Substructural logic: Difference between revisions
m clean up, replaced: ” → " (2), “ → " (2) using AWB |
No edit summary |
||
(20 intermediate revisions by 17 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{no footnotes|date=June 2016 }} |
|||
⚫ | In [[logic]], a '''substructural logic''' is a logic lacking one of the usual structural |
||
⚫ | In [[logic]], a '''substructural logic''' is a logic lacking one of the usual [[structural rule]]s (e.g. of [[classical logic|classical]] and [[intuitionistic logic]]), such as [[monotonicity of entailment|weakening]], [[idempotency of entailment|contraction]], exchange or associativity. Two of the more significant substructural logics are [[relevant logic|relevance logic]] and [[linear logic]]. |
||
==Examples== |
|||
In a [[sequent calculus]], one writes each line of a proof as |
In a [[sequent calculus]], one writes each line of a proof as |
||
:<math>\Gamma\vdash\Sigma</math>. |
:<math>\Gamma\vdash\Sigma</math>. |
||
Here the structural rules are rules for [[rewriting]] the [[Sides of an equation|LHS]] |
Here the structural rules are rules for [[rewriting]] the [[Sides of an equation|LHS]] of the sequent, denoted Γ, initially conceived of as a string (sequence) <!-- CS link for string was wrong --> of propositions. The standard interpretation of this string is as [[Logical conjunction|conjunction]]: we expect to read |
||
:<math>\mathcal A,\mathcal B \vdash\mathcal C</math> |
:<math>\mathcal A,\mathcal B \vdash\mathcal C</math> |
||
Line 15: | Line 18: | ||
Here we are taking the [[Sides of an equation|RHS]] Σ to be a single proposition ''C'' (which is the [[intuitionistic]] style of sequent); but everything applies equally to the general case, since all the manipulations are taking place to the left of the [[Turnstile (symbol)|turnstile symbol]] <math>\vdash</math>. |
Here we are taking the [[Sides of an equation|RHS]] Σ to be a single proposition ''C'' (which is the [[intuitionistic]] style of sequent); but everything applies equally to the general case, since all the manipulations are taking place to the left of the [[Turnstile (symbol)|turnstile symbol]] <math>\vdash</math>. |
||
Since conjunction is a [[commutative]] and [[associative]] operation, the formal setting-up of sequent theory normally includes '''structural rules''' for rewriting the sequent Γ |
Since conjunction is a [[commutative]] and [[associative]] operation, the formal setting-up of sequent theory normally includes '''structural rules''' for rewriting the sequent Γ accordingly—for example for deducing |
||
:<math>\mathcal B,\mathcal A\vdash\mathcal C</math> |
:<math>\mathcal B,\mathcal A\vdash\mathcal C</math> |
||
Line 23: | Line 26: | ||
:<math>\mathcal A,\mathcal B\vdash\mathcal C</math>. |
:<math>\mathcal A,\mathcal B\vdash\mathcal C</math>. |
||
There are further structural rules corresponding to the ''[[idempotent]]'' and ''[[monotonic]]'' properties of conjunction: from |
There are further structural rules corresponding to the ''[[idempotent]]'' and ''[[Monotonicity of entailment|monotonic]]'' properties of conjunction: from |
||
:<math> \Gamma,\mathcal A,\mathcal A,\Delta\vdash\mathcal C</math> |
:<math> \Gamma,\mathcal A,\mathcal A,\Delta\vdash\mathcal C</math> |
||
Line 41: | Line 44: | ||
[[Linear logic]], in which duplicated hypotheses 'count' differently from single occurrences, leaves out both of these rules, while [[relevant logic|relevant (or relevance) logic]]s merely leaves out the latter rule, on the ground that ''B'' is clearly irrelevant to the conclusion. |
[[Linear logic]], in which duplicated hypotheses 'count' differently from single occurrences, leaves out both of these rules, while [[relevant logic|relevant (or relevance) logic]]s merely leaves out the latter rule, on the ground that ''B'' is clearly irrelevant to the conclusion. |
||
The above are basic examples of structural rules. It is not that these rules are contentious, when applied in conventional propositional calculus. They occur naturally in proof theory, and were first noticed there (before receiving a name). |
|||
== Premise composition == |
== Premise composition == |
||
There are numerous ways to compose premises (and in the multiple |
There are numerous ways to compose premises (and in the multiple-conclusion case, conclusions as well). One way is to collect them into a set. But since e.g. {a,a} = {a} we have contraction for free if premises are sets. We also have associativity and permutation (or commutativity) for free as well, among other properties. In substructural logics, typically premises are not composed into sets, but rather they are composed into more fine-grained structures, such as trees or multisets (sets that distinguish multiple occurrences of elements) or sequences of formulae. For example, in linear logic, since contraction fails, the premises must be composed in something at least as fine-grained as multisets. |
||
== History == |
== History == |
||
Substructural logics are a relatively young field. The first conference on the topic was held in October 1990 in Tübingen, as "Logics with Restricted Structural Rules". During the conference, Kosta Došen proposed the term "substructural logics", which is now in use today. |
|||
== See also == |
== See also == |
||
Line 53: | Line 56: | ||
* [[Residuated lattice]] |
* [[Residuated lattice]] |
||
== |
==References== |
||
{{reflist}} |
|||
* |
* F. Paoli (2002), ''[https://books.google.com/books?id=RkPsCAAAQBAJ Substructural Logics: A Primer]'', Kluwer. |
||
* G. Restall (2000) ''[https://books.google.com/books?id=NQTm_bRupAgC An Introduction to Substructural Logics]'', Routledge. |
|||
== Further reading == |
== Further reading == |
||
* Galatos, Nikolaos, Peter Jipsen, Tomasz Kowalski, and Hiroakira Ono (2007), ''Residuated Lattices. An Algebraic Glimpse at Substructural Logics'', Elsevier, |
* Galatos, Nikolaos, Peter Jipsen, Tomasz Kowalski, and Hiroakira Ono (2007), ''Residuated Lattices. An Algebraic Glimpse at Substructural Logics'', Elsevier, {{isbn|978-0-444-52141-5}}. |
||
== |
==External links== |
||
*{{Commonscat-inline}} |
|||
*{{ |
*{{cite SEP |url-id=logic-substructural |title=Substructural logics |last=Restall |first=Greg}} |
||
{{logic}} |
{{Non-classical logic}} |
||
[[Category:Substructural logic| ]] |
[[Category:Substructural logic| ]] |
Revision as of 00:10, 3 December 2024
This article includes a list of references, related reading, or external links, but its sources remain unclear because it lacks inline citations. (June 2016) |
In logic, a substructural logic is a logic lacking one of the usual structural rules (e.g. of classical and intuitionistic logic), such as weakening, contraction, exchange or associativity. Two of the more significant substructural logics are relevance logic and linear logic.
Examples
In a sequent calculus, one writes each line of a proof as
- .
Here the structural rules are rules for rewriting the LHS of the sequent, denoted Γ, initially conceived of as a string (sequence) of propositions. The standard interpretation of this string is as conjunction: we expect to read
as the sequent notation for
- (A and B) implies C.
Here we are taking the RHS Σ to be a single proposition C (which is the intuitionistic style of sequent); but everything applies equally to the general case, since all the manipulations are taking place to the left of the turnstile symbol .
Since conjunction is a commutative and associative operation, the formal setting-up of sequent theory normally includes structural rules for rewriting the sequent Γ accordingly—for example for deducing
from
- .
There are further structural rules corresponding to the idempotent and monotonic properties of conjunction: from
we can deduce
- .
Also from
one can deduce, for any B,
- .
Linear logic, in which duplicated hypotheses 'count' differently from single occurrences, leaves out both of these rules, while relevant (or relevance) logics merely leaves out the latter rule, on the ground that B is clearly irrelevant to the conclusion.
The above are basic examples of structural rules. It is not that these rules are contentious, when applied in conventional propositional calculus. They occur naturally in proof theory, and were first noticed there (before receiving a name).
Premise composition
There are numerous ways to compose premises (and in the multiple-conclusion case, conclusions as well). One way is to collect them into a set. But since e.g. {a,a} = {a} we have contraction for free if premises are sets. We also have associativity and permutation (or commutativity) for free as well, among other properties. In substructural logics, typically premises are not composed into sets, but rather they are composed into more fine-grained structures, such as trees or multisets (sets that distinguish multiple occurrences of elements) or sequences of formulae. For example, in linear logic, since contraction fails, the premises must be composed in something at least as fine-grained as multisets.
History
Substructural logics are a relatively young field. The first conference on the topic was held in October 1990 in Tübingen, as "Logics with Restricted Structural Rules". During the conference, Kosta Došen proposed the term "substructural logics", which is now in use today.
See also
References
- F. Paoli (2002), Substructural Logics: A Primer, Kluwer.
- G. Restall (2000) An Introduction to Substructural Logics, Routledge.
Further reading
- Galatos, Nikolaos, Peter Jipsen, Tomasz Kowalski, and Hiroakira Ono (2007), Residuated Lattices. An Algebraic Glimpse at Substructural Logics, Elsevier, ISBN 978-0-444-52141-5.
External links
- Media related to Substructural logic at Wikimedia Commons
- Restall, Greg. "Substructural logics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.