Organon: Difference between revisions
Jaredscribe (talk | contribs) →Constitution of the texts: Posterior analytics inductive reasoning |
|||
(30 intermediate revisions by 18 users not shown) | |||
Line 2: | Line 2: | ||
{{about|Aristotle's works on logic|a discussion of Aristotelian logic as a system|Term logic|other uses}} |
{{about|Aristotle's works on logic|a discussion of Aristotelian logic as a system|Term logic|other uses}} |
||
{{italic title}} |
{{italic title}} |
||
[[file:Aristotele, organon, XIII secolo (bml, pluteo 11 sin 1) 01.jpg|thumb|{{PAGENAME}}]] |
|||
[[File:Aristotle_Altemps_Inv8575.jpg|thumb|Roman copy in marble of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by Lysippos, c. 330 BC, with modern alabaster mantle]] |
[[File:Aristotle_Altemps_Inv8575.jpg|thumb|Roman copy in marble of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by [[Lysippos]], c. 330 BC, with modern alabaster mantle]] |
||
The '''''Organon''''' ({{lang-grc|Ὄργανον}}, meaning "instrument, tool, organ") is the standard collection of [[Aristotle]]'s six works on [[logic]]. The name ''Organon'' was given by Aristotle's followers, the [[Peripatetic school|Peripatetic]]s. |
|||
The '''''Organon''''' ({{langx|grc|Ὄργανον}}, meaning "instrument, tool, organ") is the standard collection of [[Aristotle]]'s six works on [[logic|logical]] analysis and [[dialectic]]. The name ''Organon'' was given by Aristotle's followers, the [[Peripatetic school|Peripatetics]], who maintained against the Stoics that Logic was "an instrument" of Philosophy.<ref name=":0">{{Cite book |chapter=[[:s:Organon (Owen)/Introduction|Introduction]] |title=[[:s:Organon (Owen)|The Organon, Or Logical Treatises, of Aristotle. With the Introduction of Porphyry]] |volume=1 |last1=Owen |first1=Octavius Freire |author-link=Octavius Freire Owen |year=1853 |publisher=H.G. Bohn |others=[[Aristotle]] }}</ref> |
|||
Aristotle never uses the title ''Organon'' to refer to his logical works. The book, according to [[Jules Barthélemy-Saint-Hilaire|M. Barthélemy St. Hilaire]], was not called "Organon" before the 15th century, and the treatises were collected into one volume, as is supposed, about the time of [[Andronicus of Rhodes]]; and it was translated into Latin by [[Boethius]] about the 6th century.<ref name=":0" /> |
|||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
{{Corpus Aristotelicum table |logic |key=omit}} |
{{Corpus Aristotelicum table |logic |key=omit}} |
||
{{Br}} |
|||
== Constitution of the texts == |
== Constitution of the texts == |
||
Line 12: | Line 16: | ||
The order of the works is not chronological (which is now hard to determine) but was deliberately chosen by [[Theophrastus]] to constitute a well-structured system. Indeed, parts of them seem to be a scheme of a lecture on logic. The arrangement of the works was made by [[Andronicus of Rhodes]] around 40 BC.{{r|Oxford}} |
The order of the works is not chronological (which is now hard to determine) but was deliberately chosen by [[Theophrastus]] to constitute a well-structured system. Indeed, parts of them seem to be a scheme of a lecture on logic. The arrangement of the works was made by [[Andronicus of Rhodes]] around 40 BC.{{r|Oxford}} |
||
[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'']] has some points of overlap with the works making up the ''Organon'' but is not traditionally considered part of it; additionally there are works on logic attributed, with varying degrees of plausibility, to Aristotle that were not known to the Peripatetics.<ref name=SEP_AristotleLogic>{{cite web |title= |
[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'']] has some points of overlap with the works making up the ''Organon'' but is not traditionally considered part of it; additionally, there are works on logic attributed, with varying degrees of plausibility, to Aristotle that were not known to the Peripatetics.<ref name=SEP_AristotleLogic>{{cite web |title= Aristotle's Logic, < Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy>|date= 18 March 2000|url= https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/aristotle-logic| editor1= Edward N. Zalta |access-date =2020-12-19 }}</ref> |
||
# The ''[[Categories (Aristotle)|Categories]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|Categoriae}}) introduces Aristotle's 10-fold classification of that which exists: [[Substance theory|substance]], quantity, quality, relation, place, time, situation, condition, action, and passion. |
# The ''[[Categories (Aristotle)|Categories]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|Categoriae}}) introduces Aristotle's 10-fold classification of that which exists: [[Substance theory|substance]], quantity, quality, relation, place, time, situation, condition, action, and passion. |
||
# ''[[De Interpretatione|On Interpretation]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|De Interpretatione}}) introduces Aristotle's conception of [[proposition]] and [[judgment]], and the various relations between affirmative, negative, universal, and particular propositions. Aristotle discusses the [[square of opposition]] or square of [[Apuleius]] in Chapter 7 and its appendix Chapter 8. Chapter 9 deals with the [[problem of future contingents]]. |
# ''[[De Interpretatione|On Interpretation]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|De Interpretatione}}) introduces Aristotle's conception of [[proposition]] and [[judgment|judgement]], and the various relations between affirmative, negative, universal, and particular propositions. Aristotle discusses the [[square of opposition]] or square of [[Apuleius]] in Chapter 7 and its appendix, Chapter 8. Chapter 9 deals with the [[problem of future contingents]]. |
||
# The ''[[Prior Analytics]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|Analytica Priora}}) introduces his [[syllogism|syllogistic]] method (see [[term logic]]), argues for its correctness, and discusses inductive inference. |
# The ''[[Prior Analytics]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|Analytica Priora}}) introduces his [[syllogism|syllogistic]] method (see [[term logic]]), argues for its correctness, and discusses inductive inference. |
||
# The ''[[Posterior Analytics]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|Analytica Posteriora}}) deals with [[definition]], [[Demonstration (teaching)|demonstration]], [[inductive reasoning]], and [[scientific knowledge]]. |
# The ''[[Posterior Analytics]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|Analytica Posteriora}}) deals with [[definition]], [[Demonstration (teaching)|demonstration]], [[inductive reasoning]], and [[scientific knowledge]]. |
||
# The ''[[Topics (Aristotle)|Topics]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|Topica}}) treats issues in constructing valid arguments, and inference that is probable, rather than certain. It is in this treatise that Aristotle mentions the [[Predicables]], later discussed by [[Porphyry (philosopher)|Porphyry]] and the scholastic logicians. |
# The ''[[Topics (Aristotle)|Topics]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|Topica}}) treats issues in constructing valid arguments, and inference that is probable, rather than certain. It is in this treatise that Aristotle mentions the [[Predicables]], later discussed by [[Porphyry (philosopher)|Porphyry]] and the scholastic logicians. |
||
# The ''[[On Sophistical Refutations]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|De Sophisticis Elenchis}}) gives a treatment of logical fallacies, and provides a key link to Aristotle's |
# The ''[[On Sophistical Refutations]]'' (Latin: {{lang|la|De Sophisticis Elenchis}}) gives a treatment of [[Formal fallacy|logical fallacies]], and provides a key link to Aristotle's [[Treatise|tractate]] [[Rhetoric (Aristotle)|on rhetoric]]. |
||
Whereas the ''Organon'' of the Latin [[Scholasticism|Scholastic]] tradition comprises only the above six works, its independent reception in the Arabic medieval world saw appended to this list of works Aristotle's ''[[Rhetoric (Aristotle)|Rhetoric]]'' and ''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]''.<ref>See Black, Deborah L., ''Logic and Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics in medieval Arabic philosophy'', p. 1. Also [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/#AriLogWorOrg the “Organon” entry] at the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|SEP]].</ref> |
Whereas the ''Organon'' of the Latin [[Scholasticism|Scholastic]] tradition comprises only the above six works, its independent reception in the Arabic medieval world saw appended to this list of works Aristotle's ''[[Rhetoric (Aristotle)|Rhetoric]]'' and ''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]''.<ref>See Black, Deborah L., ''Logic and Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics in medieval Arabic philosophy'', p. 1. Also [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/#AriLogWorOrg the “Organon” entry] at the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|SEP]].</ref> |
||
Line 27: | Line 31: | ||
The ''Organon'' was used in the school founded by Aristotle at the [[Lyceum]], and some parts of the works seem to be a scheme of a lecture on logic. So much so that after Aristotle's death, his publishers ([[Andronicus of Rhodes]] in 50 BC, for example) collected these works. |
The ''Organon'' was used in the school founded by Aristotle at the [[Lyceum]], and some parts of the works seem to be a scheme of a lecture on logic. So much so that after Aristotle's death, his publishers ([[Andronicus of Rhodes]] in 50 BC, for example) collected these works. |
||
Following the collapse of the [[Western Roman Empire]] in the fifth century, much of Aristotle's work was lost in the Latin West. The ''Categories'' and ''On Interpretation'' are the only significant logical works that were available in the early Middle Ages. These had been translated into [[Latin]] by [[Boethius]]. The other logical works were not available in Western Christendom until [[Latin translations of the 12th century|translated into Latin in the 12th century]]. However, the original Greek texts had been preserved in the [[Greek language|Greek]]-speaking lands of the [[Eastern Roman Empire]] (aka [[Byzantium]]). In the mid-twelfth century, [[James of Venice]] translated into Latin the ''Posterior Analytics'' from Greek manuscripts found in Constantinople. |
Following the collapse of the [[Western Roman Empire]] in the fifth century, much of Aristotle's work was lost in the Latin West. The ''Categories'' and ''On Interpretation'' are the only significant logical works that were available in the early [[Middle Ages]]. These had been translated into [[Latin]] by [[Boethius]], along with Porphyry's [[Isagoge]], which was also translated into Arabic by [[Ibn al-Muqaffa']] via a Syriac intermediary. The other logical works were not available in Western Christendom until [[Latin translations of the 12th century|translated into Latin in the 12th century]]. However, the original Greek texts had been preserved in the [[Greek language|Greek]]-speaking lands of the [[Eastern Roman Empire]] (aka [[Byzantium]]). In the mid-twelfth century, [[James of Venice]] translated into Latin the ''Posterior Analytics'' from Greek manuscripts found in Constantinople. |
||
The books of Aristotle were available in the early |
The books of Aristotle were available in the early Muslim world, and after 750 AD Muslims had most of them{{Dubious|date=May 2022}}, including the ''Organon'', translated into Arabic, normally via earlier Syriac translations. They were studied by [[Islamic]] and [[Jewish]] scholars, including Rabbi [[Moses Maimonides]] (1135–1204) and the Muslim Judge [[Ibn Rushd]], known in the West as Averroes (1126–1198); both were originally from [[Córdoba, Spain]], although the former left Iberia and by 1168 lived in [[Egypt]]. |
||
All the major scholastic philosophers wrote commentaries on the ''Organon''. [[Aquinas]], [[William of Ockham|Ockham]] and [[Duns Scotus|Scotus]] wrote commentaries on ''On Interpretation''. Ockham and Scotus wrote commentaries on the ''Categories'' and ''Sophistical Refutations''. [[Grosseteste]] wrote an influential commentary on the ''Posterior Analytics''. |
All the major scholastic philosophers wrote commentaries on the ''Organon''. [[Aquinas]], [[William of Ockham|Ockham]] and [[Duns Scotus|Scotus]] wrote commentaries on ''On Interpretation''. Ockham and Scotus wrote commentaries on the ''Categories'' and ''Sophistical Refutations''. [[Grosseteste]] wrote an influential commentary on the ''Posterior Analytics''. |
||
In the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] there was a revival of interest in logic as the basis of rational enquiry, and a number of texts, most successfully the [[Port-Royal Logic]], polished Aristotelian term logic for pedagogy. During this period, while the logic certainly was based on that of Aristotle, Aristotle's writings themselves were less often the basis of study. There was a tendency in this period to regard the [[logical system]]s of the day to be complete, which in turn no doubt stifled innovation in this area. However [[Francis Bacon]] published his ''[[Novum Organum]]'' ("The New ''Organon''") as a scathing attack in [[1620 in literature|1620]].{{r|teaching}} [[Immanuel Kant]] thought that there was nothing else to invent after the work of Aristotle,<ref>Alain Badiou, Theoretical Writings, p 172</ref> and the famous logic historian [[Karl von Prantl]] claimed that any logician who said anything new about logic was "confused, stupid or perverse." These examples illustrate the force of influence which Aristotle's works on logic had. Indeed, he had already become known by the Scholastics (medieval Christian scholars) as "The Philosopher", due to the influence he had upon medieval theology and philosophy. His influence continued into the Early Modern period and Organon was the basis of school philosophy even in the beginning of 18th century.<ref>{{Cite book | publisher = Cambridge University Press| isbn = 9780521822428| last = Rutherford| first = Donald| title = The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy| year = 2006| page = 170ff}}</ref> |
In the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] there was a revival of interest in logic as the basis of [[Rational inquiry|rational enquiry]], and a number of texts, most successfully the [[Port-Royal Logic]], polished [[Aristotelianism|Aristotelian]] term logic for [[pedagogy]]. During this period, while the logic certainly was based on that of Aristotle, Aristotle's writings themselves were less often the basis of study. There was a tendency in this period to regard the [[logical system]]s of the day to be complete, which in turn no doubt stifled innovation in this area. However, [[Francis Bacon]] published his ''[[Novum Organum]]'' ("The New ''Organon''") as a scathing attack in [[1620 in literature|1620]].{{r|teaching}} [[Immanuel Kant]] thought that there was nothing else to invent after the work of Aristotle,<ref>Alain Badiou, Theoretical Writings, p 172</ref> and the famous logic historian [[Karl von Prantl]] claimed that any logician who said anything new about logic was "confused, stupid or perverse." These examples illustrate the force of influence which Aristotle's works on logic had. Indeed, he had already become known by the Scholastics (medieval Christian scholars) as "The Philosopher", due to the influence he had upon medieval theology and philosophy. His influence continued into the Early Modern period and Organon was the basis of school philosophy even in the beginning of the 18th century.<ref>{{Cite book | publisher = Cambridge University Press| isbn = 9780521822428| last = Rutherford| first = Donald| title = The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy| year = 2006| page = 170ff}}</ref> |
||
Since the logical innovations of the 19th century, particularly the formulation of modern [[predicate logic]], Aristotelian logic had for a time fallen out of favor among many [[analytic philosophy|analytic philosophers]]. |
Since the logical innovations of the 19th century, particularly the formulation of modern [[predicate logic]], Aristotelian logic had for a time fallen out of favor among many [[analytic philosophy|analytic philosophers]]. |
||
However the logic historian [[John Corcoran (logician)|John Corcoran]] and others have shown that the works of [[George Boole]] and [[Gottlob Frege]]—which laid the groundwork for modern mathematical logic—each represent a continuation and extension to Aristotle's logic and in no way contradict or displace it.<ref>[[George Boole]]. 1854/2003. The Laws of Thought, facsimile of 1854 edition, with an introduction by J. Corcoran. Buffalo: Prometheus Books (2003). Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review.24 (2004) 167–169.</ref><ref>[[John Corcoran (logician)|John Corcoran]], Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 24 (2003), pp. 261–288.</ref> |
However, the logic historian [[John Corcoran (logician)|John Corcoran]] and others have shown that the works of [[George Boole]] and [[Gottlob Frege]]—which laid the groundwork for modern mathematical logic—each represent a continuation and extension to Aristotle's logic and in no way contradict or displace it.<ref>[[George Boole]]. 1854/2003. The Laws of Thought, facsimile of 1854 edition, with an introduction by J. Corcoran. Buffalo: Prometheus Books (2003). Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review.24 (2004) 167–169.</ref><ref>[[John Corcoran (logician)|John Corcoran]], Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 24 (2003), pp. 261–288.</ref> |
||
Boole fully accepted and endorsed Aristotle's logic, and Frege included Aristotle's [[square of opposition]] at the end of his groundbreaking ''[[Begriffsschrift]]'' to show the harmony of his theory with the Aristotelian tradition.<ref>[[Jean-Yves Béziau]] “Is modern logic non-Aristotelian?”, in Vladimir Markin, Dmitry Zaitsev (eds.), ''The Logical Legacy of Nikolai Vasiliev and Modern Logic'', Cham, Springer, 2017, pp. 19-42.</ref> |
Boole fully accepted and endorsed Aristotle's logic, and Frege included Aristotle's [[square of opposition]] at the end of his groundbreaking ''[[Begriffsschrift]]'' to show the harmony of his theory with the Aristotelian tradition.<ref>[[Jean-Yves Béziau]] “Is modern logic non-Aristotelian?”, in Vladimir Markin, Dmitry Zaitsev (eds.), ''The Logical Legacy of Nikolai Vasiliev and Modern Logic'', Cham, Springer, 2017, pp. 19-42.</ref> |
||
Line 49: | Line 53: | ||
== References == |
== References == |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
{{refbegin}} |
{{refbegin}} |
||
* {{Citation |
* {{Citation |
||
| |
|translator-last1 = Edghill |
||
| |
|translator-first1 = E. M. |
||
| |
|translator-link1 = Ella Mary Edghill |
||
|year = 2007 |
|year = 2007 |
||
|title = Categories |
|title = Categories |
||
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
||
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
||
|url = |
|url = https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/categories/complete.html |
||
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
||
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20181211082849/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/categories/ |
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20181211082849/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/categories/ |
||
Line 68: | Line 71: | ||
* {{Citation |
* {{Citation |
||
| |
|translator-last1 = Edghill |
||
| |
|translator-first1 = E. M. |
||
| |
|translator-link1 = Ella Mary Edghill |
||
|year = 2007 |
|year = 2007 |
||
|title = On Interpretation |
|title = On Interpretation |
||
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
||
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
||
|url = |
|url = https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/interpretation/complete.html |
||
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
||
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20180216025655/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/interpretation/ |
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20180216025655/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/interpretation/ |
||
Line 83: | Line 86: | ||
* {{Citation |
* {{Citation |
||
| |
|translator-last1 = Jenkinson |
||
| |
|translator-first1 = A. J. |
||
|year = 2007 |
|year = 2007 |
||
|title = Prior Analytics |
|title = Prior Analytics |
||
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
||
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
||
|url = |
|url = https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/a8pra/complete.html |
||
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
||
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/ |
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20150907200852/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/a8pra/complete.html |
||
|archive-date = |
|archive-date = 2015-09-07 |
||
|url-status = dead |
|url-status = dead |
||
}}. |
}}. |
||
* {{Citation |
* {{Citation |
||
| |
|translator-last1 = Mure |
||
| |
|translator-first1 = G. R. G. |
||
| |
|translator-link1 = Geoffrey Reginald Gilchrist Mure |
||
|year = 2007 |
|year = 2007 |
||
|title = Posterior Analytics |
|title = Posterior Analytics |
||
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
||
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
||
|url = |
|url = https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/a8poa/complete.html |
||
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
||
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20181210015810/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/a8poa/ |
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20181210015810/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/a8poa/ |
||
Line 112: | Line 115: | ||
* {{Citation |
* {{Citation |
||
| |
|translator-last1 = Pickard-Cambridge |
||
| |
|translator-first1 = W. A. |
||
|year = 2007 |
|year = 2007 |
||
|title = Topics |
|title = Topics |
||
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
||
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
||
|url = |
|url = https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/a8t/complete.html |
||
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
|access-date = 2019-01-26 |
||
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/ |
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20160304202155/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/a8t/complete.html |
||
|archive-date = 2016- |
|archive-date = 2016-03-04 |
||
|url-status = dead |
|url-status = dead |
||
}}. |
}}. |
||
* {{Citation |
* {{Citation |
||
| |
|translator-last1 = Pickard-Cambridge |
||
| |
|translator-first1 = W. A. |
||
|year = 2007 |
|year = 2007 |
||
|title = On Sophistical Refutations |
|title = On Sophistical Refutations |
||
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
|publisher = eBooks @ Adelaide |
||
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
|place = The [[University of Adelaide]] |
||
|url = |
|url = https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/sophistical/complete.html |
||
|access-date = 2015-04-21 |
|access-date = 2015-04-21 |
||
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/ |
|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20150907114759/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/sophistical/complete.html |
||
|archive-date = |
|archive-date = 2015-09-07 |
||
|url-status = dead |
|url-status = dead |
||
}}. |
}}. |
||
'''Studies''' |
|||
* Bocheński, I. M., 1951. ''Ancient Formal Logic''. Amsterdam: North-Holland. |
* Bocheński, I. M., 1951. ''Ancient Formal Logic''. Amsterdam: North-Holland. |
||
*[[Jan Łukasiewicz]], 1951. ''Aristotle's Syllogistic, from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic''. Oxford: Clarendon Press. |
*[[Jan Łukasiewicz]], 1951. ''Aristotle's Syllogistic, from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic''. Oxford: Clarendon Press. |
||
Line 146: | Line 148: | ||
* Monteil, Jean-François ''La transmission d’Aristote par les Arabes à la chrétienté occidentale: une trouvaille relative au De Interpretatione'', Revista Española de Filosofia Medieval 11: 181-195 |
* Monteil, Jean-François ''La transmission d’Aristote par les Arabes à la chrétienté occidentale: une trouvaille relative au De Interpretatione'', Revista Española de Filosofia Medieval 11: 181-195 |
||
* Monteil, Jean-François ''Isidor Pollak et les deux traductions arabes différentes du De interpretatione d’Aristote'', Revue d’Études Anciennes 107: 29-46 (2005). |
* Monteil, Jean-François ''Isidor Pollak et les deux traductions arabes différentes du De interpretatione d’Aristote'', Revue d’Études Anciennes 107: 29-46 (2005). |
||
* Monteil, Jean-François ''Une exception allemande: la traduction du De Interpretatione par le Professeur Gohlke: la note 10 sur les indéterminées d’Aristote'', Revues de Études Anciennes 103: |
* Monteil, Jean-François ''Une exception allemande: la traduction du De Interpretatione par le Professeur Gohlke: la note 10 sur les indéterminées d’Aristote'', Revues de Études Anciennes 103: 409–427 (2001). |
||
* Parry and Hacker, 1991. ''Aristotelian Logic''. Albany: State University of New York Press. |
* Parry and Hacker, 1991. ''Aristotelian Logic''. Albany: State University of New York Press. |
||
* Rose, Lynn E., 1968. ''Aristotle's Syllogistic''. Springfield, Ill.: Clarence C. Thomas. |
* Rose, Lynn E., 1968. ''Aristotle's Syllogistic''. Springfield, Ill.: Clarence C. Thomas. |
||
Line 169: | Line 171: | ||
{{Authority control}} |
{{Authority control}} |
||
[[Category:Works by Aristotle| |
[[Category:Works by Aristotle|*]] |
||
[[Category:History of logic]] |
[[Category:History of logic]] |
||
[[Category:Logic literature]] |
[[Category:Logic literature]] |
||
[[Category:Term logic]] |
[[Category:Term logic]] |
||
[[Category:Ancient Greek logic]] |
|||
[[Category:Philosophy of Aristotle]] |
[[Category:Philosophy of Aristotle]] |
Latest revision as of 00:30, 29 October 2024
The Organon (Ancient Greek: Ὄργανον, meaning "instrument, tool, organ") is the standard collection of Aristotle's six works on logical analysis and dialectic. The name Organon was given by Aristotle's followers, the Peripatetics, who maintained against the Stoics that Logic was "an instrument" of Philosophy.[1]
Aristotle never uses the title Organon to refer to his logical works. The book, according to M. Barthélemy St. Hilaire, was not called "Organon" before the 15th century, and the treatises were collected into one volume, as is supposed, about the time of Andronicus of Rhodes; and it was translated into Latin by Boethius about the 6th century.[1]
The six works of Organon are as follows:
Bekker number |
Work | Latin name |
Logic | ||
Organon | ||
1a | Categories | Categoriae |
16a | On Interpretation | De Interpretatione |
24a | Prior Analytics | Analytica Priora |
71a | Posterior Analytics | Analytica Posteriora |
100a | Topics | Topica |
164a | On Sophistical Refutations | De Sophisticis Elenchis |
Constitution of the texts
[edit]The order of the works is not chronological (which is now hard to determine) but was deliberately chosen by Theophrastus to constitute a well-structured system. Indeed, parts of them seem to be a scheme of a lecture on logic. The arrangement of the works was made by Andronicus of Rhodes around 40 BC.[2]
Aristotle's Metaphysics has some points of overlap with the works making up the Organon but is not traditionally considered part of it; additionally, there are works on logic attributed, with varying degrees of plausibility, to Aristotle that were not known to the Peripatetics.[3]
- The Categories (Latin: Categoriae) introduces Aristotle's 10-fold classification of that which exists: substance, quantity, quality, relation, place, time, situation, condition, action, and passion.
- On Interpretation (Latin: De Interpretatione) introduces Aristotle's conception of proposition and judgement, and the various relations between affirmative, negative, universal, and particular propositions. Aristotle discusses the square of opposition or square of Apuleius in Chapter 7 and its appendix, Chapter 8. Chapter 9 deals with the problem of future contingents.
- The Prior Analytics (Latin: Analytica Priora) introduces his syllogistic method (see term logic), argues for its correctness, and discusses inductive inference.
- The Posterior Analytics (Latin: Analytica Posteriora) deals with definition, demonstration, inductive reasoning, and scientific knowledge.
- The Topics (Latin: Topica) treats issues in constructing valid arguments, and inference that is probable, rather than certain. It is in this treatise that Aristotle mentions the Predicables, later discussed by Porphyry and the scholastic logicians.
- The On Sophistical Refutations (Latin: De Sophisticis Elenchis) gives a treatment of logical fallacies, and provides a key link to Aristotle's tractate on rhetoric.
Whereas the Organon of the Latin Scholastic tradition comprises only the above six works, its independent reception in the Arabic medieval world saw appended to this list of works Aristotle's Rhetoric and Poetics.[4]
Influence
[edit]The Organon was used in the school founded by Aristotle at the Lyceum, and some parts of the works seem to be a scheme of a lecture on logic. So much so that after Aristotle's death, his publishers (Andronicus of Rhodes in 50 BC, for example) collected these works.
Following the collapse of the Western Roman Empire in the fifth century, much of Aristotle's work was lost in the Latin West. The Categories and On Interpretation are the only significant logical works that were available in the early Middle Ages. These had been translated into Latin by Boethius, along with Porphyry's Isagoge, which was also translated into Arabic by Ibn al-Muqaffa' via a Syriac intermediary. The other logical works were not available in Western Christendom until translated into Latin in the 12th century. However, the original Greek texts had been preserved in the Greek-speaking lands of the Eastern Roman Empire (aka Byzantium). In the mid-twelfth century, James of Venice translated into Latin the Posterior Analytics from Greek manuscripts found in Constantinople.
The books of Aristotle were available in the early Muslim world, and after 750 AD Muslims had most of them[dubious – discuss], including the Organon, translated into Arabic, normally via earlier Syriac translations. They were studied by Islamic and Jewish scholars, including Rabbi Moses Maimonides (1135–1204) and the Muslim Judge Ibn Rushd, known in the West as Averroes (1126–1198); both were originally from Córdoba, Spain, although the former left Iberia and by 1168 lived in Egypt.
All the major scholastic philosophers wrote commentaries on the Organon. Aquinas, Ockham and Scotus wrote commentaries on On Interpretation. Ockham and Scotus wrote commentaries on the Categories and Sophistical Refutations. Grosseteste wrote an influential commentary on the Posterior Analytics.
In the Enlightenment there was a revival of interest in logic as the basis of rational enquiry, and a number of texts, most successfully the Port-Royal Logic, polished Aristotelian term logic for pedagogy. During this period, while the logic certainly was based on that of Aristotle, Aristotle's writings themselves were less often the basis of study. There was a tendency in this period to regard the logical systems of the day to be complete, which in turn no doubt stifled innovation in this area. However, Francis Bacon published his Novum Organum ("The New Organon") as a scathing attack in 1620.[5] Immanuel Kant thought that there was nothing else to invent after the work of Aristotle,[6] and the famous logic historian Karl von Prantl claimed that any logician who said anything new about logic was "confused, stupid or perverse." These examples illustrate the force of influence which Aristotle's works on logic had. Indeed, he had already become known by the Scholastics (medieval Christian scholars) as "The Philosopher", due to the influence he had upon medieval theology and philosophy. His influence continued into the Early Modern period and Organon was the basis of school philosophy even in the beginning of the 18th century.[7] Since the logical innovations of the 19th century, particularly the formulation of modern predicate logic, Aristotelian logic had for a time fallen out of favor among many analytic philosophers.
However, the logic historian John Corcoran and others have shown that the works of George Boole and Gottlob Frege—which laid the groundwork for modern mathematical logic—each represent a continuation and extension to Aristotle's logic and in no way contradict or displace it.[8][9] Boole fully accepted and endorsed Aristotle's logic, and Frege included Aristotle's square of opposition at the end of his groundbreaking Begriffsschrift to show the harmony of his theory with the Aristotelian tradition.[10]
See also
[edit]Notes
[edit]- ^ a b Owen, Octavius Freire (1853). "Introduction". The Organon, Or Logical Treatises, of Aristotle. With the Introduction of Porphyry. Vol. 1. Aristotle. H.G. Bohn.
- ^ Hammond, p. 64, "Andronicus Rhodus"
- ^ Edward N. Zalta, ed. (18 March 2000). "Aristotle's Logic, < Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy>". Retrieved 2020-12-19.
- ^ See Black, Deborah L., Logic and Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics in medieval Arabic philosophy, p. 1. Also the “Organon” entry at the SEP.
- ^ The Teaching Company — Birth of the Modern Mind
- ^ Alain Badiou, Theoretical Writings, p 172
- ^ Rutherford, Donald (2006). The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 170ff. ISBN 9780521822428.
- ^ George Boole. 1854/2003. The Laws of Thought, facsimile of 1854 edition, with an introduction by J. Corcoran. Buffalo: Prometheus Books (2003). Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review.24 (2004) 167–169.
- ^ John Corcoran, Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 24 (2003), pp. 261–288.
- ^ Jean-Yves Béziau “Is modern logic non-Aristotelian?”, in Vladimir Markin, Dmitry Zaitsev (eds.), The Logical Legacy of Nikolai Vasiliev and Modern Logic, Cham, Springer, 2017, pp. 19-42.
References
[edit]Primary sources
- Categories, translated by Edghill, E. M., The University of Adelaide: eBooks @ Adelaide, 2007, archived from the original on 2018-12-11, retrieved 2019-01-26.
- On Interpretation, translated by Edghill, E. M., The University of Adelaide: eBooks @ Adelaide, 2007, archived from the original on 2018-02-16, retrieved 2019-01-26.
- Prior Analytics, translated by Jenkinson, A. J., The University of Adelaide: eBooks @ Adelaide, 2007, archived from the original on 2015-09-07, retrieved 2019-01-26.
- Posterior Analytics, translated by Mure, G. R. G., The University of Adelaide: eBooks @ Adelaide, 2007, archived from the original on 2018-12-10, retrieved 2019-01-26.
- Topics, translated by Pickard-Cambridge, W. A., The University of Adelaide: eBooks @ Adelaide, 2007, archived from the original on 2016-03-04, retrieved 2019-01-26.
- On Sophistical Refutations, translated by Pickard-Cambridge, W. A., The University of Adelaide: eBooks @ Adelaide, 2007, archived from the original on 2015-09-07, retrieved 2015-04-21.
Studies
- Bocheński, I. M., 1951. Ancient Formal Logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
- Jan Łukasiewicz, 1951. Aristotle's Syllogistic, from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Lea, Jonathan 1980. Aristotle and Logical Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Monteil, Jean-François La transmission d’Aristote par les Arabes à la chrétienté occidentale: une trouvaille relative au De Interpretatione, Revista Española de Filosofia Medieval 11: 181-195
- Monteil, Jean-François Isidor Pollak et les deux traductions arabes différentes du De interpretatione d’Aristote, Revue d’Études Anciennes 107: 29-46 (2005).
- Monteil, Jean-François Une exception allemande: la traduction du De Interpretatione par le Professeur Gohlke: la note 10 sur les indéterminées d’Aristote, Revues de Études Anciennes 103: 409–427 (2001).
- Parry and Hacker, 1991. Aristotelian Logic. Albany: State University of New York Press.
- Rose, Lynn E., 1968. Aristotle's Syllogistic. Springfield, Ill.: Clarence C. Thomas.
- Whitaker, C.W.A. 1996. Aristotle's De interpretatione. Contradiction and Dialectic, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Veatch, Henry B., 1969. Two Logics: The Conflict between Classical and Neo-Analytic Philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
External links
[edit]- Smith, Robin. "Aristotle's Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy..
- Parsons, Terence. "Traditional Square of Opposition". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy..
- Aristotle: Logic entry by Louis Groarke in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Turner, W., 1903. 'History of Philosophy'. Ginn and Co, Boston. All references in this article are to Chapter nine on 'Aristotle'.
- Aristotle Organon And Other Works e-book at archive.org.
- Interactive Syllogistic Machine for Aristotle's Logic, a web-based syllogistic machine for exploring fallacies, figures, terms, and modes of syllogisms.