Jump to content

Observable: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
 
(43 intermediate revisions by 30 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Any entity that can be measured}}
{{About|the use in physics|the use in statistics|Observable variable|the use in [[control theory]]|Observability}}
{{About|the use in physics|the use in statistics|Observable variable|the use in control theory|Observability|the use in software engineering|Observer pattern}}


{{No footnotes|date=May 2009}}
{{More footnotes|date=May 2009}}


In [[physics]], an '''observable''' is a [[physical quantity]] that can be measured. Examples include [[Position (vector)|position]] and [[momentum]]. In systems governed by [[classical mechanics]], it is a [[real number|real]]-valued [[function (mathematics)|function]] on the set of all possible system states. In [[quantum physics]], it is an operator, or [[gauge theory|gauge]], where the property of the [[Quantum state|system state]] can be determined by some sequence of physical [[operational definition|operations]]. For example, these operations might involve submitting the system to various [[electromagnetic field]]s and eventually reading a value.
In [[physics]], an '''observable''' is a [[physical property]] or [[physical quantity]] that can be [[Measurement|measured]]. In [[classical mechanics]], an observable is a [[real number|real]]-valued "function" on the set of all possible system states, e.g., [[Position (vector)|position]] and [[momentum]]. In [[quantum mechanics]], an observable is an [[quantum operator|operator]], or [[gauge theory|gauge]], where the property of the [[quantum state]] can be determined by some sequence of [[operational definition|operations]]. For example, these operations might involve submitting the system to various [[electromagnetic field]]s and eventually reading a value.


Physically meaningful observables must also satisfy [[linear map|transformation]] laws which relate observations performed by different [[observation|observer]]s in different [[frames of reference]]. These transformation laws are [[automorphism]]s of the state space, that is [[bijection|bijective]] [[transformation (mathematics)|transformation]]s which preserve certain mathematical properties of the space in question.
Physically meaningful observables must also satisfy [[linear map|transformation]] laws that relate observations performed by different [[observation|observer]]s in different [[frames of reference]]. These transformation laws are [[automorphism]]s of the [[state space (physics)|state space]], that is [[bijection|bijective]] [[transformation (mathematics)|transformation]]s that preserve certain mathematical properties of the space in question.


== Quantum mechanics ==
== Quantum mechanics ==


In [[quantum physics]], observables manifest as [[linear operators]] on a [[Hilbert space]] representing the [[state space]] of quantum states. The eigenvalues of observables are [[real numbers]] that correspond to possible values the dynamical variable represented by the observable can be measured as having. That is, observables in quantum mechanics assign real numbers to outcomes of ''particular measurements'', corresponding to the [[eigenvalue]] of the operator with respect to the system's measured [[quantum state]]. As a consequence, only certain measurements can determine the value of an observable for some state of a quantum system. In classical mechanics, ''any'' measurement can be made to determine the value of an observable.
In [[quantum mechanics]], observables manifest as [[self-adjoint operators]] on a [[separable space|separable]] [[complex number|complex]] [[Hilbert space]] representing the [[quantum state space]].{{sfn | Teschl | 2014 | pp=65-66}} Observables assign values to outcomes of ''particular measurements'', corresponding to the [[eigenvalue]] of the operator. If these outcomes represent physically allowable states (i.e. those that belong to the Hilbert space) the eigenvalues are [[real number|real]]; however, the converse is not necessarily true.<ref>See page 20 of [http://bohr.physics.berkeley.edu/classes/221/1112/notes/hilbert.pdf Lecture notes 1 by Robert Littlejohn] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230829114950/https://bohr.physics.berkeley.edu/classes/221/1112/notes/hilbert.pdf|date=2023-08-29}} for a mathematical discussion using the momentum operator as specific example.</ref>{{sfn|de la Madrid Modino|2001|pp=95-97}}<ref>{{cite book |last1=Ballentine |first1=Leslie |title=Quantum Mechanics: A Modern Development |date=2015 |publisher=World Scientific |isbn=978-9814578578 |page=49 |edition=2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2JShngEACAAJ}}</ref> As a consequence, only certain measurements can determine the value of an observable for some state of a quantum system. In classical mechanics, ''any'' measurement can be made to determine the value of an observable.


The relation between the state of a quantum system and the value of an observable requires some [[linear algebra]] for its description. In the [[mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics]], states are given by non-zero [[vector (geometry)|vector]]s in a [[Hilbert space]] ''V''. Two vectors '''v''' and '''w''' are considered to specify the same state if and only if <math>\mathbf{w} = c\mathbf{v}</math> for some non-zero <math>c \in \Complex</math>. Observables are given by [[self-adjoint operator]]s on ''V''. However, as indicated below, not every self-adjoint operator corresponds to a physically meaningful observable{{citation needed|date=April 2018}}. For the case of a system of [[Elementary particle|particle]]s, the space ''V'' consists of functions called [[wave function]]s or [[Quantum state|state vectors]].
The relation between the state of a quantum system and the value of an observable requires some [[linear algebra]] for its description. In the [[mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics]], up to a [[Phase factor|phase constant]], [[pure state]]s are given by non-zero [[vector (geometry)|vector]]s in a [[Hilbert space]] ''V''. Two vectors '''v''' and '''w''' are considered to specify the same state if and only if <math>\mathbf{w} = c\mathbf{v}</math> for some non-zero <math>c \in \Complex</math>. Observables are given by [[self-adjoint operator]]s on ''V''. Not every self-adjoint operator corresponds to a physically meaningful observable.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Isham |first1=Christopher |author1link = Christopher Isham|title=Lectures On Quantum Theory: Mathematical And Structural Foundations |date=1995 |publisher=World Scientific |isbn=191129802X |pages=87–88 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vM02DwAAQBAJ}}</ref><ref>{{Citation | last1=Mackey | first1=George Whitelaw | author1-link=George Mackey | title=Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics | publisher=[[Dover Publications]] | location=New York | series=Dover Books on Mathematics | isbn=978-0-486-43517-6 | year=1963}}</ref><ref>{{Citation | last1=Emch | first1=Gerard G. | title=Algebraic methods in statistical mechanics and quantum field theory | publisher=[[Wiley-Interscience]] | isbn=978-0-471-23900-0 | year=1972}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |title=Not all self-adjoint operators are observables? |url=https://physics.stackexchange.com/questions/373357/not-all-self-adjoint-operators-are-observables |website=Physics Stack Exchange |access-date=11 February 2022}}</ref> Also, not all physical observables are associated with non-trivial self-adjoint operators. For example, in quantum theory, mass appears as a parameter in the Hamiltonian, not as a non-trivial operator.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Isham |first1=Christopher |title=Lectures On Quantum Theory: Mathematical And Structural Foundations |date=1995 |publisher=World Scientific |isbn=191129802X |pages=87–88 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vM02DwAAQBAJ}}</ref>


In the case of transformation laws in quantum mechanics, the requisite automorphisms are [[unitary operator|unitary]] (or [[antiunitary]]) linear transformations of the Hilbert space ''V''. Under [[Galilean relativity]] or [[special relativity]], the mathematics of frames of reference is particularly simple, considerably restricting the set of physically meaningful observables.
In the case of transformation laws in quantum mechanics, the requisite automorphisms are [[unitary operator|unitary]] (or [[antiunitary]]) [[linear transformation]]s of the Hilbert space ''V''. Under [[Galilean relativity]] or [[special relativity]], the mathematics of frames of reference is particularly simple, considerably restricting the set of physically meaningful observables.


In quantum mechanics, measurement of observables exhibits some seemingly unintuitive properties. Specifically, if a system is in a state described by a vector in a [[Hilbert space]], the measurement process affects the state in a non-deterministic but statistically predictable way. In particular, after a measurement is applied, the state description by a single vector may be destroyed, being replaced by a [[statistical ensemble]]. The [[reversible process (thermodynamics)|irreversible]] nature of measurement operations in quantum physics is sometimes referred to as the [[measurement problem]] and is described mathematically by [[quantum operation]]s. By the structure of quantum operations, this description is mathematically equivalent to that offered by [[relative state interpretation]] where the original system is regarded as a subsystem of a larger system and the state of the original system is given by the [[partial trace]] of the state of the larger system.
In quantum mechanics, measurement of observables exhibits some seemingly unintuitive properties. Specifically, if a system is in a state described by a vector in a [[Hilbert space]], the measurement process affects the state in a non-deterministic but statistically predictable way. In particular, after a measurement is applied, the state description by a single vector may be destroyed, being replaced by a [[statistical ensemble]]. The [[reversible process (thermodynamics)|irreversible]] nature of measurement operations in quantum physics is sometimes referred to as the [[measurement problem]] and is described mathematically by [[quantum operation]]s. By the structure of quantum operations, this description is mathematically equivalent to that offered by the [[Many-worlds interpretation|relative state interpretation]] where the original system is regarded as a subsystem of a larger system and the state of the original system is given by the [[partial trace]] of the state of the larger system.


In quantum mechanics, dynamical variables <math>A</math> such as position, translational (linear) [[momentum]], [[angular momentum operator|orbital angular momentum]], [[spin (physics)|spin]], and [[total angular momentum]] are each associated with a [[Hermitian operator]] <math>\hat{A}</math> that acts on the [[quantum state|state]] of the quantum system. The [[eigenvalues]] of operator <math>\hat{A}</math> correspond to the possible values that the dynamical variable can be observed as having. For example, suppose <math>|\psi_{a}\rangle</math> is an eigenket ([[eigenvector]]) of the observable <math>\mathbf{A}</math>, with eigenvalue <math>a</math>, and exists in a d-dimensional [[Hilbert space]]. Then
In quantum mechanics, dynamical variables <math>A</math> such as position, translational (linear) [[momentum]], [[angular momentum operator|orbital angular momentum]], [[Spin (physics)|spin]], and [[total angular momentum]] are each associated with a [[self-adjoint operator]] <math>\hat{A}</math> that acts on the [[quantum state|state]] of the quantum system. The [[eigenvalues]] of operator <math>\hat{A}</math> correspond to the possible values that the dynamical variable can be observed as having. For example, suppose <math>|\psi_{a}\rangle</math> is an eigenket ([[eigenvector]]) of the observable <math>\hat{A}</math>, with eigenvalue <math>a</math>, and exists in a [[Hilbert space]]. Then
<math display="block">\hat{A}|\psi_a\rangle = a|\psi_a\rangle.</math>


This eigenket equation says that if a [[measurement]] of the observable <math>\hat{A}</math> is made while the system of interest is in the state <math>|\psi_a\rangle</math>, then the observed value of that particular measurement must return the eigenvalue <math>a</math> with certainty. However, if the system of interest is in the general state <math>|\phi\rangle \in \mathcal{H}</math> (and <math>|\phi\rangle</math> and <math>|\psi_a\rangle</math> are [[unit vector]]s, and the [[eigenspace]] of <math>a</math> is one-dimensional), then the eigenvalue <math>a</math> is returned with probability <math>|\langle \psi_a|\phi\rangle|^2</math>, by the [[Born rule]].
:<math>\mathbf{A}|\psi_a\rangle = a|\psi_a\rangle.</math>


=== Compatible and incompatible observables in quantum mechanics ===
This eigenket equation says that if a [[measurement]] of the observable <math>\mathbf{A}</math> is made while the system of interest is in the state <math>|\psi_a\rangle</math>, then the observed value of that particular measurement must return the eigenvalue <math>a</math> with certainty. However, if the system of interest is in the general state <math>|\phi\rangle \in \mathcal{H}</math>, then the eigenvalue <math>a</math> is returned with probability <math>|\langle \psi_a|\phi\rangle|^2</math>, by the [[Born rule]].
A crucial difference between classical quantities and quantum mechanical observables is that some pairs of quantum observables may not be simultaneously measurable, a property referred to as [[complementarity (physics)|complementarity]]. This is mathematically expressed by non-[[commutativity]] of their corresponding operators, to the effect that the [[commutator (physics)|commutator]]
<math display="block">\left[\hat{A}, \hat{B}\right] := \hat{A}\hat{B} - \hat{B}\hat{A} \neq \hat{0}.</math>


This inequality expresses a dependence of measurement results on the order in which measurements of observables <math>\hat{A}</math> and <math>\hat{B}</math> are performed. A measurement of <math>\hat{A}</math> alters the quantum state in a way that is incompatible with the subsequent measurement of <math>\hat{B}</math> and vice versa.
{{citation needed span|The above definition is somewhat dependent upon our convention of choosing real numbers to represent real [[physical quantities]]. Indeed, just because dynamical variables are "real" and not "unreal" in the metaphysical sense does not mean that they must correspond to real numbers in the mathematical sense.|date=September 2018}}


Observables corresponding to commuting operators are called ''compatible observables''. For example, momentum along say the <math>x</math> and <math>y</math> axis are compatible. Observables corresponding to non-commuting operators are called ''incompatible observables'' or ''complementary variables''. For example, the position and momentum along the same axis are incompatible.<ref name=messiah>{{Cite book|last=Messiah|first=Albert|authorlink = Albert Messiah|title=Quantum Mechanics|date=1966|publisher=North Holland, John Wiley & Sons|isbn=0486409244|language=en}}</ref>{{rp|155}}
To be more precise, the dynamical variable/observable is a [[self-adjoint operator]] in a Hilbert space.


Incompatible observables cannot have a complete set of common [[eigenfunction]]s. Note that there can be some simultaneous eigenvectors of <math>\hat{A}</math> and <math>\hat{B}</math>, but not enough in number to constitute a complete [[basis (vector space)|basis]].<ref>{{Cite book|last=Griffiths|first=David J.|authorlink = David J. Griffiths|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0h-nDAAAQBAJ|title=Introduction to Quantum Mechanics|date=2017|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-107-17986-8|pages=111|language=en}}</ref>{{sfn | Cohen-Tannoudji | Diu | Laloë | 2019 | p=232}}
=== Operators on finite and infinite dimensional Hilbert spaces ===
If the Hilbert space is finite-dimension, it can be represented by a Hermitian matrix if the space is finite-dimensional. In an infinite-dimensional Hilbert space, the observable is represented by a [[symmetric operator]], which [[partial function|may not be defined everywhere]]. The reason for such a change is that in an infinite-dimensional Hilbert space, the observable operator can become [[unbounded operator|unbounded]], which means that it no longer has a largest eigenvalue. This is not the case in a finite-dimensional Hilbert space: an operator can have no more eigenvalues than the [[dimension (mathematics)|dimension]] of the state it acts upon, and by the [[well-ordering property]], any finite set of real numbers has a largest element. For example, the position of a point particle moving along a line can take any real number as its value, and the set of [[real numbers]] is [[uncountable set|uncountably infinite]]. Since the eigenvalue of an observable represents a possible physical quantity that its corresponding dynamical variable can take, we must conclude that there is no largest eigenvalue for the position observable in this uncountably infinite-dimensional Hilbert space.

== Incompatibility of observables in quantum mechanics ==
A crucial difference between classical quantities and quantum mechanical observables is that the latter may not be simultaneously measurable, a property referred to as [[complementarity (physics)|complementarity]]. This is mathematically expressed by non-[[commutativity]] of the corresponding operators, to the effect that the [[commutator (phyiscs)|commutator]]

:<math>\left[\mathbf{A}, \mathbf{B}\right] := \mathbf{A}\mathbf{B} - \mathbf{B}\mathbf{A} \neq \mathbf{0}.</math>

This inequality expresses a dependence of measurement results on the order in which measurements of observables <math>\scriptstyle \mathbf{A}</math> and <math>\scriptstyle \mathbf{B}</math> are performed. Observables corresponding to non-commutative operators are called ''incompatible''.{{citation needed|reason=Is non-commutation|date=September 2018}}


==See also==
==See also==
Line 41: Line 37:
* [[Observable universe]]
* [[Observable universe]]
* [[Observer (quantum physics)]]
* [[Observer (quantum physics)]]
* [[Operator (physics)#Table of QM operators|Table of QM operators]]
* [[Unobservable]]

==References==
{{reflist}}


== Further reading ==
== Further reading ==
{{refbegin}}
*{{cite book|last1=Auyang|first1=Sunny Y.|title=How is quantum field theory possible?|date=1995|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=New York, N.Y.|isbn=978-0195093452}}
*{{cite book|last1=Auyang|first1=Sunny Y.|title=How is quantum field theory possible?|date=1995|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=New York, N.Y.|isbn=978-0195093452}}
*{{cite book | last=Cohen-Tannoudji | first=Claude | last2=Diu | first2=Bernard | last3=Laloë | first3=Franck | title=Quantum Mechanics, Volume 1 | publisher=John Wiley & Sons | publication-place=Weinheim | date=2019 | isbn=978-3-527-34553-3}}
*{{cite book|last1=Ballentine|first1=Leslie E.|title=Quantum mechanics : a modern development|date=2014|publisher=World Scientific Publishing Co |location=|isbn= 9789814578608|edition=Repr.}}
*{{cite thesis |last=de la Madrid Modino |first= R. |date=2001 |title= Quantum mechanics in rigged Hilbert space language|url=https://scholar.google.com/scholar?oi=bibs&cluster=2442809273695897641&btnI=1&hl=en |degree= PhD |publisher= Universidad de Valladolid}}
* {{cite book | last=Teschl | first=G. | title=Mathematical Methods in Quantum Mechanics | publisher=American Mathematical Soc. | publication-place=Providence (R.I) | date=2014 | isbn=978-1-4704-1704-8}}
*{{cite book|last1=von Neumann|first1=John|title=Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics|date=1996|publisher=Princeton Univ. Press|location=Princeton, N.J.|isbn=978-0691028934|edition=12. print., 1. paperback print.|others=Translated by Robert T. Beyer}}
*{{cite book|last1=von Neumann|first1=John|title=Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics|date=1996|publisher=Princeton Univ. Press|location=Princeton, N.J.|isbn=978-0691028934|edition=12. print., 1. paperback print.|others=Translated by Robert T. Beyer}}
*{{cite book|last1=Varadarajan|first1=V.S.|title=Geometry of quantum theory|date=2007|publisher=Springer|location=New York|isbn=9780387493862|edition=2nd}}
*{{cite book|last1=Varadarajan|first1=V.S.|title=Geometry of quantum theory|date=2007|publisher=Springer|location=New York|isbn=9780387493862|edition=2nd}}
*{{cite book|first1=Hermann |last1=Weyl |chapter=Appendix C: Quantum physics and causality |title=Philosophy of mathematics and natural science|date=2009|publisher=Princeton University Press|location=Princeton, N.J.|isbn=9780691141206|pages=253&ndash;265|others=Revised and augmented English edition based on a translation by Olaf Helmer}}
*{{cite book|first1=Hermann |last1=Weyl |authorlink = Hermann Weyl|chapter=Appendix C: Quantum physics and causality |title=Philosophy of mathematics and natural science|date=2009|publisher=Princeton University Press|location=Princeton, N.J.|isbn=9780691141206|pages=253&ndash;265|others=Revised and augmented English edition based on a translation by Olaf Helmer}}
*{{cite book |last1=Moretti |first1=Valter |title=Spectral Theory and Quantum Mechanics: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Theories, Symmetries and Introduction to the Algebraic Formulation |date=2017 |edition=2 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3319707068 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RNBJDwAAQBAJ}}
{{refend}}
*{{cite book |last1=Moretti |first1=Valter |title=Fundamental Mathematical Structures of Quantum Theory: Spectral Theory, Foundational Issues, Symmetries, Algebraic Formulation |date=2019 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3030183462 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2UeeDwAAQBAJ}}

{{Quantum mechanics topics}}


[[Category:Quantum mechanics]]
[[Category:Quantum mechanics]]

Latest revision as of 23:34, 27 August 2024

In physics, an observable is a physical property or physical quantity that can be measured. In classical mechanics, an observable is a real-valued "function" on the set of all possible system states, e.g., position and momentum. In quantum mechanics, an observable is an operator, or gauge, where the property of the quantum state can be determined by some sequence of operations. For example, these operations might involve submitting the system to various electromagnetic fields and eventually reading a value.

Physically meaningful observables must also satisfy transformation laws that relate observations performed by different observers in different frames of reference. These transformation laws are automorphisms of the state space, that is bijective transformations that preserve certain mathematical properties of the space in question.

Quantum mechanics

[edit]

In quantum mechanics, observables manifest as self-adjoint operators on a separable complex Hilbert space representing the quantum state space.[1] Observables assign values to outcomes of particular measurements, corresponding to the eigenvalue of the operator. If these outcomes represent physically allowable states (i.e. those that belong to the Hilbert space) the eigenvalues are real; however, the converse is not necessarily true.[2][3][4] As a consequence, only certain measurements can determine the value of an observable for some state of a quantum system. In classical mechanics, any measurement can be made to determine the value of an observable.

The relation between the state of a quantum system and the value of an observable requires some linear algebra for its description. In the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics, up to a phase constant, pure states are given by non-zero vectors in a Hilbert space V. Two vectors v and w are considered to specify the same state if and only if for some non-zero . Observables are given by self-adjoint operators on V. Not every self-adjoint operator corresponds to a physically meaningful observable.[5][6][7][8] Also, not all physical observables are associated with non-trivial self-adjoint operators. For example, in quantum theory, mass appears as a parameter in the Hamiltonian, not as a non-trivial operator.[9]

In the case of transformation laws in quantum mechanics, the requisite automorphisms are unitary (or antiunitary) linear transformations of the Hilbert space V. Under Galilean relativity or special relativity, the mathematics of frames of reference is particularly simple, considerably restricting the set of physically meaningful observables.

In quantum mechanics, measurement of observables exhibits some seemingly unintuitive properties. Specifically, if a system is in a state described by a vector in a Hilbert space, the measurement process affects the state in a non-deterministic but statistically predictable way. In particular, after a measurement is applied, the state description by a single vector may be destroyed, being replaced by a statistical ensemble. The irreversible nature of measurement operations in quantum physics is sometimes referred to as the measurement problem and is described mathematically by quantum operations. By the structure of quantum operations, this description is mathematically equivalent to that offered by the relative state interpretation where the original system is regarded as a subsystem of a larger system and the state of the original system is given by the partial trace of the state of the larger system.

In quantum mechanics, dynamical variables such as position, translational (linear) momentum, orbital angular momentum, spin, and total angular momentum are each associated with a self-adjoint operator that acts on the state of the quantum system. The eigenvalues of operator correspond to the possible values that the dynamical variable can be observed as having. For example, suppose is an eigenket (eigenvector) of the observable , with eigenvalue , and exists in a Hilbert space. Then

This eigenket equation says that if a measurement of the observable is made while the system of interest is in the state , then the observed value of that particular measurement must return the eigenvalue with certainty. However, if the system of interest is in the general state (and and are unit vectors, and the eigenspace of is one-dimensional), then the eigenvalue is returned with probability , by the Born rule.

Compatible and incompatible observables in quantum mechanics

[edit]

A crucial difference between classical quantities and quantum mechanical observables is that some pairs of quantum observables may not be simultaneously measurable, a property referred to as complementarity. This is mathematically expressed by non-commutativity of their corresponding operators, to the effect that the commutator

This inequality expresses a dependence of measurement results on the order in which measurements of observables and are performed. A measurement of alters the quantum state in a way that is incompatible with the subsequent measurement of and vice versa.

Observables corresponding to commuting operators are called compatible observables. For example, momentum along say the and axis are compatible. Observables corresponding to non-commuting operators are called incompatible observables or complementary variables. For example, the position and momentum along the same axis are incompatible.[10]: 155 

Incompatible observables cannot have a complete set of common eigenfunctions. Note that there can be some simultaneous eigenvectors of and , but not enough in number to constitute a complete basis.[11][12]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Teschl 2014, pp. 65–66.
  2. ^ See page 20 of Lecture notes 1 by Robert Littlejohn Archived 2023-08-29 at the Wayback Machine for a mathematical discussion using the momentum operator as specific example.
  3. ^ de la Madrid Modino 2001, pp. 95–97.
  4. ^ Ballentine, Leslie (2015). Quantum Mechanics: A Modern Development (2 ed.). World Scientific. p. 49. ISBN 978-9814578578.
  5. ^ Isham, Christopher (1995). Lectures On Quantum Theory: Mathematical And Structural Foundations. World Scientific. pp. 87–88. ISBN 191129802X.
  6. ^ Mackey, George Whitelaw (1963), Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Dover Books on Mathematics, New York: Dover Publications, ISBN 978-0-486-43517-6
  7. ^ Emch, Gerard G. (1972), Algebraic methods in statistical mechanics and quantum field theory, Wiley-Interscience, ISBN 978-0-471-23900-0
  8. ^ "Not all self-adjoint operators are observables?". Physics Stack Exchange. Retrieved 11 February 2022.
  9. ^ Isham, Christopher (1995). Lectures On Quantum Theory: Mathematical And Structural Foundations. World Scientific. pp. 87–88. ISBN 191129802X.
  10. ^ Messiah, Albert (1966). Quantum Mechanics. North Holland, John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 0486409244.
  11. ^ Griffiths, David J. (2017). Introduction to Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press. p. 111. ISBN 978-1-107-17986-8.
  12. ^ Cohen-Tannoudji, Diu & Laloë 2019, p. 232.

Further reading

[edit]