Jump to content

Metaphysics (Aristotle): Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Title, date, style, and the arrangement of the treatises: similar paragraphs together, change section title to match order
4 wikilinks
Tags: Visual edit Mobile edit Mobile web edit Advanced mobile edit
 
(48 intermediate revisions by 23 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|One of the principal works of Aristotle}}
{{Short description|One of the principal works of Aristotle}}
{{italic title}}
{{italic title}}
'''''Metaphysics''''' ([[Ancient Greek|Greek]]: τὰ μετὰ τὰ φυσικά, "those after the physics"; [[Latin]]: ''Metaphysica''<ref>[http://www.isnature.org/Files/Aristotle/ ''Aristotelis Opera''] by [[August Immanuel Bekker]] (1837).</ref>) is one of the principal works of [[Aristotle]], in which he develops the doctrine that he calls ''First Philosophy''.{{efn|sometimes referred to as ''Wisdom'', sometimes as , and sometimes as ''Theology''}} The work is a compilation of various texts treating abstract subjects, notably [[substance theory]], different kinds of [[Causality|causation]], [[hylomorphism|form and matter]], the existence of [[mathematical objects]] and the [[cosmos]], which together constitute much of the branch of [[philosophy]] later known as [[metaphysics]].
{{The Works of Aristotle}}
'''''Metaphysics''''' ([[Ancient Greek|Greek]]: τὰ μετὰ τὰ φυσικά, "things after the ones about the natural world"; [[Latin]]: ''Metaphysica''<ref>[http://www.isnature.org/Files/Aristotle/ ''Aristotelis Opera''] by [[August Immanuel Bekker]] (1837).</ref>) is one of the principal works of [[Aristotle]], in which he develops the doctrine that is sometimes referred to as ''Wisdom'',{{clarify|sophia? phronesis?|date=January 2023}} sometimes as ''First Philosophy'', and sometimes as ''[[Theology]]''. The work is a compilation of various texts treating abstract subjects, notably [[substance theory]], different kinds of [[Causality|causation]], [[hylomorphism|form and matter]], the existence of [[mathematical object]]s and the [[cosmos]], which together constitute much of the branch of [[philosophy]] later known as [[metaphysics]].


== Date, style and composition==
== Overview ==
Many of Aristotle's works are extremely compressed, and many scholars believe that in their current form, they are likely lecture notes.<ref>E.g. J.A.K. Thomson, The Ethics of Aristotle, (Penguin, 1953) p. 13 and E. Barker The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (Dover, 1959) p. 65.</ref> Subsequent to the arrangement of Aristotle's works by [[Andronicus of Rhodes]] in the first century BC, a number of his treatises were referred to as the writings "after ("[[Meta (prefix)|meta]]") the ''Physics''"{{efn|[[:wikt:μετὰ|μετὰ]] τὰ [[:wikt:φυσικός|φυσικά]]}}, the origin of the current title for the collection ''Metaphysics''. Some{{who|date=January 2023}} have interpreted the expression "meta" to imply that the subject of the work goes "beyond" that of Aristotle's [[Physics (Aristotle)|''Physics'']] or that it is [[Metatheory|metatheoretical]] in relation to the ''Physics''. But others{{who|date=January 2023}} believe that "meta" referred simply to the work's place in the canonical arrangement of Aristotle's writings, which is at least as old as [[Andronicus of Rhodes]] or even [[Hermippus of Smyrna]].<ref>[[W. D. Ross]], ''Aristotle's Metaphysics'' (1953), vol. 1, p. xxxii.</ref> In other surviving works of Aristotle, the metaphysical treatises are referred to as "the [writings] concerning first philosophy";{{efn|τὰ περὶ τῆς πρώτης φιλοσοφίας e.g., in ''[[Movement of Animals]]'' 700b9}} which was the term Aristotle used for metaphysics.{{efn|He called the study of nature or [[natural philosophy]] "second philosophy"<ref>''Metaphysics'' 1037a15</ref>}}
Aristotle's worldview is rooted in an analysis of natural language, [[common sense]], and the observations gathered from the natural sciences. The result is a synthesis of the naturalism of empirical science, with a critical inquiry into language, ontology and epistemology which has now informed intellectual traditions around the world for more than two thousand years.<ref>Lawson-Tancred, introduction.</ref> At the heart of the book lie three questions. What is existence, and what sorts of things exist in the world? How can things continue to exist, and yet undergo the change we see about us in the natural world? And how can this world be understood?{{cn|date=November 2021}}


It is notoriously difficult to specify the date at which Aristotle wrote these treatises as a whole or even individually, especially because the ''Metaphysics'' is, in [[Jonathan Barnes]]' words, "a farrago, a hotch-potch", and more generally because of the difficulty of dating ''any'' of Aristotle's writings.<ref>Jonathan Barnes, "Life and Work" in ''The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle'' (1995), pp. 18-22."Farrago": Barnes, "Metaphysics" in ''The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle'', p. 68.</ref> The order in which the books were written is not known; their arrangement is due to later editors. In the manuscripts, books are referred to by Greek letters. For many scholars, it is customary to refer to the books by their letter names. Book 1 is called Alpha (Α); 2, little alpha (α);{{efn|The second book was given the title "little alpha," apparently because it appears to have nothing to do with the other books (and, very early, it was supposed not to have been written by Aristotle) or, although this is less likely,{{cn|date=January 2023}} because of its shortness. This, then, disrupts the correspondence of letters to numbers, as book 2 is little alpha, book 3 is beta, and so on.}} 3, Beta (Β); 4, Gamma (Γ); 5, Delta (Δ); 6, Epsilon (Ε); 7, Zeta (Ζ); 8, Eta (Η); 9, Theta (Θ); 10, Iota (Ι); 11, Kappa (Κ); 12, Lambda (Λ); 13, Mu (Μ); 14, Nu (Ν).
==Title, style, date, and the arrangement of the treatises==
Subsequent to the arrangement of Aristotle's works by scholars at [[Alexandria]] in the first century CE, a number of his treatises were referred to as τὰ μετὰ τὰ φυσικά (''ta meta ta physika''; literally, "the [writings] after the ''Physics''"). This is the origin of the title for collection of treatises now known as Aristotle's ''Metaphysics''. Some have interpreted the expression "τὰ μετὰ τὰ φυσικά" to imply that the subject of the work goes "beyond" that of Aristotle's [[Physics (Aristotle)|''Physics'']] or that it is [[Metatheory|metatheoretical]] in relation to the ''Physics''. But others believe that "τὰ μετὰ τὰ φυσικά" referred simply to the work's place in the canonical arrangement of Aristotle's writings, which is at least as old as [[Andronicus of Rhodes]] or even [[Hermippus of Smyrna]].<ref>[[W. D. Ross]], ''Aristotle's Metaphysics'' (1953), vol. 1, p. xxxii.</ref> Within the Aristotelian corpus itself,<ref>e.g., in ''[[Movement of Animals]]'' 700b9.</ref> the metaphysical treatises are referred to as τὰ περὶ τῆς πρώτης φιλοσοφίας (literally, "the [writings] concerning first philosophy"); "first philosophy" was what Aristotle called the subjects of metaphysics. (He called the study of nature or [[natural philosophy]] "second philosophy" (''Metaphysics'' 1037a15).)


== Outline ==
Many scholars believe that Aristotle's works as we have them today are little more than lecture notes.<ref>E.g. J.A.K. Thomson, The Ethics of Aristotle, (Penguin, 1953) p. 13 and E. Barker The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (Dover, 1959) p. 65.</ref> Many of his works are extremely compressed and thus baffling to beginners. Nowhere is this more evident than in the ''Metaphysics'' — [[Avicenna]] said that he had read the ''Metaphysics'' of Aristotle forty times, but still did not understand it. Only later, after having read [[al-Farabi]]'s, ''Purposes of the Metaphysics of Aristotle'', did he understand Aristotle's book.{{efn|I read the Metaphysics [of Aristotle], but I could not comprehend its contents, and its author's object remained obscure to me, even when I had gone back and read it forty times and had got to the point where I had memorized it. In spite of this I could not understand it nor its object, and I despaired of myself and said, "This is a book which there is no way of understanding." But one day in the afternoon when I was at the booksellers' quarter a salesman approached with a book in his hand which he was calling out for sale. (...) So I bought it and, lo and behold, it was Abu Nasr al-Farabi's book on the objects of the Metaphysics.[probably the Kitab al-huruf, ed. by Muhsin Mahdi as Alfarabi's Book of Letters (Beyrouth, 1969).] I returned home and was quick to read it, and in no time the objects of that book became clear to me because I had got to the point of having memorized it by heart. (William E. Gohlam (ed.). The Life of Ibn Sina, Albany, State of New York University Press, 1974, pp. 33-35).}}
[[File:Ephesus37.jpg|thumb|upright=1|Wisdom personified as a deity in the [[Library of Celsus]] in [[Ephesus]]. Aristotle discusses the nature of wisdom, or first philosophy, which he defines as the study of first principles and causes.]]

It is notoriously difficult to specify the date at which Aristotle wrote these treatises as a whole or even individually, especially because the ''Metaphysics'' is, in [[Jonathan Barnes]]' words, "a farrago, a hotch-potch", and more generally because of the difficulty of dating ''any'' of Aristotle's writings.<ref>Jonathan Barnes, "Life and Work" in ''The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle'' (1995), pp. 18-22."Farrago": Barnes, "Metaphysics" in ''The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle'', p. 68.</ref> The order in which the books were written is not known; their arrangement is due to later editors. In the manuscripts, books are referred to by Greek letters. For many scholars, it is customary to refer to the books by their letter names. Book 1 is called Alpha (Α); 2, little alpha (α);{{efn|The second book was given the title "little alpha," apparently because it appears to have nothing to do with the other books (and, very early, it was supposed not to have been written by Aristotle) or, although this is less likely,{{cn}} because of its shortness. This, then, disrupts the correspondence of letters to numbers, as book 2 is little alpha, book 3 is beta, and so on.}} 3, Beta (Β); 4, Gamma (Γ); 5, Delta (Δ); 6, Epsilon (Ε); 7, Zeta (Ζ); 8, Eta (Η); 9, Theta (Θ); 10, Iota (Ι); 11, Kappa (Κ); 12, Lambda (Λ); 13, Mu (Μ); 14, Nu (Ν).

==Summary==
{{one source|section|date=June 2012}}
=== Books I–VI: Alpha, little Alpha, Beta, Gamma, Delta and Epsilon ===
=== Books I–VI: Alpha, little Alpha, Beta, Gamma, Delta and Epsilon ===
*'''Book I or Alpha''' outlines "first philosophy", which is a knowledge of the [[first principle]]s or causes of things. The wise are able to teach because they know the ''why'' of things, unlike those who only know ''that'' things are a certain way based on their memory and sensations. Because of their knowledge of first causes and principles, they are better fitted to command, rather than to obey. Book Alpha also surveys previous philosophies from [[Thales of Miletus|Thales]] to Plato, especially their treatment of causes.
*'''Book I or Alpha''' begins by discussing the nature of knowledge and compares knowledge gained from the [[senses]] and from [[memory]], arguing that knowledge is acquired from memory through experience.<ref>981a</ref> It then defines "[[wisdom]]" (''[[Sophia (Wisdom)|sophia]]'') as a knowledge of the [[first principles]] (''[[arche]]'') or [[Causality|causes]] of things. Because those who are wise understand the first principles and causes, they know the ''why'' of things, unlike those who only know ''that'' things are a certain way based on their memory and sensations. The wise are able to teach because they know the ''why'' of things, and so they are better fitted to command, rather than to obey. He then surveys the first principles and causes of previous philosophers, starting with the [[material monism|material monists]] of the [[Ionian School (philosophy)|Ionian school]] and continuing up until [[Plato]].
*'''Book II or "little alpha"''': The purpose of this chapter is to address a possible objection to Aristotle's account of how we understand first principles and thus acquire wisdom. Aristotle replies that the idea of an infinite causal series is absurd, and thus there must be a first cause which is not itself caused. This idea is developed later in book Lambda, where he develops an argument for the existence of [[God]], whom he calls the [[Primus Mobile|prime mover]].
*'''Book II or "little alpha"''': Book II addresses a possible objection to the account of how we understand first principles and thus acquire wisdom, that attempting to discover the first principle would lead to an [[infinite regress|infinite series of causes]]. It argues in response that the idea of an infinite causal series is absurd, and argues that only things that are [[On Generation and Corruption|created or destroyed]] require a cause, and that thus there must be a primary cause that is [[Eternity of the world|eternal]], an idea he develops later in Book Lambda.
*'''Book III or Beta''' lists the main problems or puzzles (''[[aporia]]'') of philosophy.<ref>[[Robert Maynard Hutchins]] (1952), ''[[Great Books of the Western World]]'' 8: Aristotle, p. 495.</ref>
*'''Book III or Beta''' lists the main problems or puzzles (''[[aporia]]'') of philosophy.<ref>[[Robert Maynard Hutchins]] (1952), ''[[Great Books of the Western World]]'' 8: Aristotle, p. 495.</ref>
*'''Book IV or Gamma''': Chapters 2 and 3 argue for its status as a subject in its own right. The rest is a defense of (a) what we now call the [[principle of contradiction]], the principle that it is not possible for the same proposition to be (the case) and not to be (the case), and (b) what we now call the principle of excluded middle: ''tertium non datur'' — there cannot be an intermediary between contradictory statements.
*'''Book IV or Gamma''': Chapters 2 and 3 argue for its status as a subject in its own right. The rest is a defense of (a) what we now call the [[principle of contradiction]], the principle that it is not possible for the same proposition to be (the case) and not to be (the case), and (b) what we now call the principle of excluded middle: ''tertium non datur'' — there cannot be an intermediary between contradictory statements.
*'''Book V or Delta''' ("philosophical lexicon") is a list of definitions of about thirty key terms such as [[cause]], [[nature]], [[one]], and [[Quantifier (linguistics)|many]].
*'''Book V or Delta''' ("philosophical lexicon") is a list of definitions of about thirty key terms such as [[cause]], [[nature]], [[one]], and [[Quantifier (linguistics)|many]].
*'''Book VI or Epsilon''' has two main concerns. Aristotle is first concerned with a hierarchy of the sciences. As we know, a science can be either productive, practical or theoretical. Because theoretical sciences study being or beings for their own sake—for example, Physics studies beings that can be moved (1025b27)—and do not have a target ([[Telos|Telos ''(τέλος)'', end or goal]]; τέλειος, complete or perfect) beyond themselves, they are superior. The study of being ''qua'' being, or First Philosophy, is superior to all the other theoretical sciences because it is concerned the ''ultimate'' causes of ''all'' reality, not just the secondary causes of a part of reality. The second concern of Epsilon is proving that being (τὸ ὄν) considered ''[[Accident (philosophy)|per accidens]]'' (κατὰ συμβεβηκός) cannot be studied as a science. ''Per accidens'' being does not involve art (τέχνη), nor does exist by necessity (''per se'' or καθ᾽ αὑτό), and therefore does not deserve to be studied as a science. Aristotle dismisses the study of the ''per accidens'' as a science fit for Sophists, a group whose philosophies (or lack thereof) he consistently rejects throughout the ''Metaphysics''.
*'''Book VI or Epsilon''' has two main concerns. The first concern is the hierarchy of the sciences: productive, practical or theoretical. Aristotle considers theoretical sciences superior because they study beings for their own sake—for example, Physics studies beings that can be moved{{efn|1025b27}}—and do not have a target (τέλος ''[[telos]]'', "end, goal"; τέλειος, "complete, perfect") beyond themselves. He argues that the study of being ''qua'' being, or First Philosophy, is superior to all the other theoretical sciences because it is concerned with the ''ultimate'' causes of ''all'' reality, not just the secondary causes of a part of reality. The second concern of Epsilon is the study of "[[Accident (philosophy)|accidents]]" (κατὰ συμβεβηκός), those attributes that do not depend on [[techne|(τέχνη)]] or exist by necessity, which Aristotle believes do not deserve to be studied as a science.
[[Image:Meta-moerbeke jpeg031-part.jpg|thumb|upright=1.4||Book 7 of the Metaphysics: From a manuscript of [[William of Moerbeke]]'s translation]]
[[File:Meta-moerbeke jpeg031-part.jpg|thumb|right|upright=1.3|Book 7 of the Metaphysics: From a manuscript of [[William of Moerbeke]]'s translation]]

=== Books VII–IX: Zeta, Eta, and Theta ===
=== Books VII–IX: Zeta, Eta, and Theta ===
The Middle Books are generally considered the core of the ''Metaphysics''.
Books Zeta, Eta, and Theta are generally considered the core of the ''Metaphysics''.{{cn|date=January 2023}}
Book Zeta (VII) begins by stating that "being" has several senses, the purpose of philosophy is to understand the primary kind of being, called ''[[Substance theory|substance]]'' (''[[ousia]]'') and determine what substances there are, a concept that Aristotle develops in the ''[[Categories (Aristotle)|Categories]]''.{{sfn|Cohen|loc=5}}
====VII: Zeta====
Book Zeta begins with the remark that ‘Being’ has many senses. The purpose of philosophy is to understand being. The primary kind of being is what Aristotle calls ''substance''. What substances are there, and are there any substances besides perceptible ones? Aristotle considers four candidates for substance: (i) the ‘essence’ or ‘what it was to be a thing’ (ii) the Platonic universal, (iii) the genus to which a substance belongs and (iv) the substratum or ‘matter’ which underlies all the properties of a thing. He dismisses the idea that matter can be substance, for if we eliminate everything that is a property from what can have the property, we are left with something that has no properties at all. Such 'ultimate matter' cannot be substance. Separability and 'this-ness' are fundamental to our concept of substance.
Zeta goes on to consider four candidates for substance: (i) the '[[essence]]' or 'what it is to be' of a thing (ii) the universal, (iii) the [[genus]] to which a substance belongs and (iv) the material [[Hypokeimenon|substrate]] that underlies all the properties of a thing.
* He dismisses the idea that matter can be substance, for if we eliminate everything that is a property from what can have the property, such as [[hyle|matter]] and the shape, we are left with something that has no properties at all. Such 'ultimate matter' cannot be substance. Separability and 'this-ness' are fundamental to our concept of substance.<ref>1029a</ref>
* Aristotle then describes his theory that ''essence'' is the criterion of substantiality.{{efn|Chapter 4-12}} The essence of something is what is included in a ''secundum se'' ('according to itself') account of a thing, i.e. which tells what a thing is by its very nature. You are not musical by your very nature. But you are a human by your very nature. Your essence is what is mentioned in the definition of you.
* Aristotle then considers, and dismisses, the idea that substance is the universal or the genus, criticizing the Platonic [[Theory of forms|theory of Ideas]].{{efn|Chapter 13-15}}{{clarify|date=January 2023}}
* Aristotle argues that if genus and [[Species (metaphysics)|species]] are individual things, then different species of the same genus contain the genus as individual thing, which leads to absurdities. Moreover, individuals are incapable of definition.
Finally, he concludes book Zeta by arguing that substance is really a cause.{{efn|Chapter 17}}{{sfn|Cohen|loc=11}}


Chapters 4–12 are devoted to Aristotle's own theory that ''[[essence]]'' is the criterion of substantiality. The essence of something is what is included in a ''secundum se'' ('according to itself') account of a thing, i.e. which tells what a thing is by its very nature. You are not musical by your very nature. But you are a human by your very nature. Your essence is what is mentioned in the definition of you.

Chapters 13–15 consider, and dismiss, the idea that substance is the universal or the genus, and are mostly an attack on the Platonic [[Theory of forms|theory of Ideas]]. Aristotle argues that if genus and species are individual things, then different species of the same genus contain the genus as individual thing, which leads to absurdities. Moreover, individuals are incapable of definition.

Chapter 17 takes an entirely fresh direction, which turns on the idea that substance is really a cause.

====VIII: Eta====
Book Eta consists of a summary of what has been said so far (i.e., in Book Zeta) about substance, and adds a few further details regarding difference and unity.
Book Eta consists of a summary of what has been said so far (i.e., in Book Zeta) about substance, and adds a few further details regarding difference and unity.


Book Theta sets out to define [[potentiality and actuality]]. Chapters 1–5 discuss potentiality,{{efn|δύναμις, ''dunamis''}} the potential of something to change: potentiality is "a principle of change in another thing or in the thing itself qua other."{{efn| 1046a9}} In chapter 6 Aristotle turns to actuality. We can only know actuality through observation or "analogy;" thus "as that which builds is to that which is capable of building, so is that which is awake to that which is asleep...or that which is separated from matter to matter itself".<ref>[https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.Met.9.1046a 1048b1–4]</ref> Actuality is the completed state of something that had the potential to be completed. The relationship between actuality and potentiality can be thought of as the relationship between form and matter, but with the added aspect of time. Actuality and potentiality are distinctions that occur over time ([[:wikt:diachronic|diachronic]]), whereas form and matter are distinctions that can be made at fixed points in time ([[:wikt:synchronic|synchronic]]).
====IX: Theta====
Theta sets out to define [[potentiality and actuality]]. Chapters 1–5 discuss potentiality. We learn that this term indicates the potential (δύναμις, ''dunamis'') of something to change: potentiality is "a principle of change in another thing or in the thing itself qua other" (1046a9). In chapter 6 Aristotle turns to actuality. We can only know actuality through observation or "analogy;" thus "as that which builds is to that which is capable of building, so is that which is awake to that which is asleep...or that which is separated from matter to matter itself" (1048b1–4). Actuality is the completed state of something that had the potential to be completed. The relationship between actuality and potentiality can be thought of as the relationship between form and matter, but with the added aspect of time. Actuality and potentiality are diachronic (across time) distinctions, whereas form and matter are synchronic (at one time) distinctions.


=== Books X–XIV: Iota, Kappa, Lambda, Mu, and Nu ===
=== Books X–XIV: Iota, Kappa, Lambda, Mu, and Nu ===

*'''Book X or Iota''': Discussion of unity, one and many, sameness and difference.
*'''Book X or Iota''': Discussion of unity, one and many, sameness and difference.
*'''Book XI or Kappa''': Briefer versions of other chapters and of parts of the ''Physics''.
*'''Book XI or Kappa''': Briefer versions of other chapters and of parts of the ''Physics''.
*'''Book XII or Lambda''': Further remarks on beings in general, first principles, and God or gods. This book includes Aristotle's famous description of the [[unmoved mover]], "the most divine of things observed by us", as "the thinking of thinking".
*'''Book XII or Lambda''': Further remarks on beings in general, first principles, and God or gods. This book includes Aristotle's famous description of the [[unmoved mover]], "the most divine of things observed by us", as "the thinking of thinking".
*'''Books XIII and XIV, or Mu and Nu''': Philosophy of mathematics, in particular how numbers exist.
*'''Books XIII and XIV, or Mu and Nu''': [[Philosophy of mathematics]], in particular how numbers exist.


== Legacy ==
== Translations and influence ==
The ''Metaphysics'' is considered to be one of the greatest philosophical works. Its influence on the [[Greek philosophy|Greeks]], the [[Islamic philosophy|Muslim philosophers]], [[Maimonides]] thence the [[Scholasticism|scholastic]] philosophers and even writers such as [[Dante]]<ref>S. Fazzo, ‘Sì come rota ch'igualmente è mossa’. Dalla Metafisica di Aristotele al Paradiso di Dante, Storie e linguaggi, Vol 4, N° 2 (2018)</ref> was immense.
The ''Metaphysics'' is considered to be one of the greatest philosophical works. Its influence on the [[Greek philosophy|Greeks]], the [[Islamic philosophy|Muslim philosophers]], [[Maimonides]] thence the [[Scholasticism|scholastic]] philosophers and even writers such as [[Dante]]<ref>S. Fazzo, 'Sì come rota ch'igualmente è mossa'. Dalla Metafisica di Aristotele al Paradiso di Dante, Storie e linguaggi, Vol 4, N° 2 (2018)</ref> was immense.


In the 3rd century, [[Alexander of Aphrodisias]] wrote a commentary on the first five books of the Metaphysics,<ref>Donald J. Zeyl, [[Daniel Devereux]], Phillip Mitsis, (1997), ''Encyclopedia of Classical Philosophy'', page 20.</ref> and a commentary transmitted under his name exists for the final nine, but modern scholars doubt that this part was written by him.<ref>William W. Fortenbaugh, R. W. Sharples, (2005), ''Theophrastus of Eresus, sources for his life, writings, thought and Influence'', page 22. BRILL</ref> [[Themistius]] wrote an epitome of the work, of which book 12 survives in a Hebrew translation.<ref name="catalogus">{{cite journal|last1=Todd|first1=Robert B.|title=Themistius|journal=[[Catalogus Translationum et Commentariorum]]|date=2003|volume=8|page=59|url=http://catalogustranslationum.org/PDFs/volume08/v08_themistius.pdf|access-date=25 August 2015}}</ref> The [[Neoplatonists]] [[Syrianus]] and [[Asclepius of Tralles]] also wrote commentaries on the work, where they attempted to synthesize Aristotle's doctrines with Neoplatonic cosmology.<ref>''Monad And Dyad As Cosmic Principles In Syrianus'', ''Soul And The Structure Of Being In Late Neoplatonism'', H.J. Blumenthal and A.C. Lloyd, [[Liverpool University Press]], 1982, pp. 1–10.</ref>
With the [[Fall of the Western Roman Empire|Fall of Rome]] in the latter half of the 5th century, knowledge of, and access to ''Metaphysics'' was lost to the non-Greek speaking world. The translation of ''Metaphysics'' into Arabic in Baghdad in the 9th century led to a discovery of Aristotle's work in the Arabic speaking world. These Arabic translations derived from early [[Syriac language|Syriac]] translations from the original Greek (see [[Medieval Philosophy]]). The flourishing of Arabic Aristotelian scholarship reached its peak with the work of [[Ibn Rushd]] (Latinized: Averroes), whose extensive writings on Aristotle's work led to his later designation as "The Commentator" by future generations of scholars. [[Maimonides]] wrote the [[The Guide for the Perplexed|Guide to the Perplexed]] in the 12th century, to demonstrate the compatibility of Aristotelian science with Biblical revelation.


Aristotle's works gained a reputation for complexity that is never more evident than with the ''Metaphysics'' — [[Avicenna]] said that he had read the ''Metaphysics'' of Aristotle forty times, but did not understand it until he also read [[al-Farabi]]'s ''Purposes of the Metaphysics of Aristotle''.{{blockquote|I read the Metaphysics [of Aristotle], but I could not comprehend its contents, and its author's object remained obscure to me, even when I had gone back and read it forty times and had got to the point where I had memorized it. In spite of this I could not understand it nor its object, and I despaired of myself and said, "This is a book which there is no way of understanding." But one day in the afternoon when I was at the booksellers' quarter a salesman approached with a book in his hand which he was calling out for sale. (...) So I bought it and, lo and behold, it was Abu Nasr al-Farabi's book{{efn|probably the Kitab al-huruf, ed. by Muhsin Mahdi as Alfarabi's Book of Letters (Beyrouth, 1969)}} on the objects of the Metaphysics. I returned home and was quick to read it, and in no time the objects of that book became clear to me because I had got to the point of having memorized it by heart.<ref>William E. Gohlam (ed.). The Life of Ibn Sina, Albany, State of New York University Press, 1974, pp. 33-35).</ref>}}
The [[Fourth Crusade]] (1202-1204) facilitated the discovery and delivery of many original Greek manuscripts back to the European centers of learning. Finally, after over 700 years of obscurity, the work could finally be studied in the original and properly translated into [[Latin]]. One of the first Latin translations was made by [[William of Moerbeke]]. William's translations are literal, and were intended faithfully to reflect the Greek word order and style. These formed the basis of the commentaries of [[Albert the Great]], [[Thomas Aquinas]] and [[Duns Scotus]]. They were also used by modern scholars for Greek editions, as William had access to Greek manuscripts that are now lost. [[Werner Jaeger]] lists William's translation in his edition of the Greek text in the Scriptorum Classicorum Bibliotheca Oxoniensis (Oxford 1962).<ref>Cited by Foster, in his translation of Aquinas' commentary on the ''De Anima'', Indiana 1994.</ref>


The flourishing of Arabic Aristotelian scholarship reached its peak with the work of [[Ibn Rushd]] (Latinized: Averroes), whose extensive writings on Aristotle's work led to his later designation as "The Commentator" by future generations of scholars. [[Maimonides]] wrote the [[The Guide for the Perplexed|Guide to the Perplexed]] in the 12th century, to demonstrate the compatibility of Aristotelian science with Biblical revelation.
In the 19th century, with the rise of [[textual criticism]], the ''Metaphysics'' was examined anew. Critics, noting the wide variety of topics and the seemingly illogical order of the books, concluded that it was actually a collection of shorter works thrown together haphazardly. In the 20th century two general editions have been produced by W. D. Ross (1924) and by W. Jaeger (1957). Based on a careful study of the content and of the cross-references within them, [[W. D. Ross]] concluded that books A, B, Γ, E, Z, H, Θ, M, N, and I "form a more or less continuous work", while the remaining books α, Δ, Κ and Λ were inserted into their present locations by later editors. However, Ross cautions that books A, B, Γ, E, Z, H, Θ, M, N, and I — with or without the insertion of the others — do not constitute "a complete work".<ref>''Aristotle's Metaphysics'' (1953), vol. 1, p. xxiii.</ref> [[Werner Jaeger]] further maintained that the different books were taken from different periods of Aristotle's life. [[Everyman's Library]], for their 1000th volume, published the ''Metaphysics'' in a rearranged order that was intended to make the work easier for readers.


The [[Fourth Crusade]] (1202–1204) facilitated the discovery and delivery of many original Greek manuscripts to [[Western Europe]]. [[William of Moerbeke]]'s translations of the work formed the basis of the commentaries on the ''Metaphysics'' by [[Albert the Great]], [[Thomas Aquinas]] and [[Duns Scotus]]. They were also used by modern scholars for Greek editions, as William had access to Greek manuscripts that are now lost. [[Werner Jaeger]] lists William's translation in his edition of the Greek text in the Scriptorum Classicorum Bibliotheca Oxoniensis (Oxford 1962).<ref>Cited by Foster, in his translation of Aquinas' commentary on the ''De Anima'', Indiana 1994.</ref>
Editing the ''Metaphysics'' has become an open issue in works and studies of the new millennium. New critical editions have been produced of the books Gamma (Myriam Hecquet, ''Aristote, Métaphysique Gamma'', Peeters 2008), Alpha (Oliver Primavesi, ''Aristotle Metaphysics Alpha'', OUP 2012), and Lambda (Silvia Fazzo, ''Il libro Lambda della Metafisica di Aristotel''e, "Elenchos", Bibliopolis 2012, and Stefan Alexandru, ''Aristotle's Metaphysics Lambda'', Philosophia Antiqua, Brill 2014) books. Differences from their more-familiar 20th Century critical editions (W. D. Ross, 1924, W. Jaeger 1957) mainly depend on the [[stemma codicum of Aristotle's Metaphysics]], of which different versions have been proposed since 1970 (Silvio Bernardinello, ''Eliminatio codicum della Metafisica di Aristotele'', Padua, Antenore, 1970), most remarkably by Dieter Harlfinger in 1979 ("Zur Überlieferungsgeschichte der Metaphysik", in Pierre Aubenque (ed.), ''Essais sur la Métaphysique d'Aristote'', Paris, Vrin, 1979).<ref>Silvia Fazzo, "Lo Stemma Codicum della Metafisica di Aristotele", ''Revue d'Histoire des Textes'', XII, 2017, 35-58.</ref>


== See also ==
== Textual criticism ==
In the 19th century, with the rise of [[textual criticism]], the ''Metaphysics'' was examined anew. Critics, noting the wide variety of topics and the seemingly illogical order of the books, concluded that it was actually a collection of shorter works thrown together haphazardly. In the 20th century two general editions have been produced by W. D. Ross (1924) and by W. Jaeger (1957). Based on a careful study of the content and of the cross-references within them, [[W. D. Ross]] concluded that books A, B, Γ, E, Z, H, Θ, M, N, and I "form a more or less continuous work", while the remaining books α, Δ, Κ and Λ were inserted into their present locations by later editors. However, Ross cautions that books A, B, Γ, E, Z, H, Θ, M, N, and I — with or without the insertion of the others — do not constitute "a complete work".<ref>''Aristotle's Metaphysics'' (1953), vol. 1, p. xxiii.</ref> [[Werner Jaeger]] further maintained that the different books were taken from different periods of Aristotle's life. [[Everyman's Library]], for their 1000th volume, published the ''Metaphysics'' in a rearranged order that was intended to make the work easier for readers.{{clarify|date=January 2023}}
*[[Stemma codicum of Aristotle's Metaphysics|Stemma codicum of Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'']]

*''[[Categories (Aristotle)|Categories]]''
Editing the ''Metaphysics'' has become an open issue in works and studies of the new millennium. New critical editions have been produced of books Gamma,<ref>Myriam Hecquet, ''Aristote, Métaphysique Gamma'', Peeters 2008</ref> Alpha,<ref>(Oliver Primavesi, ''Aristotle Metaphysics Alpha'', OUP 2012)</ref> and Lambda.<ref>(Silvia Fazzo, ''Il libro Lambda della Metafisica di Aristotel''e, "Elenchos", Bibliopolis 2012, and Stefan Alexandru, ''Aristotle's Metaphysics Lambda'', Philosophia Antiqua, Brill 2014)</ref> Differences from the more-familiar 20th Century critical editions of Ross and Jaeger mainly depend on the [[stemma codicum of Aristotle's Metaphysics]], of which different versions have been proposed since 1970.<ref>(Silvio Bernardinello, ''Eliminatio codicum della Metafisica di Aristotele'', Padua, Antenore, 1970)</ref><ref>(Dieter Harlfinger in 1979"Zur Überlieferungsgeschichte der Metaphysik", in Pierre Aubenque (ed.), ''Essais sur la Métaphysique d'Aristote'', Paris, Vrin, 1979)</ref><ref>Silvia Fazzo, "Lo Stemma Codicum della Metafisica di Aristotele", ''Revue d'Histoire des Textes'', XII, 2017, 35-58.</ref>
*''[[On Generation and Corruption]]''

== Editions and translations ==
* Greek text with commentary: ''Aristotle's Metaphysics''. [[W. D. Ross]]. 2 Vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924. Reprinted in 1953 with corrections.
* Greek text: ''Aristotelis Metaphysica.'' Ed. [[Werner Jaeger]]. Oxford Classical Texts. Oxford University Press, 1957. {{ISBN|978-0-19-814513-4}}.
* Greek text with English: ''Metaphysics.'' Trans. Hugh Tredennick. 2 vols. Loeb Classical Library 271, 287. Harvard U. Press, 1933–35. {{ISBN|0-674-99299-7}}, {{ISBN|0-674-99317-9}}.
* ''Aristotle's Metaphysics.'' Trans. Hippocrates Gorgias Apostle. Bloomington: Indiana U. Press, 1966.
* {{cite book | translator-first1 = Joe | translator-last1 = Sachs | title = Aristotle's Metaphysics | edition = 2nd | location = Santa Fe, N.M.| publisher = Green Lion Press| year = 2002 | isbn =1-888009-03-9}}

=== Ancient and medieval commentaries ===
* {{cite book | translator-first1 = Thomas | translator-last1 = Aquinas | translator-first2 = John P. | translator-last2 = Rowan | url = https://dhspriory.org/thomas/Metaphysics.htm | title = Commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics | language = el, la, en | website = Dominican House of Studies in Washington, D.C. | publisher = [[Regnery Publishing|Henry Regnery Company]] (Library of Living Catholic Thought) | location = Chicago | year = 1961 | volume = 3 | edition = 1st | oclc = 312731 <!-- DUPLICATE url= | url = https://archive.org/details/AquinasCommentaryOnTheMetaphysics/page/n21/ --> | others = William of Moerbeke | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20111028095410/https://dhspriory.org/thomas/Metaphysics1.htm | archive-date = October 28, 2011 | url-status = live}} (rpt. Notre Dame, Ind.: Dumb Ox, 1995).


==Notes==
==Notes==
{{notelist}}
{{notelist}}

==Citations==
{{reflist}}
{{reflist}}


==References==
== References ==
* ''Wolfgang Class: Aristotle's Metaphysics, A Philological Commentary'':
* Greek text with commentary: ''Aristotle's Metaphysics''. [[W. D. Ross]]. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924. Reprinted 1953 with corrections.
* Greek text: ''Aristotelis Metaphysica.'' Ed. [[Werner Jaeger]]. Oxford Classical Texts. Oxford University Press, 1957. {{ISBN|978-0-19-814513-4}}.
* Greek text with English: ''Metaphysics.'' Trans. Hugh Tredennick. 2 vols. Loeb Classical Library 271, 287. Harvard U. Press, 1933–35. {{ISBN|0-674-99299-7}}, {{ISBN|0-674-99317-9}}.
* ''Aristotle's Metaphysics.'' Trans. Hippocrates Gorgias Apostle. Bloomington: Indiana U. Press, 1966.
* {{cite book | translator-first1 = Joe | translator-last1 = Sachs | title = Aristotle's Metaphysics | edition = 2nd | location = Santa Fe, N.M.| publisher = Green Lion Press| year = 2002 | isbn =1-888009-03-9}}.
* {{cite book|translator-first=Hugh |translator-last=Lawson-Tancred |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics |publisher=Penguin |year=1998 |isbn=0140446192}}
* [[Frederick Copleston|Copleston, Frederick, S.J.]] ''A History of Philosophy: Volume I Greece and Rome'' (Parts I and II) New York: Image Books, 1962.
* Wolfgang Class: Aristotle's Metaphysics, A Philological Commentary:
** Volume I: Textual Criticism, {{ISBN|978-3-9815841-2-7}}, Saldenburg 2014;
** Volume I: Textual Criticism, {{ISBN|978-3-9815841-2-7}}, Saldenburg 2014;
** Volume II: The Composition of the Metaphysics, {{ISBN|978-3-9815841-3-4}}, Saldenburg 2015;
** Volume II: The Composition of the Metaphysics, {{ISBN|978-3-9815841-3-4}}, Saldenburg 2015;
** Volume III: Sources and Parallels, {{ISBN|978-3-9815841-6-5}}, Saldenburg 2017;
** Volume III: Sources and Parallels, {{ISBN|978-3-9815841-6-5}}, Saldenburg 2017;
** Volume IV: Reception and Criticism, {{ISBN|978-3-9820267-0-1}}, Saldenburg 2018.
** Volume IV: Reception and Criticism, {{ISBN|978-3-9820267-0-1}}, Saldenburg 2018.
* [[Frederick Copleston|Copleston, Frederick, S.J.]] ''A History of Philosophy: Volume I Greece and Rome'' (Parts I and II) New York: Image Books, 1962.
* {{cite book | translator-first1 = Thomas | translator-last1 = Aquinas | translator-first2 = John P. | translator-last2 = Rowan | url = https://dhspriory.org/thomas/Metaphysics.htm | title = Commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics | language = el, la, en | website = Dominican House of Studies in Washington, D.C. | publisher = [[Regnery Publishing|Henry Regnery Company]] (Library of Living Catholic Thought) | location = Chicago | year = 1961 | volume = 3 | edition = 1st | oclc = 312731 | via = [https://archive.org/details/AquinasCommentaryOnTheMetaphysics/page/n21/ archive.org] | others = William of Moerbeke | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20111028095410/https://dhspriory.org/thomas/Metaphysics1.htm | archive-date = October 28, 2011 | url-status = live}} (rpt. Notre Dame, Ind.: Dumb Ox, 1995).
* {{cite book|translator-first=Hugh |translator-last=Lawson-Tancred |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics |publisher=Penguin |year=1998 |isbn=0140446192}}


== Further reading ==
== Further reading ==
* [[Ackrill, J. L]]., 1963, ''Aristotle: Categories and De Interpretatione'', Oxford: [[Clarendon Press]].

* Ackrill, J. L., 1963, ''Aristotle: Categories and De Interpretatione'', Oxford: Clarendon Press.
* Alexandrou, S., 2014, ''Aristotle's'' Metaphysics ''Lambda: Annotated Critical Edition'', Leiden: [[Brill Publishers|Brill]].
* Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (ed.), 2009, ''A Companion to Aristotle'', Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
* –––, 1965, “Aristotle’s Distinction between ''Energeia'' and ''Kinesis'',” in Bambrough 1965, pp. 121–141.
* Elders, L., 1972, ''Aristotle's Theology: A Commentary on Book Λ of the'' Metaphysics, Assen: Van Gorcum.
* –––, 1972, “Aristotle’s Definitions of ''Psyche'',” ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', 73: 119–133.
* Gerson, Lloyd P. (ed.) and [[Joseph Owens (Redemptorist)|Joseph Owens]], 2007, ''Aristotle's Gradations of Being in Metaphysics E-Z'', South Bend: St Augustine's Press.
* [[Gill, Mary Louise]], 1989, ''Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity'', Princeton: Princeton University Press.
<!---
* –––, 1965, “Aristotle's Distinction between ''Energeia'' and ''Kinesis'',” in Bambrough 1965, pp. 121–141.
* –––, 1972, “Aristotle's Definitions of ''Psyche'',” ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', 73: 119–133.
* Addis, L., 1972, “Aristotle and the Independence of Substances,” ''Philosophy and Phenomenological Research'', 54: 699–708.
* Addis, L., 1972, “Aristotle and the Independence of Substances,” ''Philosophy and Phenomenological Research'', 54: 699–708.
* Ainsworth, Thomas, 2018, “Priority in Being in Aristotle,” ''Philosophy Compass'', 13: 1–10.
* Ainsworth, Thomas, 2018, “Priority in Being in Aristotle,” ''Philosophy Compass'', 13: 1–10.
* Albritton, Rogers, 1957, “Forms of Particular Substances in Aristotle’s ''Metaphysics'',” ''Journal of Philosophy'', 54: 699–707.
* Albritton, Rogers, 1957, “Forms of Particular Substances in Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'',” ''Journal of Philosophy'', 54: 699–707.
* Allen, R. E., 1969, “Individual Properties in Aristotle's ''Categories'',” ''Phronesis'', 14: 31–39.
* Alexandrou, S., 2014, ''Aristotle’s'' Metaphysics ''Lambda: Annotated Critical Edition'', Leiden: Brill.
* Allen, R. E., 1969, “Individual Properties in Aristotle’s ''Categories'',” ''Phronesis'', 14: 31–39.
* Anagnostopoulos, Andreas, 2011, “Senses of 'Dunamis' and the Structure of Aristotle's 'Metaphysics' Theta,” ''Phronesis'', 56: 388–425.
* Angioni, Lucas, 2014, “Definition and Essence in Aristotle's 'Metaphysics' vii 4,” ''Ancient Philosophy'', 34: 75–100.
* Anagnostopoulos, Andreas, 2011, “Senses of ‘Dunamis’ and the Structure of Aristotle’s ‘Metaphysics’ Theta,” ''Phronesis'', 56: 388–425.
* Annas, J., 1974, “Individuals in Aristotle's ''Categories'': Two Queries,” ''Phronesis'', 19: 146–152.
* Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (ed.), 2009, ''A Companion to Aristotle'', Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
* Cohen, Sheldon M., 1981, “Proper Differentiae, the Unity of Definition, and Aristotle's Essentialism,” ''The New Scholasticism'', 55: 229–240.
* Angioni, Lucas, 2014, “Definition and Essence in Aristotle’s ‘Metaphysics’ vii 4,” ''Ancient Philosophy'', 34: 75–100.
* Cohen, Sheldon M., 1984, “Aristotle's Doctrine of the Material Substrate,” ''Philosophical Review'', 93: 171–194.
* Annas, J., 1974, “Individuals in Aristotle’s ''Categories'': Two Queries,” ''Phronesis'', 19: 146–152.
* Engmann, J., 1973, “Aristotle's Distinction Between Substance and Universal,” ''Phronesis'', 18: 139–155.
* Cohen, Sheldon M., 1981, “Proper Differentiae, the Unity of Definition, and Aristotle’s Essentialism,” ''The New Scholasticism'', 55: 229–240.
* Green, Jerry, 2014, “The Underlying Argument of Aristotle's 'Metaphysics Ζ.3',” ''Phronesis'', 59: 321–342.
* Cohen, Sheldon M., 1984, “Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Material Substrate,” ''Philosophical Review'', 93: 171–194.
* Elders, L., 1972, ''Aristotle’s Theology: A Commentary on Book Λ of the'' Metaphysics, Assen: Van Gorcum.
* Engmann, J., 1973, “Aristotle’s Distinction Between Substance and Universal,” ''Phronesis'', 18: 139–155.
* Gerson, Lloyd P. (ed.) and Joseph Owens, 2007, ''Aristotle’s Gradations of being in Metaphysics E-Z'', South Bend: St Augustine’s Press.
* Gill, Mary Louise, 1989, ''Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity'', Princeton: Princeton University Press.
* Green, Jerry, 2014, “The Underlying Argument of Aristotle’s ‘Metaphysics Ζ.3’,” ''Phronesis'', 59: 321–342.
* Grene, M., 1974, “Is Genus to Species as Matter to Form? Aristotle and Taxonomy,” ''Synthèse'', 28: 51–69.
* Grene, M., 1974, “Is Genus to Species as Matter to Form? Aristotle and Taxonomy,” ''Synthèse'', 28: 51–69.
* Grice, H. P., 1988, “Aristotle on the Multiplicity of Being,” ''Pacific Philosophical Quarterly'', 69: 175–200.
* Grice, H. P., 1988, “Aristotle on the Multiplicity of Being,” ''Pacific Philosophical Quarterly'', 69: 175–200.
Line 110: Line 107:
* Makin, Stephen, 2004, “What Does Aristotle Mean by Priority in Substance?” ''Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'', 24: 209–238.
* Makin, Stephen, 2004, “What Does Aristotle Mean by Priority in Substance?” ''Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'', 24: 209–238.
* Malcolm, John, 1993, “On the Endangered Species of the ''Metaphysics'',” ''Ancient Philosophy'', 13: 79–93.
* Malcolm, John, 1993, “On the Endangered Species of the ''Metaphysics'',” ''Ancient Philosophy'', 13: 79–93.
* Modrak, Deborah K., 1979, “Forms, Types, and Tokens in Aristotle’s ''Metaphysics'',” ''Journal of the History of Philosophy'', 17: 371–381.
* Modrak, Deborah K., 1979, “Forms, Types, and Tokens in Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'',” ''Journal of the History of Philosophy'', 17: 371–381.
* Sharma, R. 2005. “‘What is Aristotle’s ‘Third Man’ Argument against the Forms?” ''Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'' 28: 123–60.
* Sharma, R. 2005. “'What is Aristotle's 'Third Man' Argument against the Forms?” ''Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'' 28: 123–60.
* Wheeler, S., 1977, “The Theory of Matter from ''Metaphysics'' Ζ, Η, Θ,” ''International Studies in Philosophy'', 13–22.
* Wheeler, S., 1977, “The Theory of Matter from ''Metaphysics'' Ζ, Η, Θ,” ''International Studies in Philosophy'', 13–22.
* White, Nicholas P., 1972, “The Origins of Aristotle’s Essentialism,” ''Review of Metaphysics'', 26: 57–85.
* White, Nicholas P., 1972, “The Origins of Aristotle's Essentialism,” ''Review of Metaphysics'', 26: 57–85.
* Yu, Jiyuan, 1997, “Two Conceptions of Hylomorphism in Metaphysics ΖΗΘ,” ''Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'', 15: 119–45.
* Yu, Jiyuan, 1997, “Two Conceptions of Hylomorphism in Metaphysics ΖΗΘ,” ''Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'', 15: 119–45.--->


==External links==
==External links==
Line 134: Line 131:
[[Category:Metaphysics literature]]
[[Category:Metaphysics literature]]
[[Category:Works by Aristotle]]
[[Category:Works by Aristotle]]
[[Category:Philosophy of Aristotle]]

Latest revision as of 05:38, 30 November 2024

Metaphysics (Greek: τὰ μετὰ τὰ φυσικά, "those after the physics"; Latin: Metaphysica[1]) is one of the principal works of Aristotle, in which he develops the doctrine that he calls First Philosophy.[a] The work is a compilation of various texts treating abstract subjects, notably substance theory, different kinds of causation, form and matter, the existence of mathematical objects and the cosmos, which together constitute much of the branch of philosophy later known as metaphysics.

Date, style and composition

[edit]

Many of Aristotle's works are extremely compressed, and many scholars believe that in their current form, they are likely lecture notes.[2] Subsequent to the arrangement of Aristotle's works by Andronicus of Rhodes in the first century BC, a number of his treatises were referred to as the writings "after ("meta") the Physics"[b], the origin of the current title for the collection Metaphysics. Some[who?] have interpreted the expression "meta" to imply that the subject of the work goes "beyond" that of Aristotle's Physics or that it is metatheoretical in relation to the Physics. But others[who?] believe that "meta" referred simply to the work's place in the canonical arrangement of Aristotle's writings, which is at least as old as Andronicus of Rhodes or even Hermippus of Smyrna.[3] In other surviving works of Aristotle, the metaphysical treatises are referred to as "the [writings] concerning first philosophy";[c] which was the term Aristotle used for metaphysics.[d]

It is notoriously difficult to specify the date at which Aristotle wrote these treatises as a whole or even individually, especially because the Metaphysics is, in Jonathan Barnes' words, "a farrago, a hotch-potch", and more generally because of the difficulty of dating any of Aristotle's writings.[5] The order in which the books were written is not known; their arrangement is due to later editors. In the manuscripts, books are referred to by Greek letters. For many scholars, it is customary to refer to the books by their letter names. Book 1 is called Alpha (Α); 2, little alpha (α);[e] 3, Beta (Β); 4, Gamma (Γ); 5, Delta (Δ); 6, Epsilon (Ε); 7, Zeta (Ζ); 8, Eta (Η); 9, Theta (Θ); 10, Iota (Ι); 11, Kappa (Κ); 12, Lambda (Λ); 13, Mu (Μ); 14, Nu (Ν).

Outline

[edit]
Wisdom personified as a deity in the Library of Celsus in Ephesus. Aristotle discusses the nature of wisdom, or first philosophy, which he defines as the study of first principles and causes.

Books I–VI: Alpha, little Alpha, Beta, Gamma, Delta and Epsilon

[edit]
  • Book I or Alpha begins by discussing the nature of knowledge and compares knowledge gained from the senses and from memory, arguing that knowledge is acquired from memory through experience.[6] It then defines "wisdom" (sophia) as a knowledge of the first principles (arche) or causes of things. Because those who are wise understand the first principles and causes, they know the why of things, unlike those who only know that things are a certain way based on their memory and sensations. The wise are able to teach because they know the why of things, and so they are better fitted to command, rather than to obey. He then surveys the first principles and causes of previous philosophers, starting with the material monists of the Ionian school and continuing up until Plato.
  • Book II or "little alpha": Book II addresses a possible objection to the account of how we understand first principles and thus acquire wisdom, that attempting to discover the first principle would lead to an infinite series of causes. It argues in response that the idea of an infinite causal series is absurd, and argues that only things that are created or destroyed require a cause, and that thus there must be a primary cause that is eternal, an idea he develops later in Book Lambda.
  • Book III or Beta lists the main problems or puzzles (aporia) of philosophy.[7]
  • Book IV or Gamma: Chapters 2 and 3 argue for its status as a subject in its own right. The rest is a defense of (a) what we now call the principle of contradiction, the principle that it is not possible for the same proposition to be (the case) and not to be (the case), and (b) what we now call the principle of excluded middle: tertium non datur — there cannot be an intermediary between contradictory statements.
  • Book V or Delta ("philosophical lexicon") is a list of definitions of about thirty key terms such as cause, nature, one, and many.
  • Book VI or Epsilon has two main concerns. The first concern is the hierarchy of the sciences: productive, practical or theoretical. Aristotle considers theoretical sciences superior because they study beings for their own sake—for example, Physics studies beings that can be moved[f]—and do not have a target (τέλος telos, "end, goal"; τέλειος, "complete, perfect") beyond themselves. He argues that the study of being qua being, or First Philosophy, is superior to all the other theoretical sciences because it is concerned with the ultimate causes of all reality, not just the secondary causes of a part of reality. The second concern of Epsilon is the study of "accidents" (κατὰ συμβεβηκός), those attributes that do not depend on (τέχνη) or exist by necessity, which Aristotle believes do not deserve to be studied as a science.
Book 7 of the Metaphysics: From a manuscript of William of Moerbeke's translation

Books VII–IX: Zeta, Eta, and Theta

[edit]

Books Zeta, Eta, and Theta are generally considered the core of the Metaphysics.[citation needed] Book Zeta (VII) begins by stating that "being" has several senses, the purpose of philosophy is to understand the primary kind of being, called substance (ousia) and determine what substances there are, a concept that Aristotle develops in the Categories.[8] Zeta goes on to consider four candidates for substance: (i) the 'essence' or 'what it is to be' of a thing (ii) the universal, (iii) the genus to which a substance belongs and (iv) the material substrate that underlies all the properties of a thing.

  • He dismisses the idea that matter can be substance, for if we eliminate everything that is a property from what can have the property, such as matter and the shape, we are left with something that has no properties at all. Such 'ultimate matter' cannot be substance. Separability and 'this-ness' are fundamental to our concept of substance.[9]
  • Aristotle then describes his theory that essence is the criterion of substantiality.[g] The essence of something is what is included in a secundum se ('according to itself') account of a thing, i.e. which tells what a thing is by its very nature. You are not musical by your very nature. But you are a human by your very nature. Your essence is what is mentioned in the definition of you.
  • Aristotle then considers, and dismisses, the idea that substance is the universal or the genus, criticizing the Platonic theory of Ideas.[h][clarification needed]
  • Aristotle argues that if genus and species are individual things, then different species of the same genus contain the genus as individual thing, which leads to absurdities. Moreover, individuals are incapable of definition.

Finally, he concludes book Zeta by arguing that substance is really a cause.[i][10]

Book Eta consists of a summary of what has been said so far (i.e., in Book Zeta) about substance, and adds a few further details regarding difference and unity.

Book Theta sets out to define potentiality and actuality. Chapters 1–5 discuss potentiality,[j] the potential of something to change: potentiality is "a principle of change in another thing or in the thing itself qua other."[k] In chapter 6 Aristotle turns to actuality. We can only know actuality through observation or "analogy;" thus "as that which builds is to that which is capable of building, so is that which is awake to that which is asleep...or that which is separated from matter to matter itself".[11] Actuality is the completed state of something that had the potential to be completed. The relationship between actuality and potentiality can be thought of as the relationship between form and matter, but with the added aspect of time. Actuality and potentiality are distinctions that occur over time (diachronic), whereas form and matter are distinctions that can be made at fixed points in time (synchronic).

Books X–XIV: Iota, Kappa, Lambda, Mu, and Nu

[edit]
  • Book X or Iota: Discussion of unity, one and many, sameness and difference.
  • Book XI or Kappa: Briefer versions of other chapters and of parts of the Physics.
  • Book XII or Lambda: Further remarks on beings in general, first principles, and God or gods. This book includes Aristotle's famous description of the unmoved mover, "the most divine of things observed by us", as "the thinking of thinking".
  • Books XIII and XIV, or Mu and Nu: Philosophy of mathematics, in particular how numbers exist.

Legacy

[edit]

The Metaphysics is considered to be one of the greatest philosophical works. Its influence on the Greeks, the Muslim philosophers, Maimonides thence the scholastic philosophers and even writers such as Dante[12] was immense.

In the 3rd century, Alexander of Aphrodisias wrote a commentary on the first five books of the Metaphysics,[13] and a commentary transmitted under his name exists for the final nine, but modern scholars doubt that this part was written by him.[14] Themistius wrote an epitome of the work, of which book 12 survives in a Hebrew translation.[15] The Neoplatonists Syrianus and Asclepius of Tralles also wrote commentaries on the work, where they attempted to synthesize Aristotle's doctrines with Neoplatonic cosmology.[16]

Aristotle's works gained a reputation for complexity that is never more evident than with the MetaphysicsAvicenna said that he had read the Metaphysics of Aristotle forty times, but did not understand it until he also read al-Farabi's Purposes of the Metaphysics of Aristotle.

I read the Metaphysics [of Aristotle], but I could not comprehend its contents, and its author's object remained obscure to me, even when I had gone back and read it forty times and had got to the point where I had memorized it. In spite of this I could not understand it nor its object, and I despaired of myself and said, "This is a book which there is no way of understanding." But one day in the afternoon when I was at the booksellers' quarter a salesman approached with a book in his hand which he was calling out for sale. (...) So I bought it and, lo and behold, it was Abu Nasr al-Farabi's book[l] on the objects of the Metaphysics. I returned home and was quick to read it, and in no time the objects of that book became clear to me because I had got to the point of having memorized it by heart.[17]

The flourishing of Arabic Aristotelian scholarship reached its peak with the work of Ibn Rushd (Latinized: Averroes), whose extensive writings on Aristotle's work led to his later designation as "The Commentator" by future generations of scholars. Maimonides wrote the Guide to the Perplexed in the 12th century, to demonstrate the compatibility of Aristotelian science with Biblical revelation.

The Fourth Crusade (1202–1204) facilitated the discovery and delivery of many original Greek manuscripts to Western Europe. William of Moerbeke's translations of the work formed the basis of the commentaries on the Metaphysics by Albert the Great, Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus. They were also used by modern scholars for Greek editions, as William had access to Greek manuscripts that are now lost. Werner Jaeger lists William's translation in his edition of the Greek text in the Scriptorum Classicorum Bibliotheca Oxoniensis (Oxford 1962).[18]

Textual criticism

[edit]

In the 19th century, with the rise of textual criticism, the Metaphysics was examined anew. Critics, noting the wide variety of topics and the seemingly illogical order of the books, concluded that it was actually a collection of shorter works thrown together haphazardly. In the 20th century two general editions have been produced by W. D. Ross (1924) and by W. Jaeger (1957). Based on a careful study of the content and of the cross-references within them, W. D. Ross concluded that books A, B, Γ, E, Z, H, Θ, M, N, and I "form a more or less continuous work", while the remaining books α, Δ, Κ and Λ were inserted into their present locations by later editors. However, Ross cautions that books A, B, Γ, E, Z, H, Θ, M, N, and I — with or without the insertion of the others — do not constitute "a complete work".[19] Werner Jaeger further maintained that the different books were taken from different periods of Aristotle's life. Everyman's Library, for their 1000th volume, published the Metaphysics in a rearranged order that was intended to make the work easier for readers.[clarification needed]

Editing the Metaphysics has become an open issue in works and studies of the new millennium. New critical editions have been produced of books Gamma,[20] Alpha,[21] and Lambda.[22] Differences from the more-familiar 20th Century critical editions of Ross and Jaeger mainly depend on the stemma codicum of Aristotle's Metaphysics, of which different versions have been proposed since 1970.[23][24][25]

Editions and translations

[edit]
  • Greek text with commentary: Aristotle's Metaphysics. W. D. Ross. 2 Vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924. Reprinted in 1953 with corrections.
  • Greek text: Aristotelis Metaphysica. Ed. Werner Jaeger. Oxford Classical Texts. Oxford University Press, 1957. ISBN 978-0-19-814513-4.
  • Greek text with English: Metaphysics. Trans. Hugh Tredennick. 2 vols. Loeb Classical Library 271, 287. Harvard U. Press, 1933–35. ISBN 0-674-99299-7, ISBN 0-674-99317-9.
  • Aristotle's Metaphysics. Trans. Hippocrates Gorgias Apostle. Bloomington: Indiana U. Press, 1966.
  • Aristotle's Metaphysics. Translated by Sachs, Joe (2nd ed.). Santa Fe, N.M.: Green Lion Press. 2002. ISBN 1-888009-03-9.

Ancient and medieval commentaries

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ sometimes referred to as Wisdom, sometimes as , and sometimes as Theology
  2. ^ μετὰ τὰ φυσικά
  3. ^ τὰ περὶ τῆς πρώτης φιλοσοφίας e.g., in Movement of Animals 700b9
  4. ^ He called the study of nature or natural philosophy "second philosophy"[4]
  5. ^ The second book was given the title "little alpha," apparently because it appears to have nothing to do with the other books (and, very early, it was supposed not to have been written by Aristotle) or, although this is less likely,[citation needed] because of its shortness. This, then, disrupts the correspondence of letters to numbers, as book 2 is little alpha, book 3 is beta, and so on.
  6. ^ 1025b27
  7. ^ Chapter 4-12
  8. ^ Chapter 13-15
  9. ^ Chapter 17
  10. ^ δύναμις, dunamis
  11. ^ 1046a9
  12. ^ probably the Kitab al-huruf, ed. by Muhsin Mahdi as Alfarabi's Book of Letters (Beyrouth, 1969)

Citations

[edit]
  1. ^ Aristotelis Opera by August Immanuel Bekker (1837).
  2. ^ E.g. J.A.K. Thomson, The Ethics of Aristotle, (Penguin, 1953) p. 13 and E. Barker The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (Dover, 1959) p. 65.
  3. ^ W. D. Ross, Aristotle's Metaphysics (1953), vol. 1, p. xxxii.
  4. ^ Metaphysics 1037a15
  5. ^ Jonathan Barnes, "Life and Work" in The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle (1995), pp. 18-22."Farrago": Barnes, "Metaphysics" in The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, p. 68.
  6. ^ 981a
  7. ^ Robert Maynard Hutchins (1952), Great Books of the Western World 8: Aristotle, p. 495.
  8. ^ Cohen, 5.
  9. ^ 1029a
  10. ^ Cohen, 11.
  11. ^ 1048b1–4
  12. ^ S. Fazzo, 'Sì come rota ch'igualmente è mossa'. Dalla Metafisica di Aristotele al Paradiso di Dante, Storie e linguaggi, Vol 4, N° 2 (2018)
  13. ^ Donald J. Zeyl, Daniel Devereux, Phillip Mitsis, (1997), Encyclopedia of Classical Philosophy, page 20.
  14. ^ William W. Fortenbaugh, R. W. Sharples, (2005), Theophrastus of Eresus, sources for his life, writings, thought and Influence, page 22. BRILL
  15. ^ Todd, Robert B. (2003). "Themistius" (PDF). Catalogus Translationum et Commentariorum. 8: 59. Retrieved 25 August 2015.
  16. ^ Monad And Dyad As Cosmic Principles In Syrianus, Soul And The Structure Of Being In Late Neoplatonism, H.J. Blumenthal and A.C. Lloyd, Liverpool University Press, 1982, pp. 1–10.
  17. ^ William E. Gohlam (ed.). The Life of Ibn Sina, Albany, State of New York University Press, 1974, pp. 33-35).
  18. ^ Cited by Foster, in his translation of Aquinas' commentary on the De Anima, Indiana 1994.
  19. ^ Aristotle's Metaphysics (1953), vol. 1, p. xxiii.
  20. ^ Myriam Hecquet, Aristote, Métaphysique Gamma, Peeters 2008
  21. ^ (Oliver Primavesi, Aristotle Metaphysics Alpha, OUP 2012)
  22. ^ (Silvia Fazzo, Il libro Lambda della Metafisica di Aristotele, "Elenchos", Bibliopolis 2012, and Stefan Alexandru, Aristotle's Metaphysics Lambda, Philosophia Antiqua, Brill 2014)
  23. ^ (Silvio Bernardinello, Eliminatio codicum della Metafisica di Aristotele, Padua, Antenore, 1970)
  24. ^ (Dieter Harlfinger in 1979"Zur Überlieferungsgeschichte der Metaphysik", in Pierre Aubenque (ed.), Essais sur la Métaphysique d'Aristote, Paris, Vrin, 1979)
  25. ^ Silvia Fazzo, "Lo Stemma Codicum della Metafisica di Aristotele", Revue d'Histoire des Textes, XII, 2017, 35-58.

References

[edit]

Further reading

[edit]
  • Ackrill, J. L., 1963, Aristotle: Categories and De Interpretatione, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Alexandrou, S., 2014, Aristotle's Metaphysics Lambda: Annotated Critical Edition, Leiden: Brill.
  • Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (ed.), 2009, A Companion to Aristotle, Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Elders, L., 1972, Aristotle's Theology: A Commentary on Book Λ of the Metaphysics, Assen: Van Gorcum.
  • Gerson, Lloyd P. (ed.) and Joseph Owens, 2007, Aristotle's Gradations of Being in Metaphysics E-Z, South Bend: St Augustine's Press.
  • Gill, Mary Louise, 1989, Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
[edit]