Jump to content

Lazy argument: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
titles in italics
Monkbot (talk | contribs)
m Task 20: replace {lang-??} templates with {langx|??} ‹See Tfd› (Replaced 1);
 
(10 intermediate revisions by 6 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
The '''Lazy Argument''' or '''Idle Argument''' ({{lang-grc|ἀργὸς λόγος}}) is either an argument for [[fatalism]] or an attempt at undermining the philosophical doctrine of [[fatalism]]. Its basic form is that of a complex constructive [[dilemma]].<ref>[[Susanne Bobzien|S. Bobzien]], [http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0199247676.001.0001''Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy'', ch.5]</ref><ref>T. Brennan, [http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0199256268.001.0001/acprof-9780199256266''The Stoic Life'', ch.16]</ref>
The '''lazy argument''' or '''idle argument''' ({{langx|grc|ἀργὸς λόγος}}) is an attempt to undermine the philosophical doctrine of [[fatalism]] by demonstrating that, if everything that happens is determined by fate, it is futile to take any kind of action.<ref>{{cite book |last=Bobzien |first=Susanne |authorlink=Susanne Bobzien |title=Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy |chapter=Fate, Action, and Motivation: The Idle Argument |date=2001 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=0-19-924767-6 |doi=10.1093/0199247676.003.0006 |page=180}}</ref> Its basic form is that of a complex constructive [[dilemma]].<ref>{{harvnb|Bobzien|2001|page=185}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Brennan |first=Tad |date=2005 |title=The Stoic Life: Emotions, Duties, and Fate |chapter=The Lazy Argument |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-925626-6 |doi=10.1093/0199256268.003.0016}}</ref>


==History==
==History==
The general idea behind the Lazy Argument can already be found in [[Aristotle]]'s ''[[De Interpretatione]]'', chapter 9. The earliest surviving text that provides the argument in full is [[Cicero]]'s ''On Fate'' 28-9. It is also presented in [[Origen]], ''Against Celsus'' (''Cels'' II 20) and mentioned in Pseudo-[[Plutarch]], ''On Fate'' 574e. [[Seneca the Younger|Seneca]] ''Natural Questions'' II 38.3 provides evidence for a similar argument.<ref>[[Susanne Bobzien|S. Bobzien]], [http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0199247676.001.0001''Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy'', ch.5]</ref>
The general idea behind the lazy argument can already be found in [[Aristotle]]'s ''[[De Interpretatione]]'', chapter 9. The earliest surviving text that provides the argument in full is [[Cicero]]'s ''[[De fato|On Fate]]'' 28–9. It is also presented in [[Origen]], ''[[Against Celsus]]'' II.20, and mentioned in [[Pseudo-Plutarch]], ''On Fate'' 574e. [[Seneca the Younger|Seneca]]'s ''[[Natural Questions]]'' II.38.3 provides evidence for a similar argument.<ref>{{harvnb|Bobzien|2001|pages=180–1}}</ref>


==Argument==
==Argument==
Here is the argument, as found in Origen:
The argument is stated by Origen as follows:
<blockquote>If it is fated that you will recover from this illness, then, regardless of whether you consult a doctor or you do not consult [a doctor] you will recover. But also: if it is fated that you won't recover from this illness, then, regardless of whether you consult a doctor or you do not consult [a doctor] you won't recover. But either it is fated that you will recover from this illness or it is fated that you won't recover. Therefore it is futile to consult a doctor.<ref>transl. after [[Susanne Bobzien|Bobzien]], [http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0199247676.001.0001''Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy'', p.182.]</ref></blockquote> The argument has force only for those who accept that what happens to people is determined by fate.
<blockquote>If it is fated that you will recover from this illness, then, regardless of whether you consult a doctor or you do not consult [a doctor] you will recover. But also: if it is fated that you won't recover from this illness, then, regardless of whether you consult a doctor or you do not consult [a doctor] you won't recover. But either it is fated that you will recover from this illness or it is fated that you won't recover. Therefore it is futile to consult a doctor.<ref>As quoted in {{harvnb|Bobzien|2001|page=182}}</ref></blockquote> The argument has force only for those who accept that what happens to people is determined by fate.
==Refutation==
==Refutation==
The [[Stoicism|Stoic]] philosopher [[Chrysippus]]' refutation of the lazy argument is given in [[Cicero]]'s ''On Fate'' (''De fato'') and in [[Eusebius of Caesarea|Eusebius]]' ''Preparation for the Gospel'' (''[[Praeparatio evangelica]]''). The argument, as presented by Cicero, calls upon the idea that an event is 'co-fated' with other events. As in the example above, if it is fated for someone to recover from an illness, then the necessary steps towards recovery are also fated, and can be said to be co-fated along with this final event; so whilst recovery will occur, the steps towards recovery must also occur and evidently will occur if one is truly fated to recover.
The [[Stoicism|Stoic]] philosopher [[Chrysippus]]' refutation of the lazy argument is given in Cicero's ''On Fate'' and in [[Eusebius of Caesarea|Eusebius]]' ''[[Praeparatio evangelica|Preparation for the Gospel]]''. The argument, as presented by Cicero, calls upon the idea that an event is "co-fated" with other events. As in the example above, if it is fated for someone to recover from an illness, then the necessary steps towards recovery are also fated, and can be said to be co-fated along with this final event; so whilst recovery will occur, the steps towards recovery must also occur and evidently will occur if one is truly fated to recover.


The same argument is presented by Eusebius as follows:
The lazy argument only seems plausible if one fails to consider the necessity of the occurrence of intermediate events related to a final, fated event. Yet this is unsound and thus the lazy argument must be rejected. Consider this hypothetical argument; if at a given time it is fated that I will pass an exam, the lazy argument would suggest that it is as justifiable for me to not study as it would be to study, because I will pass the exam regardless of any action I may take. This is due to the fact that, after all, it is fated for me to pass the exam. However, whilst my passing of the exam is in fact fated, it is also dependent on my completion of a series of events beforehand (which are also fated) and thus, if I did not complete these intermediate events, then I would not pass my test. The following passage in Eusebius, reporting Chrysippus, illustrates this:
<blockquote>The non-destruction of one's coat, he says, is not fated simply, but co-fated with its being taken care of, and someone's being saved from his enemies is co-fated with his fleeing those enemies; and having children is co-fated with being willing to lie with a woman. ... For many things cannot occur without our being willing and indeed contributing a most strenuous eagerness and zeal for these things, since, he says, it was fated for these things to occur in conjunction with this personal effort. ... But it will be in our power, he says, with what is in our power being included in fate.<ref>[[Diogenianus]] in [[Eusebius of Caesarea|Eusebius]], ''[[Praeparatio evangelica]]'', vi. 8, quoted in {{Harvnb|Inwood|Gerson|1997|p=190}}</ref></blockquote>
<blockquote>The non-destruction of one's coat, he [Chrysippus] says, is not fated simply, but co-fated with its being taken care of, and someone's being saved from his enemies is co-fated with his fleeing those enemies; and having children is co-fated with being willing to lie with a woman. ... For many things cannot occur without our being willing and indeed contributing a most strenuous eagerness and zeal for these things, since, he says, it was fated for these things to occur in conjunction with this personal effort. ... But it will be in our power, he says, with what is in our power being included in fate.<ref>''Preparation for the Gospel'' 6.8. Quoted in {{cite book |editor-last1=Inwood |editor-first1=Brad |editor-last2=Gerson |editor-first2=L. P. |date=1997 |title=Hellenistic Philosophy |edition=2nd |url=https://archive.org/details/hellenisticphilo0000unse_t2t5/page/190/mode/2up?view=theater |page=190 |publisher=Hackett Publishing Company |isbn=0-87220-378-6}}</ref></blockquote>


The lazy argument has also been attacked by [[G. W. Leibniz]], who referred to it as '' la raison paresseuse'' ('the lazy reason'). In his 1710 work ''[[Théodicée|Theodicy]]'', Leibniz writes:
==Notes==
{{reflist}}


<blockquote>Men have been perplexed in well-nigh every age by a sophism which the ancients called the 'Lazy Reason', because it tended towards doing nothing, or at least towards being careful for nothing and only following inclination for the pleasure of the moment. For, they said, if the future is necessary, that which must happen will happen, whatever I may do ... But it is taking an unfair advantage of this alleged necessity of fate to employ it in excuse for our vices and our libertinism ... It is untrue that the event happens whatever one may do: it will happen because one does what leads thereto; and if the event is written beforehand, the cause that will make it happen is written also. Thus the connexion of effects and causes, so far from establishing the doctrine of a necessity detrimental to conduct, serves to overthrow it.<ref>{{cite book |last=Leibniz |first=G. W. |date=1710 |translator=E. M. Huggard |title=Theodicy |chapter=Preface |url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/17147/17147-h/17147-h.htm#page49 |via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref></blockquote>
==Sources==

* [http://lexitechnia.frath.net/2010/01/the-lazy-argument/ The Lazy Argument]
==References==
* [http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0199247676.001.0001 S.Bobzien, ''Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy''] (Oxford 1998), ch.5, 'The Idle Argument'.
{{reflist}}


{{DEFAULTSORT:Lazy Argument}}
{{DEFAULTSORT:Lazy Argument}}
[[Category:Philosophical arguments]]
[[Category:Philosophical arguments]]
[[Category:Determinism]]
[[Category:Stoicism]]

Latest revision as of 21:42, 28 October 2024

The lazy argument or idle argument (Ancient Greek: ἀργὸς λόγος) is an attempt to undermine the philosophical doctrine of fatalism by demonstrating that, if everything that happens is determined by fate, it is futile to take any kind of action.[1] Its basic form is that of a complex constructive dilemma.[2][3]

History

[edit]

The general idea behind the lazy argument can already be found in Aristotle's De Interpretatione, chapter 9. The earliest surviving text that provides the argument in full is Cicero's On Fate 28–9. It is also presented in Origen, Against Celsus II.20, and mentioned in Pseudo-Plutarch, On Fate 574e. Seneca's Natural Questions II.38.3 provides evidence for a similar argument.[4]

Argument

[edit]

The argument is stated by Origen as follows:

If it is fated that you will recover from this illness, then, regardless of whether you consult a doctor or you do not consult [a doctor] you will recover. But also: if it is fated that you won't recover from this illness, then, regardless of whether you consult a doctor or you do not consult [a doctor] you won't recover. But either it is fated that you will recover from this illness or it is fated that you won't recover. Therefore it is futile to consult a doctor.[5]

The argument has force only for those who accept that what happens to people is determined by fate.

Refutation

[edit]

The Stoic philosopher Chrysippus' refutation of the lazy argument is given in Cicero's On Fate and in Eusebius' Preparation for the Gospel. The argument, as presented by Cicero, calls upon the idea that an event is "co-fated" with other events. As in the example above, if it is fated for someone to recover from an illness, then the necessary steps towards recovery are also fated, and can be said to be co-fated along with this final event; so whilst recovery will occur, the steps towards recovery must also occur and evidently will occur if one is truly fated to recover.

The same argument is presented by Eusebius as follows:

The non-destruction of one's coat, he [Chrysippus] says, is not fated simply, but co-fated with its being taken care of, and someone's being saved from his enemies is co-fated with his fleeing those enemies; and having children is co-fated with being willing to lie with a woman. ... For many things cannot occur without our being willing and indeed contributing a most strenuous eagerness and zeal for these things, since, he says, it was fated for these things to occur in conjunction with this personal effort. ... But it will be in our power, he says, with what is in our power being included in fate.[6]

The lazy argument has also been attacked by G. W. Leibniz, who referred to it as la raison paresseuse ('the lazy reason'). In his 1710 work Theodicy, Leibniz writes:

Men have been perplexed in well-nigh every age by a sophism which the ancients called the 'Lazy Reason', because it tended towards doing nothing, or at least towards being careful for nothing and only following inclination for the pleasure of the moment. For, they said, if the future is necessary, that which must happen will happen, whatever I may do ... But it is taking an unfair advantage of this alleged necessity of fate to employ it in excuse for our vices and our libertinism ... It is untrue that the event happens whatever one may do: it will happen because one does what leads thereto; and if the event is written beforehand, the cause that will make it happen is written also. Thus the connexion of effects and causes, so far from establishing the doctrine of a necessity detrimental to conduct, serves to overthrow it.[7]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Bobzien, Susanne (2001). "Fate, Action, and Motivation: The Idle Argument". Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 180. doi:10.1093/0199247676.003.0006. ISBN 0-19-924767-6.
  2. ^ Bobzien 2001, p. 185
  3. ^ Brennan, Tad (2005). "The Lazy Argument". The Stoic Life: Emotions, Duties, and Fate. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199256268.003.0016. ISBN 978-0-19-925626-6.
  4. ^ Bobzien 2001, pp. 180–1
  5. ^ As quoted in Bobzien 2001, p. 182
  6. ^ Preparation for the Gospel 6.8. Quoted in Inwood, Brad; Gerson, L. P., eds. (1997). Hellenistic Philosophy (2nd ed.). Hackett Publishing Company. p. 190. ISBN 0-87220-378-6.
  7. ^ Leibniz, G. W. (1710). "Preface". Theodicy. Translated by E. M. Huggard – via Project Gutenberg.