Jump to content

Converse (logic): Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m whitespace cleanup; convert special characters found by Wikipedia:Typo Team/moss (via WP:JWB)
 
(47 intermediate revisions by 29 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Reverse of a categorical or hypothetical proposition}}
In [[logic]], the '''converse''' of a categorical or implicational statement is the result of reversing its two parts. For the [[Material conditional|implication]] ''P'' &rarr; ''Q'', the converse is ''Q'' &rarr; ''P''. For the [[categorical proposition]] ''All S are P'', the converse is ''All P are S''. In neither case does the converse [[logical consequence|necessarily follow]] from the original statement.<ref name="Audi">Robert Audi, ed. (1999), ''The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy'', 2nd ed., Cambridge University Press: "converse".</ref>
{{Logical connectives sidebar}}
In [[logic]] and [[mathematics]], the '''converse''' of a categorical or implicational statement is the result of reversing its two constituent statements. For the [[Material conditional|implication]] ''P'' ''Q'', the converse is ''Q'' ''P''. For the [[categorical proposition]] ''All S are P'', the converse is ''All P are S''. Either way, the truth of the converse is generally independent from that of the original statement.<ref name="Audi">Robert Audi, ed. (1999), ''The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy'', 2nd ed., Cambridge University Press: "converse".</ref>


==Implicational converse==
==Implicational converse==
[[File:Venn1101.svg|220px|thumb|[[Venn diagram]] of <math>P \leftarrow Q</math> <br> <small>The white area shows where the statement is false.</small>]]
Let ''S'' be a statement of the form ''P implies Q'' (''P'' &rarr; ''Q''). Then the '''converse''' of ''S'' is the statement ''Q implies P'' (''Q'' &rarr; ''P''). In general, the verity of ''S'' says nothing about the verity of its converse, unless the [[Antecedent (logic)|antecedent]] ''P'' and the [[consequent]] ''Q'' are logically equivalent.


Let ''S'' be a statement of the form ''P implies Q'' (''P'' ''Q''). Then the ''converse'' of ''S'' is the statement ''Q implies P'' (''Q'' ''P''). In general, the truth of ''S'' says nothing about the truth of its converse,<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.thoughtco.com/converse-contrapositive-and-inverse-3126458|title=What Are the Converse, Contrapositive, and Inverse?|last=Taylor|first=Courtney|website=ThoughtCo|language=en|access-date=2019-11-27}}</ref> unless the [[Antecedent (logic)|antecedent]] ''P'' and the [[consequent]] ''Q'' are logically equivalent.
For example, consider the true statement "If I am a human, then I am mortal." The converse of that statement is "If I am mortal, then I am a human," which is not [[logical truth|necessarily true]].


For example, consider the true statement "If I am a human, then I am mortal." The converse of that statement is "If I am mortal, then I am a human," which is not necessarily [[logical truth|true]].
On the other hand, the converse of a statement with mutually inclusive terms remains true, given the truth of the original proposition. This is equivalent to saying that the converse of a definition is true. Thus, the statement "If I am a triangle, then I am a three-sided polygon" is logically equivalent to "If I am a three-sided polygon, then I am a triangle", because the definition of "triangle" is "three-sided polygon".


However, the converse of a statement with mutually inclusive terms remains true, given the truth of the original proposition. This is equivalent to saying that the converse of a definition is true. Thus, the statement "If I am a triangle, then I am a three-sided polygon" is logically equivalent to "If I am a three-sided polygon, then I am a triangle," because the definition of "triangle" is "three-sided polygon".
A truth table makes it clear that ''S'' and the converse of ''S'' are not logically equivalent unless both terms imply each other:


A truth table makes it clear that ''S'' and the converse of ''S'' are not logically equivalent, unless both terms imply each other:
{| class="wikitable"

! ''P'' || ''Q'' || ''P'' &rarr; ''Q'' || ''Q'' &rarr; ''P'' (converse)
{{2-ary truth table|A=P|B=Q
|-
|1|1|0|1|<math> P \rightarrow Q</math>
| T || T || T || T
|thick
|-
|1|0|1|1|<math> P \leftarrow Q</math> (converse)
| T || F || F || T
}}

Going from a statement to its converse is the fallacy of [[affirming the consequent]]. However, if the statement ''S'' and its converse are equivalent (i.e., ''P'' is true [[iff|if and only if]] ''Q'' is also true), then affirming the consequent will be valid.

Converse implication is logically equivalent to the disjunction of <math>P</math> and <math>\neg Q</math>

{| style="text-align: center; border: 1px solid darkgray;"
|-
|-
| <math>P \leftarrow Q</math>
| F || T || T || F
| <math>\Leftrightarrow</math>
| <math>P</math>
| <math>\lor</math>
| <math>\neg Q</math>
|-
|-
| [[File:Venn1101.svg|50px]]
| F || F || T || T
| <math>\Leftrightarrow</math>
| [[File:Venn0101.svg|50px]]
| <math>\lor</math>
| [[File:Venn1100.svg|50px]]
|}
|}


In natural language, this could be rendered "not ''Q'' without ''P''".
Going from a statement to its converse is the fallacy of [[affirming the consequent]]. However, if the statement ''S'' and its converse are equivalent (i.e., if ''P'' is true [[iff|if and only if]] ''Q'' is also true), then affirming the consequent will be valid.


===Converse of a theorem===
===Converse of a theorem===
In mathematics, the converse of a theorem of the form ''P'' &rarr; ''Q'' will be ''Q'' &rarr; ''P''. The converse may or may not be true. If true, the proof may be difficult. For example, the [[Four-vertex theorem]] was proved in 1912, but its converse only in 1998.
In mathematics, the converse of a theorem of the form ''P'' ''Q'' will be ''Q'' ''P''. The converse may or may not be true, and even if true, the proof may be difficult. For example, the [[four-vertex theorem]] was proved in 1912, but its converse was proved only in 1997.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.math.colostate.edu/~clayton/research/talks/FourVertexPrint.pdf|title=The Four Vertex Theorem and its Converse|last=Shonkwiler|first=Clay|date=October 6, 2006|website=math.colostate.edu|access-date=2019-11-26}}</ref>


In practice, when determining the converse of a mathematical theorem, aspects of the antecedent may be taken as establishing context. That is, the converse of ''Given P, if Q then R'' will be ''Given P, if R then Q''. For example, the [[Pythagorean theorem]] can be stated as:
In practice, when determining the converse of a mathematical theorem, aspects of the antecedent may be taken as establishing context. That is, the converse of "Given P, if Q then R''"'' will be "Given P, if R then Q''"''. For example, the [[Pythagorean theorem]] can be stated as:


<blockquote>
<blockquote>
'''Given''' a triangle with sides of length ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'', '''if''' the angle opposite the side of length ''c'' is a right angle, '''then''' '''''a''<sup>2</sup>&nbsp;+&nbsp;''b''<sup>2</sup>&nbsp;=&nbsp;''c''<sup>2</sup>.
''Given'' a triangle with sides of length ''<math>a</math>'', ''<math>b</math>'', and ''<math>c</math>'', ''if'' the angle opposite the side of length ''<math>c</math>'' is a right angle, ''then'' <math>a^2 + b^2 = c^2</math>'''.'''
</blockquote>
</blockquote>


Line 36: Line 53:


<blockquote>
<blockquote>
'''Given''' a triangle with sides of length ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'', '''if''' ''a''<sup>2</sup>&nbsp;+&nbsp;''b''<sup>2</sup>&nbsp;=&nbsp;''c''<sup>2</sup>, '''then''' the angle opposite the side of length ''c'' is a right angle.
''Given'' a triangle with sides of length ''<math>a</math>'', ''<math>b</math>'', and ''<math>c</math>'', ''if'' <math>a^2 + b^2 = c^2</math>, ''then'' the angle opposite the side of length ''<math>c</math>'' is a right angle.
</blockquote>
</blockquote>

===Converse of a relation===
[[File:An example of converse property.png|thumb|Converse a simple mathematical relation]]
If <math>R</math> is a [[binary relation]] with <math>R \subseteq A \times B,</math> then the [[converse relation]] <math>R^T = \{ (b,a) : (a,b) \in R \}</math> is also called the ''transpose''.<ref>[[Gunther Schmidt]] & Thomas Ströhlein (1993) ''Relations and Graphs'', page 9, [[Springer books]]</ref>

==Notation==
The converse of the implication ''P'' → ''Q'' may be written ''Q'' → ''P'', <math>P \leftarrow Q</math>, but may also be notated <math>P \subset Q</math>, or "B''pq''" (in [[Józef Maria Bocheński|Bocheński notation]]).{{cn|date=March 2020}}


==Categorical converse==
==Categorical converse==
{{see also|Categorical proposition#Conversion}}
In traditional logic, the process of going from ''All S are P'' to its converse ''All P are S'' is called '''conversion'''. In the words of [[Asa Mahan]], "The original proposition is called the exposita; when converted, it is denominated the converse. Conversion is valid when, and only when, nothing is asserted in the converse which is not affirmed or implied in the exposita."<ref>Asa Mahan (1857), The Science of Logic: or, An Analysis of the Laws of Thought, [https://books.google.com/books?id=J_wtAAAAMAAJ&pg=PA82 p. 82].</ref> The "exposita" is more usually called the "convertend." In its simple form, conversion is valid only for '''E''' and '''I''' propositions:<ref>William Thomas Parry and Edward A. Hacker (1991), ''Aristotelian Logic'', SUNY Press, [https://books.google.com/books?id=3Sg84H6B-m4C&pg=PA207 p. 207].</ref>

In traditional logic, the process of switching the subject term with the predicate term is called ''conversion''. For example, going from "No ''S'' are ''P"'' to its converse "No ''P'' are ''S"''. In the words of [[Asa Mahan]]: <blockquote>"The original proposition is called the exposita; when converted, it is denominated the converse. Conversion is valid when, and only when, nothing is asserted in the converse which is not affirmed or implied in the exposita."<ref>[[Asa Mahan]] (1857) ''The Science of Logic: or, An Analysis of the Laws of Thought'', [https://books.google.com/books?id=J_wtAAAAMAAJ&pg=PA82 p. 82].</ref> </blockquote>The "exposita" is more usually called the "convertend". In its simple form, conversion is valid only for '''E''' and '''I''' propositions:<ref>William Thomas Parry and Edward A. Hacker (1991), ''Aristotelian Logic'', SUNY Press, [https://books.google.com/books?id=3Sg84H6B-m4C&pg=PA207 p. 207].</ref>


{| class="wikitable"
{| class="wikitable"
! Type || Convertend || Simple converse || Converse ''per accidens''
! Type || Convertend || Simple converse || Converse ''per accidens'' (valid if P exists)
|-
|-
| '''A''' || All S are P || ''not valid'' || Some P is S
| '''A''' || All S are P || ''not valid'' || Some P is S
Line 49: Line 75:
| '''E''' || No S is P || No P is S || Some P is not S
| '''E''' || No S is P || No P is S || Some P is not S
|-
|-
| '''I''' || Some S is P || Some P is S || &ndash;
| '''I''' || Some S is P || Some P is S ||
|-
|-
| '''O''' || Some S is not P || ''not valid'' || &ndash;
| '''O''' || Some S is not P || ''not valid'' ||
|}
|}


The validity of simple conversion only for '''E''' and '''I''' propositions can be expressed by the restriction that "No term must be distributed in the converse which is not distributed in the convertend."<ref>[[James H. Hyslop]] (1892), ''The Elements of Logic'', C. Scribner's sons, p. 156.</ref> For '''E''' propositions, both subject and predicate are [[Distribution of terms|distributed]], while for '''I''' propositions, neither is.
The validity of simple conversion only for '''E''' and '''I''' propositions can be expressed by the restriction that "No term must be distributed in the converse which is not distributed in the convertend."<ref>[[James H. Hyslop]] (1892), ''The Elements of Logic'', C. Scribner's sons, p. 156.</ref> For '''E''' propositions, both subject and predicate are [[Distribution of terms|distributed]], while for '''I''' propositions, neither is.


For '''A''' propositions, the subject is distributed while the predicate is not, and so the inference from an '''A''' statement to its converse is not valid. As an example, for the '''A''' proposition "All cats are mammals," the converse "All mammals are cats" is obviously false. However, the weaker statement "Some mammals are cats" is true. Logicians define conversion ''per accidens'' to be the process of producing this weaker statement. Inference from a statement to its converse ''per accidens'' is generally valid. However, as with [[syllogism]]s, this switch from the universal to the particular causes problems with empty categories: "All unicorns are mammals" is often taken as true, while the converse ''per accidens'' "Some mammals are unicorns" is clearly false.
For '''A''' propositions, the subject is distributed while the predicate is not, and so the inference from an '''A''' statement to its converse is not valid. As an example, for the '''A''' proposition "All cats are mammals", the converse "All mammals are cats" is obviously false. However, the weaker statement "Some mammals are cats" is true. Logicians define conversion ''per accidens'' to be the process of producing this weaker statement. Inference from a statement to its converse ''per accidens'' is generally valid. However, as with [[syllogism]]s, this switch from the universal to the particular causes problems with empty categories: "All unicorns are mammals" is often taken as true, while the converse ''per accidens'' "Some mammals are unicorns" is clearly false.


In [[First-order logic|first-order predicate calculus]], ''All S are P'' can be represented as <math>\forall x. S(x) \to P(x)</math>.<ref>Gordon Hunnings (1988), ''The World and Language in Wittgenstein's Philosophy'', SUNY Press, [https://books.google.com/books?id=5XXz7B2PLRsC&pg=PA42 p. 42].</ref> It is therefore clear that the categorical converse is closely related to the implicational converse, and that ''S'' and ''P'' cannot be swapped in ''All S are P''.
In [[First-order logic|first-order predicate calculus]], ''All S are P'' can be represented as <math>\forall x. S(x) \to P(x)</math>.<ref>Gordon Hunnings (1988), ''The World and Language in Wittgenstein's Philosophy'', SUNY Press, [https://books.google.com/books?id=5XXz7B2PLRsC&pg=PA42 p. 42].</ref> It is therefore clear that the categorical converse is closely related to the implicational converse, and that ''S'' and ''P'' cannot be swapped in ''All S are P''.


==See also==
==See also==
{{Portal|Logic}}
{{Portal|Philosophy}}
{{col-begin}}
{{col-break}}
* [[Aristotle]]
* [[Aristotle]]
* [[Contraposition]]
* [[Contraposition]]
* [[Inference]]
* [[Inverse (logic)]]
* [[Logical connective]]
* [[Obversion]]
* [[Obversion]]
* [[Syllogism]]
{{col-break}}
* [[Converse (semantics)]]
* [[Term logic]]
* [[Term logic]]
* [[Transposition (logic)]]
* [[Transposition (logic)]]
* [[Inverse (logic)]]
{{col-end}}


==References==
==References==
Line 80: Line 100:


==Further reading==
==Further reading==
*[[Aristotle]]. ''Organon''.
* [[Aristotle]]. ''Organon''.
*[[Irving Copi|Copi, Irving]]. ''Introduction to Logic''. MacMillan, 1953.
* [[Irving Copi|Copi, Irving]]. ''Introduction to Logic''. MacMillan, 1953.
*Copi, Irving. ''Symbolic Logic''. MacMillan, 1979, fifth edition.
* Copi, Irving. ''Symbolic Logic''. MacMillan, 1979, fifth edition.
*[[Susan Stebbing|Stebbing, Susan]]. ''A Modern Introduction to Logic''. Cromwell Company, 1931.
* [[Susan Stebbing|Stebbing, Susan]]. ''A Modern Introduction to Logic''. Cromwell Company, 1931.

{{Logical connectives}}


[[Category:Logical connectives]]
[[Category:Immediate inference]]
[[Category:Immediate inference]]

Latest revision as of 02:32, 19 November 2024

In logic and mathematics, the converse of a categorical or implicational statement is the result of reversing its two constituent statements. For the implication PQ, the converse is QP. For the categorical proposition All S are P, the converse is All P are S. Either way, the truth of the converse is generally independent from that of the original statement.[1]

Implicational converse

[edit]
Venn diagram of
The white area shows where the statement is false.

Let S be a statement of the form P implies Q (PQ). Then the converse of S is the statement Q implies P (QP). In general, the truth of S says nothing about the truth of its converse,[2] unless the antecedent P and the consequent Q are logically equivalent.

For example, consider the true statement "If I am a human, then I am mortal." The converse of that statement is "If I am mortal, then I am a human," which is not necessarily true.

However, the converse of a statement with mutually inclusive terms remains true, given the truth of the original proposition. This is equivalent to saying that the converse of a definition is true. Thus, the statement "If I am a triangle, then I am a three-sided polygon" is logically equivalent to "If I am a three-sided polygon, then I am a triangle," because the definition of "triangle" is "three-sided polygon".

A truth table makes it clear that S and the converse of S are not logically equivalent, unless both terms imply each other:

(converse)
FFTT
FTTF
TFFT
TTTT

Going from a statement to its converse is the fallacy of affirming the consequent. However, if the statement S and its converse are equivalent (i.e., P is true if and only if Q is also true), then affirming the consequent will be valid.

Converse implication is logically equivalent to the disjunction of and

In natural language, this could be rendered "not Q without P".

Converse of a theorem

[edit]

In mathematics, the converse of a theorem of the form PQ will be QP. The converse may or may not be true, and even if true, the proof may be difficult. For example, the four-vertex theorem was proved in 1912, but its converse was proved only in 1997.[3]

In practice, when determining the converse of a mathematical theorem, aspects of the antecedent may be taken as establishing context. That is, the converse of "Given P, if Q then R" will be "Given P, if R then Q". For example, the Pythagorean theorem can be stated as:

Given a triangle with sides of length , , and , if the angle opposite the side of length is a right angle, then .

The converse, which also appears in Euclid's Elements (Book I, Proposition 48), can be stated as:

Given a triangle with sides of length , , and , if , then the angle opposite the side of length is a right angle.

Converse of a relation

[edit]
Converse a simple mathematical relation

If is a binary relation with then the converse relation is also called the transpose.[4]

Notation

[edit]

The converse of the implication PQ may be written QP, , but may also be notated , or "Bpq" (in Bocheński notation).[citation needed]

Categorical converse

[edit]

In traditional logic, the process of switching the subject term with the predicate term is called conversion. For example, going from "No S are P" to its converse "No P are S". In the words of Asa Mahan:

"The original proposition is called the exposita; when converted, it is denominated the converse. Conversion is valid when, and only when, nothing is asserted in the converse which is not affirmed or implied in the exposita."[5]

The "exposita" is more usually called the "convertend". In its simple form, conversion is valid only for E and I propositions:[6]

Type Convertend Simple converse Converse per accidens (valid if P exists)
A All S are P not valid Some P is S
E No S is P No P is S Some P is not S
I Some S is P Some P is S
O Some S is not P not valid

The validity of simple conversion only for E and I propositions can be expressed by the restriction that "No term must be distributed in the converse which is not distributed in the convertend."[7] For E propositions, both subject and predicate are distributed, while for I propositions, neither is.

For A propositions, the subject is distributed while the predicate is not, and so the inference from an A statement to its converse is not valid. As an example, for the A proposition "All cats are mammals", the converse "All mammals are cats" is obviously false. However, the weaker statement "Some mammals are cats" is true. Logicians define conversion per accidens to be the process of producing this weaker statement. Inference from a statement to its converse per accidens is generally valid. However, as with syllogisms, this switch from the universal to the particular causes problems with empty categories: "All unicorns are mammals" is often taken as true, while the converse per accidens "Some mammals are unicorns" is clearly false.

In first-order predicate calculus, All S are P can be represented as .[8] It is therefore clear that the categorical converse is closely related to the implicational converse, and that S and P cannot be swapped in All S are P.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Robert Audi, ed. (1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2nd ed., Cambridge University Press: "converse".
  2. ^ Taylor, Courtney. "What Are the Converse, Contrapositive, and Inverse?". ThoughtCo. Retrieved 2019-11-27.
  3. ^ Shonkwiler, Clay (October 6, 2006). "The Four Vertex Theorem and its Converse" (PDF). math.colostate.edu. Retrieved 2019-11-26.
  4. ^ Gunther Schmidt & Thomas Ströhlein (1993) Relations and Graphs, page 9, Springer books
  5. ^ Asa Mahan (1857) The Science of Logic: or, An Analysis of the Laws of Thought, p. 82.
  6. ^ William Thomas Parry and Edward A. Hacker (1991), Aristotelian Logic, SUNY Press, p. 207.
  7. ^ James H. Hyslop (1892), The Elements of Logic, C. Scribner's sons, p. 156.
  8. ^ Gordon Hunnings (1988), The World and Language in Wittgenstein's Philosophy, SUNY Press, p. 42.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Aristotle. Organon.
  • Copi, Irving. Introduction to Logic. MacMillan, 1953.
  • Copi, Irving. Symbolic Logic. MacMillan, 1979, fifth edition.
  • Stebbing, Susan. A Modern Introduction to Logic. Cromwell Company, 1931.