavily critical of, which relies on an erroneous vision of the process of thinking and moral action. He made these criticisms throughout many of his writings, but primarily in his 1913 paper "The lost wanderers of Descartes and the auxiliary motive"<ref name=":0">{{Citation |last=Neurath |first=Otto |title=The Lost Wanderers of Descartes and the Auxiliary Motive |date=1983 |work=Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English |pages=8 |editor-last=Neurath |editor-first=Otto |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_1 |access-date=2024-03-09 |series=Vienna Circle Collection |place=Dordrecht |publisher=Springer Netherlands |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_1 |isbn=978-94-009-6995-7 |editor2-last=Cohen |editor2-first=Robert Sonné |editor3-last=Neurath |editor3-first=Marie}}</ref> and later to a lesser extent in his 1935 "Pseudorationalismus der Falsifikation".<ref>{{Citation |last=Neurath |first=Otto |title=Pseudorationalism of Falsification |date=1983 |work=Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English |pages=121–131 |editor-last=Neurath |editor-first=Otto |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_10 |access-date=2024-03-09 |series=Vienna Circle Collection |place=Dordrecht |publisher=Springer Netherlands |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_10 |isbn=978-94-009-6995-7 |editor2-last=Cohen |editor2-first=Robert Sonné |editor3-last=Neurath |editor3-first=Marie}}</ref>
{{quote|Once reason has gained a certain influence, people generally show a tendency to regard all their actions as reasonable. Ways of action which depend on dark instincts receive reinterpretation or obfuscation.|{{sfn|Cartwright|Cat|Fleck|Uebel|2008|p=129}} {{harvnb|Neurath|1913|p=441}}}}


== A criticism of the naive conception of reason ==
Neurath considered that "pseudo-rationalists", be they philosophers or scientists, made the mistake of assuming that a complete rational system could be devised for the [[natural law|laws of nature]]. He argued rather that no system could be complete, being based upon an picture of reality that could only ever be incomplete and imperfect. Pseudo-rationalism, in Neurath's view, was a refusal or simple inability to face up to the limits of rationality and reason.{{sfn|Cartwright|Cat|Fleck|Uebel|2008|p=129}} "Rationalism", he wrote {{harv|Neurath|1913|p=8}}, "sees its chief triumph in the clear recognition of the limits of actual insight.". Whereas a pseudorationalist acknowledges no such limits, but rather contents that ''all'' decisions can be subject to the rules of insight.{{sfn|O'Neill|2008|p=84}} Scientific method is, according to Neurath, pseudorationalist where it contends that the rules for the [[scientific method]] will always lead ever closer to the truth.{{sfn|O'Neill|2008|p=84}}
In "The lost wanderers of Descartes and the auxiliary motive", Neurath writes that "Descartes was of the opinion that, in the field of theory, by forming successive series of statements that one has recognised as defmitely true, one could reach a complete picture of the world".<ref name=":0" /> Moreover, especially in the ''[[Principles of Philosophy]]'', [[René Descartes|Descartes]] sharply distinguished thinking and action, and rejected the possibility of having provisional rules in the moral and practical field, which is an assumption Neurath rejects.


Descartes' approach can thus be metaphorically described as "lost wanderers," suggesting a solitary and introspective journey towards certainty and knowledge, starting from a point of complete skepticism.
Neurath further challenged Cartesian "pseudorationalism" by asserting that operating upon incomplete data was in fact the norm, where Cartesian thinking would have it be the rare exception. Rather than there being one, final, rational answer to any given problem, Neurath asserted that scientific endeavour required a continuing and never ending series of choices, made so in part because of the ambiguity of language.{{sfn|Reisch|2005|p=31}}

Neurath introduced the parable of the boat in another article, 'Protocol statements' (1932), and not in his 1913 paper. This metaphor describes science and knowledge as a never-ending voyage where we must repair our ship at sea, without ever being able to start anew from the ground up. It emphasizes the collective, provisional, and piecemeal nature of scientific endeavor, contrasting sharply with Descartes' pursuit of an indubitable foundation for knowledge.:<blockquote>There is no way to establish fully secured, neat protocol statements as starting points of the sciences. There is no ''tabula rasa''. We are like sailors who have to rebuild their ship on the open sea, without ever being able to dismantle it in dry-dock and reconstruct it from its best components.<ref>{{Citation |last=Neurath |first=Otto |title=Protocol Statements |date=1983 |work=Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English |pages=92 |editor-last=Neurath |editor-first=Otto |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_7 |access-date=2024-03-09 |series=Vienna Circle Collection |place=Dordrecht |publisher=Springer Netherlands |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_7 |isbn=978-94-009-6995-7 |editor2-last=Cohen |editor2-first=Robert Sonné |editor3-last=Neurath |editor3-first=Marie}}</ref></blockquote>
Thus, pseudorationalism can be understood as a misunderstanding of Descartes' principles, and can lead to a form of cynicism. "Pseudorationalism leads partly to self-deception, partly to hypocrisy".<ref name=":0" /> It is a "belief in powers that regulate existence and foretell the future" and according to Neurath, is similar to superstion. It can be identified to a special form of naive [[scientism]].

== A criticism of "rational absolutism" ==
The second paper mentioning pseudorationalism was a review of [[Karl Popper|Popper]]'s first book, ''Logik der Forschung'' (''[[The Logic of Scientific Discovery]]''), contrasting this approach with his own view of what [[rationalism]] should properly be.{{sfn|Uebel|2008|p=54}} Neurath criticises the cumulative conception of knowledge endowed by Popper. For instance, Popper writes that:<blockquote>For a theory which has been well corroborated can only be superseded by one of a higher level of universality; that is, by a theory which is better testable and which, in addition, ''contains'' the old, well corroborated theory—or at least a good approximation to it. It may be better, therefore, to describe that trend—the advance towards theories of an ever higher level of universality—as ‘quasi-inductive’.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Popper |first=Karl |title=The logic of scientific discovery |date=2010 |publisher=Routledge |orig-year=1934 |isbn=978-0-415-27844-7 |edition=Special Indian |location=London |pages=250}}</ref></blockquote>

Neurath's criticism addresses the fact that the various steps of gravitational theory can barely be understood as approximations of ''one'' theory. He is relying on [[Pierre Duhem]]'s work ''The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory''<ref>{{Cite book |last=Duhem |first=Pierre |title=The aim and structure of physical theory |last2=Wiener |first2=Philip P. |last3=Vuillemin |first3=Jules |last4=Duhem |first4=Pierre |date=1991 |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-02524-7 |edition=1. Princeton paperback printing |series=The Princeton science library |location=Princeton, NJ}}</ref>''.''

Another aspect of his critique suggests that Popper advocates for a form of traditional absolutism, in which all scientific theories progressively converge towards a comprehensive understanding of the world.<ref>{{Citation |last=Neurath |first=Otto |title=Pseudorationalism of Falsification |date=1983 |work=Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English |pages=130 |editor-last=Neurath |editor-first=Otto |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_10 |access-date=2024-03-09 |series=Vienna Circle Collection |place=Dordrecht |publisher=Springer Netherlands |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_10 |isbn=978-94-009-6995-7 |editor2-last=Cohen |editor2-first=Robert Sonné |editor3-last=Neurath |editor3-first=Marie}}</ref> According to Neurath, pseudorationalists, much more successful in the 1930's than it was before, make the mistake of assuming a complete picture of reality, an impossibility which leads them to further false assumptions.

Consequently, the necessity for calculation in kind ushered in a demand for an alternative approach to practical reasoning. This new approach diverged significantly from the precise, astronomical ideals epitomized by [[Pierre-Simon Laplace|Laplace]] in science, as well as from the rationalist and individualist principles associated with Descartes in philosophy. He termed this departure "pseudorationality," a concept he later identified within Popper's perspectives.

Rationalism is thus an epistemological and political doctrine, destined to fight theses avatars of rationalism.<ref name=":0" /> <blockquote>
Rationalism sees its chief triumph in the clear recognition of the limits of actual insight. I tend to derive the widespread tendency towards pseudo-rationalism from the same unconscious endeavours as the tendency towards superstition.<ref name=":0" /></blockquote>Pseudorationalism also refers to Neurath's conception of economics and his criticism of the misusage of the concept of rationality.<ref>{{Cite book |last=O'Neill |first=John |title=The market: ethics, knowledge, and politics |date=1998 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-415-09827-4 |series=Economics as social theory |location=London : New York, NY}}</ref>


==References==
==References==
{{reflist|30em}}
{{reflist|30em}}
{{refbegin}}
{{refbegin}}
* {{cite book|ref=harv|title=Otto Neurath: Philosophy Between Science and Politics|volume=38|series=Ideas in Context|first1=Nancy|last1=Cartwright|first2=Jordi|last2=Cat|first3=Lola|last3=Fleck|first4=Thomas E.|last4=Uebel|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=2008|isbn=978-0-521-04111-9}}
* {{cite book|title=Otto Neurath: Philosophy Between Science and Politics|volume=38|series=Ideas in Context|first1=Nancy|last1=Cartwright|first2=Jordi|last2=Cat|first3=Lola|last3=Fleck|first4=Thomas E.|last4=Uebel|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=2008|isbn=978-0-521-04111-9}}
* {{cite book|ref=harv|title=Otto Neurath's economics in context|volume=13|series=Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook|editor1-first=Elisabeth|editor1-last=Nemeth|editor2-first=Stefan W.|editor2-last=Schmitz|first=J.F.|last=O'Neill|publisher=Springer|year=2008|isbn=978-1-4020-6904-8|chapter=Pluralism and economic institutions}}
* {{cite book|title=Otto Neurath's economics in context|volume=13|series=Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook|editor1-first=Elisabeth|editor1-last=Nemeth|editor2-first=Stefan W.|editor2-last=Schmitz|first=J.F.|last=O'Neill|publisher=Springer|year=2008|isbn=978-1-4020-6904-8|chapter=Pluralism and economic institutions}}
* {{cite book|ref=harv|title=How the Cold War transformed philosophy of science: to the icy slopes of logic|first=George A.|last=Reisch|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=2005|isbn=978-0-521-54689-8}}
* {{cite book|title=How the Cold War transformed philosophy of science: to the icy slopes of logic|first=George A.|last=Reisch|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=2005|isbn=978-0-521-54689-8}}
* {{cite book|ref=harv|title=Otto Neurath's economics in context|volume=13|series=Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook|editor1-first=Elisabeth|editor1-last=Nemeth|editor2-first=Stefan W.|editor2-last=Schmitz|first=Thomas Ernst|last=Uebel|publisher=Springer|year=2008|isbn=978-1-4020-6904-8|chapter=Otto Neurath as an Austrian Economist}}
* {{cite book|title=Otto Neurath's economics in context|volume=13|series=Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook|editor1-first=Elisabeth|editor1-last=Nemeth|editor2-first=Stefan W.|editor2-last=Schmitz|first=Thomas Ernst|last=Uebel|publisher=Springer|year=2008|isbn=978-1-4020-6904-8|chapter=Otto Neurath as an Austrian Economist}}
{{refend}}
{{refend}}
== Further reading ==
== Further reading ==
* {{cite journal|ref=harv|authorlink=Otto Neurath|first=Otto|last=Neurath|title=Die Verirrten des Cartesius und das Auxiliarmotiv:Zur Psychologie des Entschlusses|language=German|year=1913|journal=Jahrbuch der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität Wien}}
* {{cite journal|authorlink=Otto Neurath|first=Otto|last=Neurath|title=Die Verirrten des Cartesius und das Auxiliarmotiv:Zur Psychologie des Entschlusses|language=German|year=1913|journal=Jahrbuch der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität Wien}}

{{philosophy-stub}}


[[Category:Metatheory of science]]
[[Category:Metatheory of science]]
[[Category:Rationalism]]
[[Category:Rationalism]]


{{science-philo-stub}}

Latest revision as of 02:46, 22 April 2024

Pseudorationalism was the label given by economist and philosopher Otto Neurath to a school of thought that he was heavily critical of, which relies on an erroneous vision of the process of thinking and moral action. He made these criticisms throughout many of his writings, but primarily in his 1913 paper "The lost wanderers of Descartes and the auxiliary motive"[1] and later to a lesser extent in his 1935 "Pseudorationalismus der Falsifikation".[2]

A criticism of the naive conception of reason

[edit]

In "The lost wanderers of Descartes and the auxiliary motive", Neurath writes that "Descartes was of the opinion that, in the field of theory, by forming successive series of statements that one has recognised as defmitely true, one could reach a complete picture of the world".[1] Moreover, especially in the Principles of Philosophy, Descartes sharply distinguished thinking and action, and rejected the possibility of having provisional rules in the moral and practical field, which is an assumption Neurath rejects.

Descartes' approach can thus be metaphorically described as "lost wanderers," suggesting a solitary and introspective journey towards certainty and knowledge, starting from a point of complete skepticism.

Neurath introduced the parable of the boat in another article, 'Protocol statements' (1932), and not in his 1913 paper. This metaphor describes science and knowledge as a never-ending voyage where we must repair our ship at sea, without ever being able to start anew from the ground up. It emphasizes the collective, provisional, and piecemeal nature of scientific endeavor, contrasting sharply with Descartes' pursuit of an indubitable foundation for knowledge.:

There is no way to establish fully secured, neat protocol statements as starting points of the sciences. There is no tabula rasa. We are like sailors who have to rebuild their ship on the open sea, without ever being able to dismantle it in dry-dock and reconstruct it from its best components.[3]

Thus, pseudorationalism can be understood as a misunderstanding of Descartes' principles, and can lead to a form of cynicism. "Pseudorationalism leads partly to self-deception, partly to hypocrisy".[1] It is a "belief in powers that regulate existence and foretell the future" and according to Neurath, is similar to superstion. It can be identified to a special form of naive scientism.

A criticism of "rational absolutism"

[edit]

The second paper mentioning pseudorationalism was a review of Popper's first book, Logik der Forschung (The Logic of Scientific Discovery), contrasting this approach with his own view of what rationalism should properly be.[4] Neurath criticises the cumulative conception of knowledge endowed by Popper. For instance, Popper writes that:

For a theory which has been well corroborated can only be superseded by one of a higher level of universality; that is, by a theory which is better testable and which, in addition, contains the old, well corroborated theory—or at least a good approximation to it. It may be better, therefore, to describe that trend—the advance towards theories of an ever higher level of universality—as ‘quasi-inductive’.[5]

Neurath's criticism addresses the fact that the various steps of gravitational theory can barely be understood as approximations of one theory. He is relying on Pierre Duhem's work The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory[6].

Another aspect of his critique suggests that Popper advocates for a form of traditional absolutism, in which all scientific theories progressively converge towards a comprehensive understanding of the world.[7] According to Neurath, pseudorationalists, much more successful in the 1930's than it was before, make the mistake of assuming a complete picture of reality, an impossibility which leads them to further false assumptions.

Consequently, the necessity for calculation in kind ushered in a demand for an alternative approach to practical reasoning. This new approach diverged significantly from the precise, astronomical ideals epitomized by Laplace in science, as well as from the rationalist and individualist principles associated with Descartes in philosophy. He termed this departure "pseudorationality," a concept he later identified within Popper's perspectives.

Rationalism is thus an epistemological and political doctrine, destined to fight theses avatars of rationalism.[1]

Rationalism sees its chief triumph in the clear recognition of the limits of actual insight. I tend to derive the widespread tendency towards pseudo-rationalism from the same unconscious endeavours as the tendency towards superstition.[1]

Pseudorationalism also refers to Neurath's conception of economics and his criticism of the misusage of the concept of rationality.[8]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c d e Neurath, Otto (1983), Neurath, Otto; Cohen, Robert Sonné; Neurath, Marie (eds.), "The Lost Wanderers of Descartes and the Auxiliary Motive", Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English, Vienna Circle Collection, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, p. 8, doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_1, ISBN 978-94-009-6995-7, retrieved 2024-03-09
  2. ^ Neurath, Otto (1983), Neurath, Otto; Cohen, Robert Sonné; Neurath, Marie (eds.), "Pseudorationalism of Falsification", Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English, Vienna Circle Collection, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 121–131, doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_10, ISBN 978-94-009-6995-7, retrieved 2024-03-09
  3. ^ Neurath, Otto (1983), Neurath, Otto; Cohen, Robert Sonné; Neurath, Marie (eds.), "Protocol Statements", Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English, Vienna Circle Collection, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, p. 92, doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_7, ISBN 978-94-009-6995-7, retrieved 2024-03-09
  4. ^ Uebel 2008, p. 54.
  5. ^ Popper, Karl (2010) [1934]. The logic of scientific discovery (Special Indian ed.). London: Routledge. p. 250. ISBN 978-0-415-27844-7.
  6. ^ Duhem, Pierre; Wiener, Philip P.; Vuillemin, Jules; Duhem, Pierre (1991). The aim and structure of physical theory. The Princeton science library (1. Princeton paperback printing ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02524-7.
  7. ^ Neurath, Otto (1983), Neurath, Otto; Cohen, Robert Sonné; Neurath, Marie (eds.), "Pseudorationalism of Falsification", Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English, Vienna Circle Collection, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, p. 130, doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_10, ISBN 978-94-009-6995-7, retrieved 2024-03-09
  8. ^ O'Neill, John (1998). The market: ethics, knowledge, and politics. Economics as social theory. London : New York, NY: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-09827-4.
  • Cartwright, Nancy; Cat, Jordi; Fleck, Lola; Uebel, Thomas E. (2008). Otto Neurath: Philosophy Between Science and Politics. Ideas in Context. Vol. 38. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-04111-9.
  • O'Neill, J.F. (2008). "Pluralism and economic institutions". In Nemeth, Elisabeth; Schmitz, Stefan W. (eds.). Otto Neurath's economics in context. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook. Vol. 13. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4020-6904-8.
  • Reisch, George A. (2005). How the Cold War transformed philosophy of science: to the icy slopes of logic. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-54689-8.
  • Uebel, Thomas Ernst (2008). "Otto Neurath as an Austrian Economist". In Nemeth, Elisabeth; Schmitz, Stefan W. (eds.). Otto Neurath's economics in context. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook. Vol. 13. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4020-6904-8.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Neurath, Otto (1913). "Die Verirrten des Cartesius und das Auxiliarmotiv:Zur Psychologie des Entschlusses". Jahrbuch der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität Wien (in German).