Jump to content

Universal wavefunction: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m Changed: "and forms" to informs.
Tags: Visual edit Mobile edit Mobile web edit
m Role of observers: replaced citations which were generating warnings
 
(26 intermediate revisions by 13 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Use American English|date=January 2019}}{{Short description|Concept in some interpretations of quantum mechanics
{{Short description|Quantum state of the entire universe}}
The '''universal wavefunction''' or the '''wavefunction of the universe''' is the [[wavefunction]] or [[quantum state]] of the entire [[universe]].<ref>Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", introduction, pg 8–9</ref> It is regarded as the basic physical entity<ref>Everett 1957, section 3, 2nd paragraph, 1st sentence.</ref> in the [[many-worlds interpretation]] of [[quantum mechanics]],<ref name="everett57">[[Hugh Everett]], Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics, ''Reviews of Modern Physics'' vol 29, (1957) pp 454–462. An abridged summary of ''The Theory of the Universal Wavefunction''</ref><ref>[[John Archibald Wheeler]], Assessment of Everett's "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Theory", ''Reviews of Modern Physics'', vol 29, (1957) pp 463–465</ref><ref>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]],
}}
The '''universal wavefunction''' (or '''wave function''') is a term introduced by [[Hugh Everett]] in his [[PhD]] thesis<ref>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], [[R. Neill Graham]], eds, ''The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics'', Princeton Series in Physics, [[Princeton University Press]] (1973), {{ISBN|0-691-08131-X}} Contains Everett's thesis: ''The Theory of the Universal Wave Function'', pp 3–140.</ref> ''The Theory of the Universal Wave Function informs'' a core concept in the [[Many-worlds interpretation#Relative state|relative state interpretation]]<ref name="everett57">[[Hugh Everett]], Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics, ''Reviews of Modern Physics'' vol 29, (1957) pp 454–462. An abridged summary of ''The Theory of the Universal Wavefunction''</ref><ref>[[John Archibald Wheeler]], Assessment of Everett's "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Theory", ''Reviews of Modern Physics'', vol 29, (1957) pp 463–465</ref> or [[many-worlds interpretation]]<ref>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]],
Quantum Mechanics and Reality, ''Physics Today'',23(9) pp 30–40 (1970) also April 1971 letters followup
Quantum Mechanics and Reality, ''Physics Today'',23(9) pp 30–40 (1970) also April 1971 letters followup
</ref><ref>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], The Many-Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, ''Proceedings of the International School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" Course IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', [[Academic Press]] (1972)
</ref><ref>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], The Many-Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, ''Proceedings of the International School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" Coursu IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', [[Academic Press]] (1972)
</ref> and finds applications in [[quantum cosmology]]. It evolves deterministically according to a wave equation.<ref>Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", chapter 6 (e)</ref>
</ref> of [[quantum mechanics]]. It has also received more recent investigation from [[James Hartle]] and [[Stephen Hawking]]<ref>[[Stephen Hawking|Stephen W Hawking]], [[James Hartle|James B Hartle]] "The Wave Function of the Universe," ''Physical Review D'', vol 28, (1983) pp 2960–2975</ref> in which they derive a specific solution to the [[Wheeler–deWitt equation]] to explain the initial conditions of the [[Big Bang]] cosmology.


The concept of universal wavefunction was introduced by [[Hugh Everett]] in his 1956 PhD thesis draft ''The Theory of the Universal Wave Function''.<ref>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], [[R. Neill Graham]], eds, ''The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics'', Princeton Series in Physics, [[Princeton University Press]] (1973), {{ISBN|0-691-08131-X}} Contains the reprint of Everett's thesis: ''The Theory of the Universal Wave Function'', pp 3–140.</ref> It later received investigation from [[James Hartle]] and [[Stephen Hawking]]<ref>[[Stephen Hawking|Stephen W Hawking]], [[James Hartle|James B Hartle]] "The Wave Function of the Universe," ''Physical Review D'', vol 28, (1983) pp 2960–2975</ref> who derived the [[Hartle–Hawking state|Hartle–Hawking solution]] to the [[Wheeler–deWitt equation]] to explain the initial conditions of the [[Big Bang]] cosmology.
Everett's thesis introduction reads:
{{Quote|Since the universal validity of the state function description is asserted, one can regard the state functions themselves as the fundamental entities, and one can even consider the state function of the entire universe. In this sense this theory can be called the theory of the "universal wave function," since all of physics is presumed to follow from this function alone.<ref>Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", introduction, pg 8–9</ref>}}


==Role of observers==
The universal wave function is the [[wavefunction]] or [[quantum state]] of the totality of existence, regarded as the "basic physical entity"<ref>Everett 1957, section 3, 2nd paragraph, 1st sentence.</ref> or "the fundamental entity, obeying at all times a deterministic wave equation."<ref>Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", chapter 6 (e)</ref>


[[Hugh Everett]]'s universal wavefunction supports the idea that observed and observer are all mixed together:
==Everett's Response to Streater==
{{Quote|If we try to limit the applicability so as to exclude the measuring apparatus, or in general systems of macroscopic size, we are faced with the difficulty of sharply defining the region of validity. For what '''n''' might a group of '''n''' particles be construed as forming a measuring device so that the quantum description fails? And to draw the line at human or animal observers, i.e., to assume that all mechanical apparata obey the usual laws, but that they are not valid for living observers, does violence to the so-called principle of [[Psychophysical parallelism|psycho-physical parallelism]].''<ref>Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", introduction, pg 6</ref>}}
[[Ray Streater]] writes:
{{Quote|The idea of the wave-function of the universe is meaningless; we do not even know what variables it is supposed to be a function of. [...] We find the laws of Nature by reproducible experiments. The theory needs a cut, between the observer and the system, and the details of the apparatus should not appear in the theory of the system.<ref>{{Cite web |url=http://www.mth.kcl.ac.uk/~streater/lostcauses.html |title="lost causes" web page |access-date=2005-04-03 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20050403215217/http://www.mth.kcl.ac.uk/~streater/lostcauses.html#XII |archive-date=2005-04-03 |url-status=dead }}</ref>}}


[[Eugene Wigner]] and [[John Archibald Wheeler]] take issue with this stance. Wigner wrote:
[[Hugh Everett]]'s response:
{{Quote|The state vector of my mind, even if it were completely known, would not give its impressions. A translation from state vector to impressions would be necessary; without such a translation the state vector would be meaningless.<ref name="t895">{{cite book | last=Wigner | first=E. P. | title=Philosophical Reflections and Syntheses | chapter=Epistemological Perspective on Quantum Theory | publisher=Springer Berlin Heidelberg | publication-place=Berlin, Heidelberg | date=1973 | isbn=978-3-540-63372-3 | doi=10.1007/978-3-642-78374-6_5 | page=55–71}}</ref>}}
{{Quote|If we try to limit the applicability so as to exclude the measuring apparatus, or in general systems of macroscopic size, we are faced with the difficulty of sharply defining the region of validity. For what '''n''' might a group of '''n''' particles be construed as forming a measuring device so that the quantum description fails? And to draw the line at human or animal observers, i.e., to assume that all mechanical aparata obey the usual laws, but that they are not valid for living observers, does violence to the so-called principle of [[Psychophysical parallelism|psycho-physical parallelism]].''<ref>Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", introduction, pg 6</ref>}}

Wheeler wrote:
{{Quote|One is led to recognize that a wave function 'encompassing the whole universe' is an idealization, formalistically perhaps a convenient idealization, but an idealization so strained that it can be used only in part in any forecast of correlations that makes physical sense. For making sense it seems essential most of all to 'leave the observer out of the wave function'.<ref name="v766">{{cite book | last=Wheeler | first=John Archibald | title=Quantum Mechanics, A Half Century Later | chapter=Include the Observer in the Wave Function? | publisher=Springer Netherlands | publication-place=Dordrecht | date=1977 | isbn=978-94-010-1198-3 | doi=10.1007/978-94-010-1196-9_1 | page=1–18}}</ref>}}


==See also==
==See also==
* [[Hartle–Hawking state]]
* [[Heisenberg cut]]
* [[Heisenberg cut]]



Latest revision as of 11:08, 8 August 2024

The universal wavefunction or the wavefunction of the universe is the wavefunction or quantum state of the entire universe.[1] It is regarded as the basic physical entity[2] in the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics,[3][4][5][6] and finds applications in quantum cosmology. It evolves deterministically according to a wave equation.[7]

The concept of universal wavefunction was introduced by Hugh Everett in his 1956 PhD thesis draft The Theory of the Universal Wave Function.[8] It later received investigation from James Hartle and Stephen Hawking[9] who derived the Hartle–Hawking solution to the Wheeler–deWitt equation to explain the initial conditions of the Big Bang cosmology.

Role of observers

[edit]

Hugh Everett's universal wavefunction supports the idea that observed and observer are all mixed together:

If we try to limit the applicability so as to exclude the measuring apparatus, or in general systems of macroscopic size, we are faced with the difficulty of sharply defining the region of validity. For what n might a group of n particles be construed as forming a measuring device so that the quantum description fails? And to draw the line at human or animal observers, i.e., to assume that all mechanical apparata obey the usual laws, but that they are not valid for living observers, does violence to the so-called principle of psycho-physical parallelism.[10]

Eugene Wigner and John Archibald Wheeler take issue with this stance. Wigner wrote:

The state vector of my mind, even if it were completely known, would not give its impressions. A translation from state vector to impressions would be necessary; without such a translation the state vector would be meaningless.[11]

Wheeler wrote:

One is led to recognize that a wave function 'encompassing the whole universe' is an idealization, formalistically perhaps a convenient idealization, but an idealization so strained that it can be used only in part in any forecast of correlations that makes physical sense. For making sense it seems essential most of all to 'leave the observer out of the wave function'.[12]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", introduction, pg 8–9
  2. ^ Everett 1957, section 3, 2nd paragraph, 1st sentence.
  3. ^ Hugh Everett, Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics, Reviews of Modern Physics vol 29, (1957) pp 454–462. An abridged summary of The Theory of the Universal Wavefunction
  4. ^ John Archibald Wheeler, Assessment of Everett's "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Theory", Reviews of Modern Physics, vol 29, (1957) pp 463–465
  5. ^ Bryce Seligman DeWitt, Quantum Mechanics and Reality, Physics Today,23(9) pp 30–40 (1970) also April 1971 letters followup
  6. ^ Bryce Seligman DeWitt, The Many-Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Proceedings of the International School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" Coursu IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Academic Press (1972)
  7. ^ Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", chapter 6 (e)
  8. ^ Bryce Seligman DeWitt, R. Neill Graham, eds, The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton Series in Physics, Princeton University Press (1973), ISBN 0-691-08131-X Contains the reprint of Everett's thesis: The Theory of the Universal Wave Function, pp 3–140.
  9. ^ Stephen W Hawking, James B Hartle "The Wave Function of the Universe," Physical Review D, vol 28, (1983) pp 2960–2975
  10. ^ Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", introduction, pg 6
  11. ^ Wigner, E. P. (1973). "Epistemological Perspective on Quantum Theory". Philosophical Reflections and Syntheses. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg. p. 55–71. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-78374-6_5. ISBN 978-3-540-63372-3.
  12. ^ Wheeler, John Archibald (1977). "Include the Observer in the Wave Function?". Quantum Mechanics, A Half Century Later. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. p. 1–18. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-1196-9_1. ISBN 978-94-010-1198-3.