Early modern philosophy: Difference between revisions
m Changes I made are, prepositions of 'in the' and correct spelling of the word 'vote'. Tags: Visual edit Mobile edit Mobile web edit Newcomer task Newcomer task: links |
Citation bot (talk | contribs) Added journal. | Use this bot. Report bugs. | Suggested by Pancho507 | Linked from User:Pancho507/sandbox | #UCB_webform_linked 208/3809 |
||
(32 intermediate revisions by 19 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|Period in the history of philosophy}} |
{{Short description|Period in the history of philosophy}} |
||
{{histphil}} |
{{histphil}} |
||
'''Early modern philosophy''' (also '''classical modern philosophy''')<ref>Jeffrey Tlumak, ''Classical Modern Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction'', Routledge, 2006, p. xi: "[''Classical Modern Philosophy''] is a guide through the systems of the seven brilliant seventeenth- and eighteenth-century European philosophers most regularly taught in college Modern Philosophy courses".</ref><ref name="Schacht">[[Richard Schacht]], ''Classical Modern Philosophers: Descartes to Kant'', Routledge, 2013, p. 1: "Seven men have come to stand out from all of their counterparts in what has come to be known as the 'modern' period in the history of philosophy (i.e., the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries): Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume and Kant".</ref> is a period in the [[history of philosophy]] that overlaps with the beginning of the period known as [[modern philosophy]]. |
'''Early modern philosophy''' (also '''classical modern philosophy''')<ref>Jeffrey Tlumak, ''Classical Modern Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction'', Routledge, 2006, p. xi: "[''Classical Modern Philosophy''] is a guide through the systems of the seven brilliant seventeenth- and eighteenth-century European philosophers most regularly taught in college Modern Philosophy courses".</ref><ref name="Schacht">[[Richard Schacht]], ''Classical Modern Philosophers: Descartes to Kant'', Routledge, 2013, p. 1: "Seven men have come to stand out from all of their counterparts in what has come to be known as the 'modern' period in the history of philosophy (i.e., the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries): Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume and Kant".</ref> The early modern era of philosophy was a progressive movement of Western thought, exploring through theories and discourse such topics as mind and matter, is a period in the [[history of philosophy]] that overlaps with the beginning of the period known as [[modern philosophy]]. It succeeded the [[Medieval philosophy|medieval era of philosophy]]. Early modern philosophy is usually thought to have occurred between the 16th and 18th centuries, though some philosophers and historians may put this period slightly earlier. During this time, influential philosophers included [[René Descartes|Descartes]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[David Hume|Hume]], and [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]], all of whom contributed to the current understanding of philosophy. |
||
The early modern era of philosophy was a progressive movement of Western thought, exploring through theories and discourse such topics as [[Mind–body dualism|mind and matter]], the [[supernatural]], and [[Civil liberties|civil life]]. It succeeded in the [[Medieval philosophy|medieval era of philosophy]]. Early modern philosophy is usually thought to have occurred between the [[16th century|16th]] and [[18th century|18th]] centuries, though some philosophers and historians may put this period slightly earlier. During this time, influential philosophers included [[René Descartes|Descartes]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[David Hume|Hume]], and [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]], all of whom contributed to the current understanding of philosophy. |
|||
==Overview== |
==Overview== |
||
The [[early modern period]] in history is |
The [[early modern period]] in history is around {{Circa|1500}}–1789, but the label "early modern philosophy" is typically used to refer to a narrower period of time.<ref>[[Marshall Berman]]. 1982. ''[[All That Is Solid Melts into Air]]: The Experience of Modernity''. New York: Simon and Schuster. {{ISBN|0-671-24602-X}}. London: Verso. pp. 16–17. {{ISBN|0-86091-785-1}}. Paperback reprint New York: Viking Penguin, 1988. {{ISBN|0-14-010962-5}}.</ref> |
||
In the narrowest sense, the term is used to refer principally to the [[17th-century philosophy|philosophy of the 17th century]] and [[18th-century philosophy|18th century]], typically beginning with [[René Descartes]]. 17th-century philosophers typically included in such analyses are [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[Blaise Pascal]], [[Baruch Spinoza]], [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]], and [[Isaac Newton]]. The 18th century, often known as the [[Age of Enlightenment]], included such early modern figures as [[John Locke]], [[George Berkeley]], and [[David Hume]].<ref name="Schacht"/> |
In the narrowest sense, the term is used to refer principally to the [[17th-century philosophy|philosophy of the 17th century]] and [[18th-century philosophy|18th century]], typically beginning with [[René Descartes]]. 17th-century philosophers typically included in such analyses are [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[Blaise Pascal]], [[Baruch Spinoza]], [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]], and [[Isaac Newton]]. The 18th century, often known as the [[Age of Enlightenment]], included such early modern figures as [[John Locke]], [[George Berkeley]], and [[David Hume]].<ref name="Schacht"/> |
||
The term is sometimes used more broadly, including earlier thinkers from the 16th century such as [[Niccolò Machiavelli]], [[Martin Luther]], [[John Calvin]], [[Michel de Montaigne]], and [[Francis Bacon]].<ref>[[Brian Leiter]] (ed.), ''The Future for Philosophy'', Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 44 n. 2.</ref> Some definitions also broaden the range of thinkers included under the "early modern" moniker, such as [[Voltaire]], [[Giambattista Vico]], [[Thomas Paine]]. By the broadest definition, the early modern period is said to have ended in 1804 with the death of [[Immanuel Kant]]. Considered in this way, the period extends |
The term is sometimes used more broadly, including earlier thinkers from the 16th century such as [[Niccolò Machiavelli]], [[Martin Luther]], [[John Calvin]], [[Michel de Montaigne]], and [[Francis Bacon]].<ref>[[Brian Leiter]] (ed.), ''The Future for Philosophy'', Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 44 n. 2.</ref> Some definitions also broaden the range of thinkers included under the "early modern" moniker, such as [[Voltaire]], [[Giambattista Vico]], [[Thomas Paine]]. By the broadest definition, the early modern period is said to have ended in 1804 with the death of [[Immanuel Kant]]. Considered in this way, the period extends from the last [[Renaissance philosophy|Renaissance philosophers]] to the final days of the [[Age of Enlightenment]]. |
||
⚫ | Most scholars consider the period to begin with [[René Descartes]]’ ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy|Meditationes de Prima Philosophiae]]'' (Meditations on First Philosophy) in Paris in 1641 and conclude with the work of the German philosopher Immanuel Kant (''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'') in the 1780s.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=Smith|first=Kurt|title=Descartes' Life and Works|date=2018|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/descartes-works/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Winter 2018|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-05-19}}</ref> |
||
== Early modern European philosophy == |
|||
⚫ | Most scholars consider the period to begin with [[René Descartes]]’ ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy|Meditationes de Prima Philosophiae]]'' (Meditations on First Philosophy) in |
||
[[File:Dispute-of-queen-cristina-vasa-and-rene-descartes.png|thumb|Dispute between Queen Christina and René Descartes]] |
[[File:Dispute-of-queen-cristina-vasa-and-rene-descartes.png|thumb|Dispute between Queen Christina and René Descartes]] |
||
At the time, various thinkers faced difficult philosophical challenges: reconciling the tenets of classical [[Aristotelianism|Aristotelian]] thought and [[Christian theology]] with the new [[Innovation|technological advances]] that followed in the wake of [[Nicolaus Copernicus|Copernicus]], [[Galileo Galilei|Galileo]], and [[Isaac Newton|Newton]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Levers|first=Merry-Jo D.|date=2013-01-01|title=Philosophical Paradigms, Grounded Theory, and Perspectives on Emergence|journal=SAGE Open|language=en|volume=3|issue=4|pages=2158244013517243|doi=10.1177/2158244013517243|issn=2158-2440|doi-access=free}}</ref> A modern [[Mechanical philosophy|mechanical image of the cosmos]] in which mathematically definable [[universal law]]s directed the motion of lifeless objects without the interference of something non-physical, specifically challenged established ways of thought about the [[mind]], [[Mind–body problem|body]] and |
At the time, various thinkers faced difficult philosophical challenges: reconciling the tenets of classical [[Aristotelianism|Aristotelian]] thought and [[Christian theology]] with the new [[Innovation|technological advances]] that followed in the wake of [[Nicolaus Copernicus|Copernicus]], [[Galileo Galilei|Galileo]], and [[Isaac Newton|Newton]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Levers|first=Merry-Jo D.|date=2013-01-01|title=Philosophical Paradigms, Grounded Theory, and Perspectives on Emergence|journal=SAGE Open|language=en|volume=3|issue=4|pages=2158244013517243|doi=10.1177/2158244013517243|issn=2158-2440|doi-access=free}}</ref> A modern [[Mechanical philosophy|mechanical image of the cosmos]] in which mathematically definable [[universal law]]s directed the motion of lifeless objects without the interference of something non-physical, specifically challenged established ways of thought about the [[mind]], [[Mind–body problem|body]] and God. In response, philosophers, many of whom were involved in experimental advances, invented and perfected various perspectives on humans’ relationship to the [[cosmos]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Bica|first=Daian|date=2020-12-25|title=Thinking with Mechanisms: Mechanical Philosophy and Early Modern Science|url=https://www.pdcnet.org/pdc/bvdb.nsf/purchase?openform&fp=jems&id=jems_2020_0009_0001_0133_0141|access-date=2021-05-19|journal=Journal of Early Modern Studies|volume=9|pages=133–141|doi=10.5840/jems2020916|s2cid=235002069 |language=en}}</ref> |
||
Three critical historical events that shaped Western thought profoundly were the [[Age of Discovery]], the progress of modern science, and the [[Protestant reformation |
Three critical historical events that shaped Western thought profoundly were the [[Age of Discovery]], the progress of modern science, and the [[Protestant reformation]] and its [[European wars of religion|resulting civil wars]].<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/oso/9780198829294.001.0001/oso-9780198829294|title=Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, Volume VIII|journal=Oxford Scholarship Online |year=2018|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0-19-186788-0|language=en-US|doi=10.1093/oso/9780198829294.001.0001|editor1-last=Garber|editor1-first=Daniel|editor2-first=Donald|editor2-last=Rutherford}}</ref> The relationship between philosophy and [[scientific research]] was complicated, as many early modern scientists considered themselves philosophers, conflating the two disciplines.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Wu|first=Kun|date=December 2016|title=The Interaction and Convergence of the Philosophy and Science of Information|journal=Philosophies|language=en|volume=1|issue=3|pages=228–244|doi=10.3390/philosophies1030228|doi-access=free}}</ref> These two fields would eventually separate. Contemporary philosophy's [[Epistemology|epistemological]] and [[Methodology|methodological]] concerns about scientific certainty remained regardless of such a separation.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199659593.001.0001/acprof-9780199659593|title=Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy Volume VI|journal=Oxford Scholarship Online |year=2012|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0-19-174521-8|language=en-US|doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199659593.001.0001|editor1-last=Garber|editor1-first=Daniel|editor2-first=Donald|editor2-last=Rutherford}}</ref> |
||
The early modern [[Intellectual tradition|intellectual era]] also contributed to the development of [[Western philosophy]]. New philosophical theories, such as the [[Metaphysics|metaphysical]], civic existence, [[epistemology]], and rationalist thinking, were established.<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Beatty|first1=Joy E.|last2=Leigh|first2=Jennifer S. A.|last3=Dean|first3=Kathy Lund|date=2009-02-01|title=Philosophy Rediscovered: Exploring the Connections Between Teaching Philosophies, Educational Philosophies, and Philosophy|url=https://doi.org/10.1177/1052562907310557|journal=Journal of Management Education|language=en|volume=33|issue=1|pages=99–114|doi=10.1177/1052562907310557|s2cid=146478936|issn=1052-5629}}</ref> There was a strong emphasis on the advancement and expansion of [[rationalism]], which placed a premium on [[rationality]], [[reason]]ing, and discovery to pursue |
The early modern [[Intellectual tradition|intellectual era]] also contributed to the development of [[Western philosophy]]. New philosophical theories, such as the [[Metaphysics|metaphysical]], civic existence, [[epistemology]], and rationalist thinking, were established.<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Beatty|first1=Joy E.|last2=Leigh|first2=Jennifer S. A.|last3=Dean|first3=Kathy Lund|date=2009-02-01|title=Philosophy Rediscovered: Exploring the Connections Between Teaching Philosophies, Educational Philosophies, and Philosophy|url=https://doi.org/10.1177/1052562907310557|journal=Journal of Management Education|language=en|volume=33|issue=1|pages=99–114|doi=10.1177/1052562907310557|s2cid=146478936|issn=1052-5629}}</ref> There was a strong emphasis on the advancement and expansion of [[rationalism]], which placed a premium on [[rationality]], [[reason]]ing, and discovery to pursue reality.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Berchielli|first=Laura|chapter=Introduction: Ideas of Space and Their Relation to Experience in Early Modern Philosophy|date=2020|chapter-url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-3-030-57620-2_1|title=Empiricist Theories of Space|series=Studies in History and Philosophy of Science|volume=54|pages=1–48|editor-last=Berchielli|editor-first=Laura|place=Cham|publisher=Springer International Publishing|language=en|doi=10.1007/978-3-030-57620-2_1|isbn=978-3-030-57619-6|s2cid=229272121 |access-date=2021-05-19}}</ref> |
||
== Enlightenment Period == |
|||
The [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]], also referred to as the Age of Enlightenment, was a [[philosophical movement]] that dominated the realm of ideas in 18th-century Europe. It was founded on the principle that [[reason]] is the fundamental source of power and legitimacy, and it promoted principles such as [[liberty]], progress, tolerance, fraternity, [[Constitutionalism|constitutional]] governance, and [[Separation of church and state|church-state separation]]. The Enlightenment was defined by a focus on |
The [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]], also referred to as the Age of Enlightenment, was a [[philosophical movement]] that dominated the realm of ideas in 18th-century Europe. It was founded on the principle that [[reason]] is the fundamental source of power and legitimacy, and it promoted principles such as [[liberty]], progress, tolerance, fraternity, [[Constitutionalism|constitutional]] governance, and [[Separation of church and state|church-state separation]]. The Enlightenment was defined by a focus on science and [[reductionism]], as well as a growing suspicion of [[Dogmatism|religious rigidity]]. The Enlightenment's ideals challenged the monarchy and the church, laying the groundwork for the political upheavals of the 18th and 19th centuries. According to [[French historians]], the [[Age of Enlightenment]] began in 1715, the year [[Louis XIV]] died, and ended in 1789, the year of the [[French Revolution]]. According to some contemporary historians, the era begins in the 1620s, with the birth of the [[Scientific Revolution]]. However, during the first decades of the 18th century and the first decades of the 19th century, several national variations of the movement developed.[[File:Enlightenment .png|thumb|Enlightenment discussions between various thinkers]]The Englishmen [[Francis Bacon]] and [[Thomas Hobbes]], the Frenchman [[René Descartes]], and the prominent natural philosophers of the [[Scientific Revolution]], including [[Galileo Galilei]], [[Johannes Kepler]], and [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]], were significant 17th-century antecedents of the Enlightenment. Its origins are often ascribed to [[1600s in England|1680s England]], when [[Isaac Newton]] published his "[[Principia Mathematica]]" (1686) and [[John Locke]] wrote his [[An Essay Concerning Human Understanding|"Essay Concerning Human Understanding"]] (1689)—two works that laid the groundwork for the Enlightenment's great advancements in science, mathematics, and philosophy.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Schmidt|first=James|date=January 2006|title=What Enlightenment Was, What It Still Might Be, and Why Kant May Have Been Right After All|url=http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0002764205282215|journal=American Behavioral Scientist|language=en|volume=49|issue=5|pages=647–663|doi=10.1177/0002764205282215|hdl=2144/3877|s2cid=144140862|issn=0002-7642|hdl-access=free}}</ref> |
||
The Age Of Enlightenment |
The Age Of Enlightenment was swiftly sweeping across Europe. In the late seventeenth century, scientists such as [[Isaac Newton]] and authors such as [[John Locke]] challenged the established order. Newton's principles of [[gravity]] and [[motion]] defined the universe in terms of natural principles that were independent of any spiritual source. Locke advocated the freedom of a people to replace a government that did not defend inherent rights to [[life, liberty, and property]] in the aftermath of England's political instability. People began to mistrust the possibility of a God [[Theological determinism|capable of predestining]] human beings to [[Hell in Christianity|everlasting damnation]] and [[Divine right of kings|empowering a despotic ruler]] to rule. These ideals would permanently alter Europe. |
||
=== Major Enlightenment concepts === |
|||
Europe had a burst of philosophical and scientific activity in the mid-18th century, challenging established theories and dogmas.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=Nickles|first=Thomas|title=Scientific Revolutions|date=2017|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/scientific-revolutions/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Winter 2017|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-05-27}}</ref> [[Voltaire]] and [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]] headed the philosophic movement, arguing for a society founded on [[reason]] rather than |
Europe had a burst of philosophical and scientific activity in the mid-18th century, challenging established theories and dogmas.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=Nickles|first=Thomas|title=Scientific Revolutions|date=2017|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/scientific-revolutions/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Winter 2017|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-05-27}}</ref> [[Voltaire]] and [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]] headed the philosophic movement, arguing for a society founded on [[reason]] rather than religion and [[Catholic theology]], for a new civic order based on [[natural law]], and for science founded on experimentation and observation.<ref>{{Cite web|title=Enlightenment |url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/enlightenment|access-date=2021-05-27|website=encyclopedia.com}}</ref> [[Montesquieu]], a political philosopher, proposed the notion of a government's [[Separation of powers|division of powers]], which was enthusiastically accepted by the framers of the [[Constitution of the United States|United States Constitution]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Douglass|first=Robin|date=2012-10-01|title=Montesquieu and Modern Republicanism|url=https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2011.00932.x|journal=Political Studies|language=en|volume=60|issue=3|pages=703–719|doi=10.1111/j.1467-9248.2011.00932.x|s2cid=142651026|issn=0032-3217}}</ref> |
||
Two separate schools of Enlightenment philosophy existed. Inspired by [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza's theory]], the radical enlightenment argued for |
Two separate schools of Enlightenment philosophy existed. Inspired by [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza's theory]], the radical enlightenment argued for democracy, [[individual liberty]], [[freedom of speech]], and the abolition of [[Theocracy|religious authority]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Colilli|first=Julian|date=2016|title=Jonathan Israel's Enlightenment: The Case of Giambattista Vico|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/44504589|journal=Italica|volume=93|issue=3|pages=469–493|jstor=44504589|issn=0021-3020}}</ref> A second, more moderate kind, championed by [[René Descartes]], [[John Locke]], [[Christian Wolff (philosopher)|Christian Wolff]], and [[Isaac Newton]], aimed to strike a balance between reform and old power and religious institutions.<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Nicolaidis|first1=Efthymios|last2=Delli|first2=Eudoxie|last3=Livanos|first3=Nikolaos|last4=Tampakis|first4=Kostas|last5=Vlahakis|first5=George|date=2016-09-20|title=Science and Orthodox Christianity: An Overview|url=https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1086/688704|journal=Isis|language=en|volume=107|issue=3|pages=542–566|doi=10.1086/688704|pmid=28707856|s2cid=34598125|issn=0021-1753}}</ref> |
||
Science eventually began to dominate Enlightenment speech and thinking.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Domínguez|first=Juan Pablo|date=2017-05-19|title=Introduction: Religious toleration in the Age of Enlightenment|journal=History of European Ideas|volume=43|issue=4|pages=273–287|doi=10.1080/01916599.2016.1203590|issn=0191-6599|doi-access=free}}</ref> Numerous Enlightenment authors and intellectuals came from scientific backgrounds and equated scientific progress with the downfall of religion and conventional authority in favour of the growth of free speech and ideas.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=De Cruz|first=Helen|title=Religion and Science|date=2019|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/religion-science/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Summer 2019|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-05-27}}</ref> In general, Enlightenment science placed a high premium on [[empiricism]] and logical reasoning, and was inextricably linked to the Enlightenment ideal of progression and development.<ref>{{Cite book|last1=Desai|first1=Vandana|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=AO4jAwAAQBAJ&q=enlightenment+and+progression+and+development&pg=PA95|title=The Companion to Development Studies|last2=Potter|first2=Rob|date=2014-03-21|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1-134-05159-5|language=en}}</ref> However, as was the case with the majority of Enlightenment ideals, the advantages of science were not widely recognized.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last1=Reiss|first1=Julian|title=Scientific Objectivity|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/scientific-objectivity/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Winter 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-05-27|last2=Sprenger|first2=Jan}}</ref> |
Science eventually began to dominate Enlightenment speech and thinking.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Domínguez|first=Juan Pablo|date=2017-05-19|title=Introduction: Religious toleration in the Age of Enlightenment|journal=History of European Ideas|volume=43|issue=4|pages=273–287|doi=10.1080/01916599.2016.1203590|issn=0191-6599|doi-access=free}}</ref> Numerous Enlightenment authors and intellectuals came from scientific backgrounds and equated scientific progress with the downfall of religion and conventional authority in favour of the growth of free speech and ideas.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=De Cruz|first=Helen|title=Religion and Science|date=2019|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/religion-science/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Summer 2019|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-05-27}}</ref> In general, Enlightenment science placed a high premium on [[empiricism]] and logical reasoning, and was inextricably linked to the Enlightenment ideal of progression and development.<ref>{{Cite book|last1=Desai|first1=Vandana|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=AO4jAwAAQBAJ&q=enlightenment+and+progression+and+development&pg=PA95|title=The Companion to Development Studies|last2=Potter|first2=Rob|date=2014-03-21|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1-134-05159-5|language=en}}</ref> However, as was the case with the majority of Enlightenment ideals, the advantages of science were not widely recognized.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last1=Reiss|first1=Julian|title=Scientific Objectivity|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/scientific-objectivity/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Winter 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-05-27|last2=Sprenger|first2=Jan}}</ref> |
||
The Enlightenment has traditionally been credited with laying the groundwork for current Western political and intellectual culture.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Zafirovski|first=Milan|url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-1-4419-7387-0|title=The Enlightenment and Its Effects on Modern Society|date=2011|publisher=Springer New York|isbn=978-1-4419-7386-3|location=New York, NY|language=en|doi=10.1007/978-1-4419-7387-0}}</ref> It ushered in a period of political modernization in the West, focused on democratic principles and institutions and resulting in the establishment of modern, liberal democracies. The fundamentals of European liberal thought include the individual right, natural equality of all men, [[separation of powers]], the artificial nature of [[The Origins of Political Order|political order]] (which resulted in the later distinction between civil society and the state), the view that all legitimate political power must be "representative" and based on popular consent, and liberal interpretationism.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Müßig|first=Ulrike|chapter=A New Order of the Ages. Normativity and Precedence|date=2018|title=Reconsidering Constitutional Formation II Decisive Constitutional Normativity: From Old Liberties to New Precedence|pages=1–97|editor-last=Müßig|editor-first=Ulrike|series=Studies in the History of Law and Justice|volume=12|place=Cham|publisher=Springer International Publishing|language=en|doi=10.1007/978-3-319-73037-0_1|isbn=978-3-319-73037-0|doi-access=free}}</ref> |
|||
Enlightenment-era criticism on religion was a reaction to Europe's previous century of religious turmoil.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://sydney.primo.exlibrisgroup.com/discovery/fulldisplay?docid=cdi_jstor_primary_43572323&context=PC&vid=61USYD_INST:sydney&lang=en&search_scope=MyInst_and_CI&adaptor=Primo%20Central&tab=Everything&query=any,contains,religious%20turmoil%20in%20europe%20during%20the%20early%20modern%20period&offset=0|access-date=2021-05-27|website=sydney.primo.exlibrisgroup.com|language=en}}</ref> Enlightenment intellectuals intended to limit organized religion's political dominance, so averting another period of intolerable religious violence.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Collins|first=Jeffrey R.|date=2009|title=Redeeming the Enlightenment: New Histories of Religious Toleration|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/599275|journal=The Journal of Modern History|volume=81|issue=3|pages=607–636|doi=10.1086/599275|jstor=10.1086/599275|s2cid=143375411|issn=0022-2801}}</ref> Numerous unique concepts emerged, including [[deism]] (belief in God the Creator without reference to the |
Enlightenment-era criticism on religion was a reaction to Europe's previous century of religious turmoil.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://sydney.primo.exlibrisgroup.com/discovery/fulldisplay?docid=cdi_jstor_primary_43572323&context=PC&vid=61USYD_INST:sydney&lang=en&search_scope=MyInst_and_CI&adaptor=Primo%20Central&tab=Everything&query=any,contains,religious%20turmoil%20in%20europe%20during%20the%20early%20modern%20period&offset=0|access-date=2021-05-27|website=sydney.primo.exlibrisgroup.com|language=en}}</ref> Enlightenment intellectuals intended to limit organized religion's political dominance, so averting another period of intolerable religious violence.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Collins|first=Jeffrey R.|date=2009|title=Redeeming the Enlightenment: New Histories of Religious Toleration|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/599275|journal=The Journal of Modern History|volume=81|issue=3|pages=607–636|doi=10.1086/599275|jstor=10.1086/599275|s2cid=143375411|issn=0022-2801}}</ref> Numerous unique concepts emerged, including [[deism]] (belief in God the Creator without reference to the Bible or other authoritative source) and [[atheism]].<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=Draper|first=Paul|title=Atheism and Agnosticism|date=2017|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/atheism-agnosticism/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2017|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-05-27}}</ref> The latter was hotly debated but garnered few supporters. Many, like Voltaire, believed that without believing in a God who punishes wrong, society's moral order would be jeopardised.<ref>{{Cite web|title=Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern Word-Gaudium et Spes|url=https://www.vatican.va/archive/hist_councils/ii_vatican_council/documents/vat-ii_cons_19651207_gaudium-et-spes_en.html|access-date=2021-05-27|website=vatican.va}}</ref> |
||
== Characteristics == |
|||
The early modern period arose from dramatic shifts in many fields of human endeavour. Among the most significant characteristics are the formalisation of science, the acceleration of scientific advancement, and the creation of secularised civic politics, law courts, and the nation-state.<ref>{{Cite journal|date=2007|title=D. Rutherford (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy|url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/j.1755-2567.2007.tb01212.x|journal=Theoria|language=en|volume=73|issue=4|pages=334–339|doi=10.1111/j.1755-2567.2007.tb01212.x|issn=1755-2567}}</ref> There was some skepticism against traditional interpretive concepts associated with the modern era, such as the distinction between [[Empiricism|empiricists]] and [[Rationalism|rationalists]], which represented a philosophical and historical shift away from ethics, [[political philosophy]], and [[Epistemology|metaphysical epistemology]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Sellars|first=John|date=2020|title=Renaissance Humanism and Philosophy as a Way of Life|journal=Metaphilosophy|language=en|volume=51|issue=2–3|pages=226–243|doi=10.1111/meta.12409|issn=1467-9973|doi-access=free}}</ref> |
The early modern period arose from dramatic shifts in many fields of human endeavour. Among the most significant characteristics are the formalisation of science, the acceleration of scientific advancement, and the creation of secularised civic politics, law courts, and the nation-state.<ref>{{Cite journal|date=2007|title=D. Rutherford (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy|url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/j.1755-2567.2007.tb01212.x|journal=Theoria|language=en|volume=73|issue=4|pages=334–339|doi=10.1111/j.1755-2567.2007.tb01212.x|issn=1755-2567}}</ref> There was some skepticism against traditional interpretive concepts associated with the modern era, such as the distinction between [[Empiricism|empiricists]] and [[Rationalism|rationalists]], which represented a philosophical and historical shift away from ethics, [[political philosophy]], and [[Epistemology|metaphysical epistemology]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Sellars|first=John|date=2020|title=Renaissance Humanism and Philosophy as a Way of Life|journal=Metaphilosophy|language=en|volume=51|issue=2–3|pages=226–243|doi=10.1111/meta.12409|issn=1467-9973|doi-access=free}}</ref> |
||
[[Individualism]] also emerged as a reaction to [[belief]] and [[authority]], challenging the element of |
[[Individualism]] also emerged as a reaction to [[belief]] and [[authority]], challenging the element of Christianity and [[Christian philosophy|Christianised philosophy]] united with whoever the desired political leader happened to be at the time.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Ash|first=Eric H.|date=2010|title=Introduction: Expertise and the Early Modern State|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/657254|journal=Osiris|volume=25|issue=1|pages=1–24|doi=10.1086/657254|jstor=10.1086/657254|s2cid=144330049|issn=0369-7827}}</ref> The steady rise of the [[bourgeoisie]] would challenge the power of the Church and begin the journey towards the eventual separation of church and state. The political and economic situation of Modern Europe would have an influence on philosophical thought, mainly on ethics and [[political philosophy]].<ref>{{Cite web|title=Hobbes, Thomas: Moral and Political Philosophy {{!}} Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy|url=https://iep.utm.edu/hobmoral/|access-date=2021-05-19|language=en-US}}</ref> |
||
The [[Scientific Revolution |
The [[Scientific Revolution]] also gained legitimacy during this period. Early modern attempts to grapple with the [[Infinity (philosophy)|philosophy of infinity]] focused on and discussed three fundamental disagreements about the infinite—differences that had their origins in the academic philosophical tradition.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/cambridge-history-of-renaissance-philosophy/56DCEA40CA07B949448B608C47B2B670|title=The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy|date=1988|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0-521-25104-4|editor-last=Schmitt|editor-first=C. B.|location=Cambridge|doi=10.1017/CHOL9780521251044|s2cid=170086821 |editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Kessler|editor3-first=Eckhard|editor4-last=Kraye|editor4-first=Jill}}</ref> Philosophers such as [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]] and [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]] used this distinction to distinguish God's [[God and eternity|qualitative infinity]] from the mathematically abstract concept of [[infinity]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Schechtman|first=Anat|date=2019-10-01|title=Three Infinities in Early Modern Philosophy|url=https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/128/512/1117/5110139|journal=Mind|language=en|volume=128|issue=512|pages=1117–1147|doi=10.1093/mind/fzy034|issn=0026-4423}}</ref> Early modern thinkers differentiated between actual and potential infinity. Academic tradition has traditionally rejected the existence of actual infinities in the created world but has acknowledged potential infinities, following Aristotle's approach to Zeno's paradoxes.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Huggett|first=Nick|date=2002-04-30|title=Zeno's Paradoxes|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/paradox-zeno/}}</ref> Additionally, the advent of early modern thought was linked to changes in the period's intellectual and cultural context, such as the advancement of [[natural science]], theological contradictions within and between the [[Catholic Church|Catholic]] and [[Protestantism|Protestant churches]], and the growth of the modern nation-state.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Spruyt|first=Hendrik|date=2002-06-01|title=The origins, development, and possible decline of the modern state|journal=Annual Review of Political Science|volume=5|issue=1|pages=127–149|doi=10.1146/annurev.polisci.5.101501.145837|issn=1094-2939|doi-access=free}}</ref> |
||
== Significant thinkers == |
|||
[[File:Dispute-of-queen-cristina-vasa-and-rene-descartes.png|thumb|Reńe Descartes amid philosophical discussion with several philosophers during the early modern philosophical period]] |
[[File:Dispute-of-queen-cristina-vasa-and-rene-descartes.png|thumb|Reńe Descartes amid philosophical discussion with several philosophers during the early modern philosophical period]] |
||
[[René Descartes|Descartes]], [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]], [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], [[David Hume|Hume]], [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]], and [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]], as well as philosophers such as [[Hugo Grotius]], [[Pierre Gassendi]], [[Antoine Arnauld]], [[Nicolas Malebranche]], [[Pierre Bayle]], [[Samuel von Pufendorf]], and [[Francis Hutcheson (philosopher)|Francis Hutcheson]] are all recognised as significant figures in early modern philosophy, for their discourses and theories developed |
[[René Descartes|Descartes]], [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]], [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], [[David Hume|Hume]], [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]], and [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]], as well as philosophers such as [[Hugo Grotius]], [[Pierre Gassendi]], [[Antoine Arnauld]], [[Nicolas Malebranche]], [[Pierre Bayle]], [[Samuel von Pufendorf]], and [[Francis Hutcheson (philosopher)|Francis Hutcheson]] are all recognised as significant figures in early modern philosophy, for their discourses and theories developed throughout the various philosophical periods. |
||
The political philosophy of natural law, developed by John Locke, was a common and significant concept in early modern thought. Natural law evolved into individual rights and subjective claims. Adding to Aristotle's already known philosophy, Locke suggested that the government give its citizens what they believe are fundamental and [[Natural rights and legal rights|natural rights]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Uzgalis|first=William|date=2001-09-02|title=John Locke|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/locke/}}</ref> Thomas Hobbes, alternatively, asserted that natural law has a finite scope. Unchecked liberty led to a state of war where everybody struggled for life.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Schmaltz|first=Tad M.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=pIYcUBCOrNgC&q=%28Schmaltz%2C+2002%29+early+modern+philosophy&pg=PP1|title=Radical Cartesianism: The French Reception of Descartes|date=2002|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-139-43425-6|language=en}}</ref> Hobbes encapsulated this state of violence in one of philosophy's most famous passages: "And the life of man, solitary, bad, nasty, brutish, and brief".<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Lloyd|first1=Sharon A.|last2=Sreedhar|first2=Susanne|date=2002-02-12|title=Hobbes's Moral and Political Philosophy|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/hobbes-moral/}}</ref> Thomas Hobbes' worldview concentrated on social and political order and how humans could coexist without danger or risk of civil war.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Hampton|first=Jean|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1M_LCgAAQBAJ&pg=PP1|title=Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition|date=1988|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-316-58325-8|language=en}}</ref> |
The political philosophy of natural law, developed by John Locke, was a common and significant concept in early modern thought. Natural law evolved into individual rights and subjective claims. Adding to Aristotle's already known philosophy, Locke suggested that the government give its citizens what they believe are fundamental and [[Natural rights and legal rights|natural rights]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Uzgalis|first=William|date=2001-09-02|title=John Locke|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/locke/}}</ref> Thomas Hobbes, alternatively, asserted that natural law has a finite scope. Unchecked liberty led to a state of war where everybody struggled for life.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Schmaltz|first=Tad M.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=pIYcUBCOrNgC&q=%28Schmaltz%2C+2002%29+early+modern+philosophy&pg=PP1|title=Radical Cartesianism: The French Reception of Descartes|date=2002|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-139-43425-6|language=en}}</ref> Hobbes encapsulated this state of violence in one of philosophy's most famous passages: "And the life of man, solitary, bad, nasty, brutish, and brief".<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Lloyd|first1=Sharon A.|last2=Sreedhar|first2=Susanne|date=2002-02-12|title=Hobbes's Moral and Political Philosophy|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/hobbes-moral/}}</ref> Thomas Hobbes' worldview concentrated on social and political order and how humans could coexist without danger or risk of civil war.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Hampton|first=Jean|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1M_LCgAAQBAJ&pg=PP1|title=Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition|date=1988|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-316-58325-8|language=en}}</ref> |
||
=== Thomas Hobbes === |
|||
Hobbes' moral and political theory includes a consideration of [[natural rights]]. Hobbes' natural rights notion also included man in a "[[state of nature]]". As he saw it, the basic natural (human) right was to use his |
Hobbes' moral and political theory includes a consideration of [[natural rights]]. Hobbes' natural rights notion also included man in a "[[state of nature]]". As he saw it, the basic natural (human) right was to use his power, as he will, to preserve his nature, which is to protect his life.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Carmichael|first=D. J. C.|date=March 1990|title=Hobbes on Natural Right in Society: The Leviathan Account*|url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/canadian-journal-of-political-science-revue-canadienne-de-science-politique/article/abs/hobbes-on-natural-right-in-society-the-leviathan-account/2BDA061BBFAA7069EBEEF31B9F8A9F67|journal=Canadian Journal of Political Science/Revue Canadienne de Science Politique|language=en|volume=23|issue=1|pages=3–21|doi=10.1017/S0008423900011598|s2cid=154964034 |issn=1744-9324}}</ref> |
||
[[Libertarianism (metaphysics)|Natural liberty]] is distinct from universal laws, which [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]] referred to as precepts, or rules discovered by reason, which ban a man from doing something that will destroy his life or deprives him of the means to retain it.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Estrada|first=Fernando|date=2012|title=El Leviathan de Thomas Hobbes (The Leviathan of Thomas Hobbes)|url=http://www.ssrn.com/abstract=2127939|journal=SSRN Electronic Journal|language=en|doi=10.2139/ssrn.2127939|issn=1556-5068}}</ref> |
[[Libertarianism (metaphysics)|Natural liberty]] is distinct from universal laws, which [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]] referred to as precepts, or rules discovered by reason, which ban a man from doing something that will destroy his life or deprives him of the means to retain it.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Estrada|first=Fernando|date=2012|title=El Leviathan de Thomas Hobbes (The Leviathan of Thomas Hobbes)|url=http://www.ssrn.com/abstract=2127939|journal=SSRN Electronic Journal|language=en|doi=10.2139/ssrn.2127939|issn=1556-5068}}</ref> |
||
Line 57: | Line 53: | ||
In Hobbes' view, life comprised just of freedoms and nothing else "Because of that, everyone has the right to anything, even to one another's body. Because of this, though, as long as inherent human rights to every commodity remain in place, there can be no long-term security for anybody."<ref>{{Cite journal|last=McCrudden|first=Christopher|date=2008-09-01|title=Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights|journal=European Journal of International Law|volume=19|issue=4|pages=655–724|doi=10.1093/ejil/chn043|issn=0938-5428|doi-access=free}}</ref> |
In Hobbes' view, life comprised just of freedoms and nothing else "Because of that, everyone has the right to anything, even to one another's body. Because of this, though, as long as inherent human rights to every commodity remain in place, there can be no long-term security for anybody."<ref>{{Cite journal|last=McCrudden|first=Christopher|date=2008-09-01|title=Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights|journal=European Journal of International Law|volume=19|issue=4|pages=655–724|doi=10.1093/ejil/chn043|issn=0938-5428|doi-access=free}}</ref> |
||
This would result in the condition called the "[[Bellum omnium contra omnes|war of all against all]]," in which humans murder, steal, and enslave each other |
This would result in the condition called the "[[Bellum omnium contra omnes|war of all against all]]," in which humans murder, steal, and enslave each other to remain alive. Hobbes theorised that human existence would be lonely, poor, ugly, brutish, and short in a state of chaos generated by unrestricted rights. As such, people would agree to give up many of their basic rights to build a political and civil society. [[Social contract|Social contract theory]] was first articulated using this early argumentation.<ref>{{Cite journal|date=October 1970|url=http://doi.wiley.com/10.1111/j.1468-0149.1970.tb00060.x|journal=Philosophical Books|language=en|volume=11|issue=3|pages=10–12|doi=10.1111/j.1468-0149.1970.tb00060.x|title=The Logic of Leviathan |last1=Minogue |first1=K. R. }}</ref> |
||
Natural or institutional laws are useless without first being established by a [[Westphalian sovereignty|sovereign authority]]. Before you can talk about right and unjust, |
Natural or institutional laws are useless without first being established by a [[Westphalian sovereignty|sovereign authority]]. Before you can talk about right and unjust, some coercive authority must compel folks to keep their promises. There is no such coercive force before the establishment of the state.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Skinner|first=Quentin|date=1966|title=The Ideological Context of Hobbes's Political Thought|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2637983|journal=The Historical Journal|volume=9|issue=3|pages=286–317|doi=10.1017/S0018246X66000014|jstor=2637983|s2cid=248825400 |issn=0018-246X}}</ref> This coercive State would, in Hobbes' view, have the right to confiscate property in return for a guarantee of citizens' safety from one another and from foreign intervention. |
||
According to [[Social contract|social contract theory]], "inalienable rights" are those rights that can't be relinquished by people to the sovereign.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Scott|first=John T.|date=September 2000|title=The Sovereignless State and Locke's Language of Obligation|url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/american-political-science-review/article/abs/sovereignless-state-and-lockes-language-of-obligation/DCF01EF56A5FC3D1E8F9D7FAA1B4E174|journal=American Political Science Review|language=en|volume=94|issue=3|pages=547–561|doi=10.2307/2585830|jstor=2585830|s2cid=144108638|issn=0003-0554}}</ref> These inherent rights were believed to be law-independent. |
According to [[Social contract|social contract theory]], "inalienable rights" are those rights that can't be relinquished by people to the sovereign.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Scott|first=John T.|date=September 2000|title=The Sovereignless State and Locke's Language of Obligation|url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/american-political-science-review/article/abs/sovereignless-state-and-lockes-language-of-obligation/DCF01EF56A5FC3D1E8F9D7FAA1B4E174|journal=American Political Science Review|language=en|volume=94|issue=3|pages=547–561|doi=10.2307/2585830|jstor=2585830|s2cid=144108638|issn=0003-0554}}</ref> These inherent rights were believed to be law-independent. Only the strongest could use their privileges in the [[state of nature]].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Bruner|first=Justin P.|date=2020-03-01|title=Locke, Nozick and the state of nature|journal=Philosophical Studies|language=en|volume=177|issue=3|pages=705–726|doi=10.1007/s11098-018-1201-9|s2cid=171478513|issn=1573-0883|doi-access=free}}</ref> Thereby, individuals give up their natural rights to get protection, and thus have the legal rights conferred by the power to do so.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=Tuckness|first=Alex|title=Locke's Political Philosophy|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/locke-political/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Winter 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-06-02}}</ref> |
||
Many historical justifications for [[slavery]] and [[Illiberal democracy|illiberal governance]] include consensual arrangements to relinquish inherent rights to freedom and [[self-determination]]. De facto inalienability arguments supplied the foundation for the anti-slavery movement to argue against all involuntary enslavement, not only slavery explicitly defined as such. An agreement to unlawfully divide a right would be void of law. Similarly, the argument was used by the democratic movement to reject explicit or implicit social covenants of subjection (e.g., pactum subjectionis) that subjugate a people, for example, in [[Leviathan (Hobbes book)|Leviathan]] by [[Thomas Hobbes]]. According to [[Ernst Cassirer]] |
Many historical justifications for [[slavery]] and [[Illiberal democracy|illiberal governance]] include consensual arrangements to relinquish inherent rights to freedom and [[self-determination]]. De facto inalienability arguments supplied the foundation for the anti-slavery movement to argue against all involuntary enslavement, not only slavery explicitly defined as such. An agreement to unlawfully divide a right would be void of law. Similarly, the argument was used by the democratic movement to reject explicit or implicit social covenants of subjection (e.g., pactum subjectionis) that subjugate a people, for example, in [[Leviathan (Hobbes book)|Leviathan]] by [[Thomas Hobbes]]. According to [[Ernst Cassirer]]:<blockquote>There is, at least, one right that cannot be ceded or abandoned: the right to personality...They charged the great logician [Hobbes] with a contradiction in terms. If a man could give up his personality he would cease being a moral being. … There is no ''pactum subjectionis'', no act of submission by which man can give up the state of free agent and enslave himself. For by such an act of renunciation he would give up that very character which constitutes his nature and essence: he would lose his humanity.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Ellerman|first=David|date=September 2010|title=Inalienable Rights: A Litmus Test for Liberal Theories of Justice|journal=Law and Philosophy|language=en|volume=29|issue=5|pages=571–599|doi=10.1007/s10982-010-9076-8|s2cid=52028430|issn=0167-5249|doi-access=free}}</ref></blockquote> |
||
== Influence == |
|||
Until the twenty-first century, standard accounts of early modern philosophy and traditional survey courses in Anglo-Saxon universities—presented histories dominated by [[René Descartes|Descartes]], [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]], [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], [[David Hume|Hume]], and [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]].<ref>{{Cite web|last=Broad|first=Jacqueline|date=2020-10-21|title=Early Modern Philosophy: A Perverse Thought Experiment|url=https://blog.apaonline.org/2020/10/21/early-modern-philosophy-a-perverse-thought-experiment/|access-date=2021-05-19|website=Blog of the APA|language=en-US}}</ref> |
Until the twenty-first century, standard accounts of early modern philosophy and traditional survey courses in Anglo-Saxon universities—presented histories dominated by [[René Descartes|Descartes]], [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]], [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], [[David Hume|Hume]], and [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]].<ref>{{Cite web|last=Broad|first=Jacqueline|date=2020-10-21|title=Early Modern Philosophy: A Perverse Thought Experiment|url=https://blog.apaonline.org/2020/10/21/early-modern-philosophy-a-perverse-thought-experiment/|access-date=2021-05-19|website=Blog of the APA|language=en-US}}</ref> |
||
Early modern theory has |
Early modern theory has significantly impacted many modern developments, one of which is political philosophy. American political philosopher [[A. John Simmons]] examined two interrelated transitions in the [[early modern period]]. The first is a metaphysical contrast between [[political naturalism]], which holds that human beings are political by birth, and political anti-naturalism, which holds that humankind's natural state is apolitical.<ref>{{Cite book|last1=Caro|first1=Mario, 20 /21 Jh [Hrsg ] De|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cQke-j8oMHUC&pg=PA1|title=Naturalism in Question|last2=Caro|first2=Mario De|last3=Macarthur|first3=David|last4=Macarthur|first4=Professor David|last5=MacArthur|first5=Douglas|date=2004|publisher=Harvard University Press|isbn=978-0-674-01295-0|language=en}}</ref> The second is the historical shift from "complex, bureaucratic systems with intertwined religious and contractual relationships" to political cultures that "take the form of independent, territorial states".<ref>{{Cite web|date=2016-12-26|title=The Making of the Modern World|url=https://www.e-ir.info/2016/12/26/the-making-of-the-modern-world/|access-date=2021-05-19|website=E-International Relations|language=en-US}}</ref> Observing how these transformations occur is important as the ideas advanced by early modern political theorists played an important role in the creation of political institutions that exist today.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Brooks|first=Thom|date=2013-05-01|title=In Defence of Political Theory: Impact and Opportunities|journal=Political Studies Review|language=en|volume=11|issue=2|pages=209–215|doi=10.1111/1478-9302.12007|issn=1478-9299|doi-access=free}}</ref> |
||
The evolution of early modern philosophy has been recognized as inextricably linked to developments in the period's intellectual and cultural environment |
The evolution of early modern philosophy has been recognized as inextricably linked to developments in the period's intellectual and cultural environment through important developments in science, the [[Catholic Church|Catholic]] and [[Protestantism|Protestant churches]], and the rise of the new modern nation state.<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Loewenstein|first1=David|last2=Shell|first2=Alison|date=2019-07-03|title=Early Modern Literature and England's Long Reformation|journal=Reformation|volume=24|issue=2|pages=53–58|doi=10.1080/13574175.2019.1665264|issn=1357-4175|doi-access=free}}</ref> |
||
== Early modern Asian philosophy == |
|||
=== Rise of Navya Nyaya in India === |
|||
{{copyedit|reason=Clarity, grammar, syntax|date=April 2023}} |
|||
{{Underlinked|section|date=April 2023}} |
|||
Before the beginning of early modern era, [[Indian philosophy]] saw dramatic changes and evolution. The Nyaya-[[Vaisheshika]] system merged, the old school of [[Navya-Nyāya|Nyāya]] gradually transformed into [[Navya-Nyāya|Navya-Nyāya system]] over a period of centuries.<ref>{{Cite book|chapter=3. Sense and Knowledge in Indian Philosophy|url=http://dx.doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-06654-8/6|title=Indian and Chinese Philosophy|year=2016 |publisher=Peter Lang|doi=10.3726/978-3-653-06654-8/6 |isbn=978-3-653-06654-8|access-date=2021-07-17}}</ref> The philosopher who led the transformation of philosophy in early modern India was [[Gaṅgeśa|Gangesa]] (14th century). After facing a severe and fierce [[Advaitin]] skeptical attack of [[Shriharsha|Sriharsha]] (12th century),<ref>{{Cite book|last=Mills|first=Ethan|url=https://www.amazon.in/Three-Pillars-Skepticism-Classical-India-ebook/dp/B07GQ6GNFY|title=Three Pillars of Skepticism in Classical India: Nagarjuna, Jayarasi, and Sri Harsa|date=2018-09-15|publisher=Lexington Books }}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|last=Handiqui|first=Krishna Kanta|url=http://archive.org/details/in.gov.ignca.5338|title=Naisadhacarita of Sriharsa|date=1956}}</ref> he wrote his magnum opus, [[Tattvacintāmaṇi|''Tattvacintamani'']], which initiated radical developments in the whole of Indian philosophy, leading scholars to attribute him as the founder of Navya-Nyāya. Tattvacintamani was a highly influential and sophisticated text; it led the other previous major work on logic to go into insignificance, replaced the chain of commentaries on old text of [[Nyāya Sūtras|''Nyāya Sūtras'']], and became the bedrock upon which new methods and techniques of logic and epistemology could be developed, and it introduced a new language in which logical and philosophical discourse can take place (10th century Nyaya philosopher [[Udayana]] observed that natural language possesses intrinsic ambiguity, comparable to developments and reasons to invent new language in modern logic, which also often led to misunderstandings in discourse. He wrote his independent works of the system deviating from traditional style, and scholars believe it led to the foundation of the [[Navya-Nyāya]] language.) |
|||
The new language tended to remove ambiguity of natural language and be a medium through which opponents can completely understand the view point of proponents without any gap. The language became so influential that all the [[Philosophical theory|philosophical systems]] adopted it in one ways or another (alongside logical techniques). The language also found its popularity among other fields of [[literature]] and [[law]]. The language's complexity and sophistication were so high that today there is no single complete [[translation]] of [[Tattvacintāmaṇi|Tattvacintamani]] and other major works (given the fact that major texts before him had found way into translation into Western languages). Matilal and others argue that Indian philosophy must not be overlooked but must be a part of mainstream philosophical discussion. He discards the position of Indian philosophy as merely a museum piece and considers it a thing to be looked into for deep insights into modern philosophical problem and for new ways, world views, perspectives or creativity to analyse and understand things.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Phillips|first=Stephen H|url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203152386|title=Epistemology in Classical India|date=2013-04-15|publisher=Routledge|doi=10.4324/9780203152386 |isbn=978-1-136-51899-7}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|last=Matilal|first=Bimal K.|date=1971-12-31|title=Epistemology, Logic, and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis|url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/9783110813562|doi=10.1515/9783110813562|isbn=978-3-11-081356-2 }}</ref> There had been efforts to translate a subsection of Tattvacintamani by scholars like Ingall, Potter, etc,<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=Phillips|first=Stephen|title=Gaṅgeśa|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/gangesa/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Summer 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-07-17}}</ref> but they faced fierce criticism for being unable to find a good English equivalent to highly complicated and technical terms and sentences, using some Western tools of logic and analysis which fail to get the intended meaning, thus unable to represent the meaning, and sometimes even the scholars themselves didn't understand the text (and other works).<ref>{{Citation|title=Can logic & Critical reasoning remove suffering permanently? - Gaṅgeśa & his Tattva-cintā-maṇi|url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ml5nbtZ62yw|language=en|access-date=2021-11-08}}</ref> The popularity of Tattvacintamani in India can be measured by the fact that the original work only had 300 pages but the commentaries upon it amount to about a million pages (with a text completely devoted one line/sentence in inference section <ref>{{Cite book|last1=Annambhaṭṭa|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=MS5kMwEACAAJ|title=Tarkasaṅgraha of Annambhaṭṭa: English Translation with Notes|last2=Jha|first2=Vashishtha Narayan|date=2010|publisher=Chinmaya International Foundation Shodha Sansthan|isbn=978-93-80864-03-7|language=en}}</ref>). In an attempt to introduce [[Navya-Nyāya]] to the study of Indian philosophy and philosophy in general, an entire perception section was translated for the first time.<ref>{{Cite web|last=bloomsbury.com|title=Jewel of Reflection on the Truth about Epistemology|url=https://www.bloomsbury.com/uk/jewel-of-reflection-on-the-truth-about-epistemology-9781350066533/|access-date=2021-07-17|website=Bloomsbury|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|last1=Phillips|first1=Stephen H.|title=Epistemology of Perception: Gangesa's Tattvacintamani|last2=Tatacharya|first2=N. S. Ramanuja|date=2004-12-29|isbn=0-9753734-3-9 }}</ref> Ganeri said:<ref>{{Cite web|title=Ganeri, Review of Epistemology Of Perception: Gaṅgeśa's Tattvacintāmaṇi, Jewel Of Reflection On The Truth (About Epistemology): The Perception Chapter (Pratyakṣa-khaṇḍa), Transliterated Text, Translation, And Philosophical Commentary. By STEPHEN H. PHILLIPS AND N.S. RAMANUJA TATACHARYA|url=http://www.columbia.edu/itc/mealac/pollock/sks/papers/Ganeri(review%2520of%2520Philips).pdf&sa=U&ved=2ahUKEwiX3KXDmunxAhXHzjgGHZJ_COYQFjAAegQICBAB&usg=AOvVaw1gfsKdBQET2GGvQeGrUsXJ|url-status=live}}</ref> |
|||
{{Blockquote|text=I was once asked in an interview for a job in a philosophy department whether I really believed that there were Indian philosophers of the same stature as Kant and Wittgenstein. I answered "yes" and mentioned Gaṅgeśa. Needless to say, none of them had ever heard of him |
|||
(and I didn’t get the job). Now at last it will be possible literally to ‘throw the book’ at philosophers who want to see proof.|author=Jonardon Ganeri}} |
|||
However, Gangesa didn't come without critical examination of Tattvacintamani and new innovation in field logic, language and philosophy. Varanasi, Nabadvipa and Mithila became the cosmopolitan hub of intellectual discourse in India, there were many major logicians from these regions, to state one radical (as scholar calls him) thinker, philosopher and logician was definitely Raghunatha Siromani, a man of new innovation and insights, without him the system wouldn't have reached at its zenith and this description of Navya-Nyaya remains incomplete. Jonardon Ganeri and considers him quite of a modern philosopher who transformed Indian philosophy in this period for the second time,<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Ganeri|first=Jonardon|title=Raghunātha Śiromaṇi and the Origins of Modernity in India (2012)|url=https://www.academia.edu/2146175|journal=Nagoya Studies in Indian Culture and Buddhism|date=January 2013 }}</ref> despite the critical approach of his system Gangesa had quite a conservative leaning but Siromani wasn't the same kind, he wrote a critical commentary on tattvacintamani known as didhiti and a work on critical examination of his own system, if gangesa worked on epistemology siromani worked for metaphysics, for him any old idea which doesn't fit into the framework of rigorous and robust logic and proof was discarded and rejected at once and the one which went fit was built upon and expanded further deeply, siromani's camp seem to a new system within the new.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|last=Ganeri|first=Jonardon|title=Analytic Philosophy in Early Modern India|date=2019|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/early-modern-india/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Summer 2019|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2021-07-17}}</ref> Siromani was the major spike where the navya system and techniques became very sophisticated and complicated in language and logic, and just like the languages in modern logic the system became unapproachable, not only by common people, but also to the best scholars and philosophers who have learnt from elsewhere. The system was confined in the intellectual environment of mithila, varanasi and navadvipa only but still every philosophical system had a reach to it. Ganeri even notes that the ideas of early enlightenment thinkers like descarte were actually known to Varanasi pundits in 17th century.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Ganeri|first=Jonardon|url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199218745.001.0001|title=The Lost Age of Reason|date=2011-03-10|publisher=Oxford University Press|doi=10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199218745.001.0001 |isbn=978-0-19-921874-5}}</ref> ganeri says that 16th and 17th century texts reflect a unique characteristic of Indian modernity l, that is not present in text of colonial era, where the central ideas of both old and new system could be willingly gave up on critical investigation, just as much the similar sceptical and new approach of descarte Indian thinkers like siromani started looking at both old and new ideas with a different perspective which tied the past with the future, gangesa is referred to as via antiqua where as siromani as via moderna as for the matter o fact siromani camp considered gangesa navya but siromani as navina (new within the new)<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Phillips|first=Stephen H.|editor1-first=Jonardon |editor1-last=Ganeri |date=2015-04-17|title=A Defeasibility Theory of Knowledge in Gaṅgeśa|url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199314621.013.32|journal=Oxford Handbooks Online|doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199314621.013.32}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Williams|first=Michael|editor1-first=Jonardon |editor1-last=Ganeri |date=2016-07-07|title=Raghunātha Śiromaṇi and the Examination of the Truth about the Categories|url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199314621.013.30|journal=Oxford Handbooks Online|doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199314621.013.30}}</ref> V N Jha argues that Navya-Nyaya language must also be introduced and adapted in mainstream philosophical and logical discourse, he claims that Navya-Nyaya theory of inference is more elaborate and complicated, with less ambiguity.<ref>{{Cite book|last1=Gaṅgeśa|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=g98MAAAAIAAJ|title=The logic of the intermediate casual link: containing the Sanskrit text of the Apūrvavāda of the Śabdakhaṇḍa of the Tattvacintāmaṇi of Gaṅgeśa with English translation and introduction|last2=Jha|first2=Vashishtha Narayan|date=1986|publisher=Sri Satguru Publications|isbn=978-81-7030-102-8|language=en}}</ref> |
|||
==See also== |
==See also== |
||
* [[Late modern philosophy]] |
* [[Late modern philosophy]] |
||
* [[Phases of modernity]] |
* [[Phases of modernity]] |
||
==Notes== |
|||
{{reflist|group=note}} |
|||
==Citations== |
==Citations== |
||
Line 99: | Line 78: | ||
== References == |
== References == |
||
* Ash, E. (2010). Introduction: Expertise and the Early Modern State. ''Osiris'', ''25''(1), |
* Ash, E. (2010). Introduction: Expertise and the Early Modern State. ''Osiris'', ''25''(1), 1–24. |
||
* Allhoff, F., Martinich, A., & Vaidya, A. (2007). ''Early modern philosophy''. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub. |
* Allhoff, F., Martinich, A., & Vaidya, A. (2007). ''Early modern philosophy''. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub. |
||
* Arblaster, P. (2017). Early Modern English Catholicism: Identity, Memory and Counter-Reformation. ''Reformation'', ''22''(2), 147–148. |
* Arblaster, P. (2017). Early Modern English Catholicism: Identity, Memory and Counter-Reformation. ''Reformation'', ''22''(2), 147–148. |
||
Line 107: | Line 86: | ||
* Broad, J. (2020). Early Modern Philosophy: A Perverse Thought Experiment | Blog of the APA. Retrieved 18 April 2021, from <nowiki>https://blog.apaonline.org/2020/10/21/early-modern-philosophy-a-perverse-thought-experiment/</nowiki> |
* Broad, J. (2020). Early Modern Philosophy: A Perverse Thought Experiment | Blog of the APA. Retrieved 18 April 2021, from <nowiki>https://blog.apaonline.org/2020/10/21/early-modern-philosophy-a-perverse-thought-experiment/</nowiki> |
||
* Brooks, T. (2013). In Defence of Political Theory: Impact and Opportunities. ''Political Studies Review'', ''11''(2), 209–215. |
* Brooks, T. (2013). In Defence of Political Theory: Impact and Opportunities. ''Political Studies Review'', ''11''(2), 209–215. |
||
* Carmichael, D. (1990). Hobbes on Natural Right in Society: The Leviathan Account. ''Canadian Journal Of Political Science'', ''23''(1), |
* Carmichael, D. (1990). Hobbes on Natural Right in Society: The Leviathan Account. ''Canadian Journal Of Political Science'', ''23''(1), 3–21. |
||
* Colilli, Julian (2016). "Jonathan Israel's Enlightenment: The Case of Giambattista Vico". ''Italica''. '''93''' (3): 469–493. {{ISSN|0021-3020}}. |
* Colilli, Julian (2016). "Jonathan Israel's Enlightenment: The Case of Giambattista Vico". ''Italica''. '''93''' (3): 469–493. {{ISSN|0021-3020}}. |
||
* Dickason, O., & Ellingson, T. (2002). The Myth of the Noble Savage. ''The Journal Of American History'', ''88''(4), 1499. |
* Dickason, O., & Ellingson, T. (2002). The Myth of the Noble Savage. ''The Journal Of American History'', ''88''(4), 1499. |
||
Line 121: | Line 100: | ||
* Huggett, N. (2018). Zeno's Paradoxes. In ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University. |
* Huggett, N. (2018). Zeno's Paradoxes. In ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University. |
||
* Joy, L., Copenhaver, B., & Schmitt, C. (1993). Renaissance Philosophy. ''The Philosophical Quarterly'', ''43''(173), 537. |
* Joy, L., Copenhaver, B., & Schmitt, C. (1993). Renaissance Philosophy. ''The Philosophical Quarterly'', ''43''(173), 537. |
||
* KATEB, G. (1989). Hobbes and the Irrationality of Politics. ''Political Theory'', ''17''(3), 355–391. doi |
* KATEB, G. (1989). Hobbes and the Irrationality of Politics. ''Political Theory'', ''17''(3), 355–391. {{doi|10.1177/0090591789017003001}} |
||
* Lærke, M., Smith, J., & Schliesser, E. (2013). ''Philosophy and its history''. London: Oxford University. |
* Lærke, M., Smith, J., & Schliesser, E. (2013). ''Philosophy and its history''. London: Oxford University. |
||
* May, L., & Kavka, G. (1989). Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. ''Noûs'', ''23''(4), 560. |
* May, L., & Kavka, G. (1989). Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. ''Noûs'', ''23''(4), 560. |
||
Line 140: | Line 119: | ||
* Rutherford, D. (2008). D. Rutherford (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. ''Cambridge University Press'', ''73''(4), 334–339. |
* Rutherford, D. (2008). D. Rutherford (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. ''Cambridge University Press'', ''73''(4), 334–339. |
||
* Salami, M. (2021). Philosophy has to be about more than white men. ''The Guardian''. Retrieved from <nowiki>https://www.theguardian.com/education/commentisfree/2015/mar/23/philosophy-white-men-university-courses</nowiki> |
* Salami, M. (2021). Philosophy has to be about more than white men. ''The Guardian''. Retrieved from <nowiki>https://www.theguardian.com/education/commentisfree/2015/mar/23/philosophy-white-men-university-courses</nowiki> |
||
* Sellars, J. (2020). RENAISSANCE HUMANISM AND PHILOSOPHY AS A WAY OF LIFE. ''Metaphilosophy'', ''51''( |
* Sellars, J. (2020). RENAISSANCE HUMANISM AND PHILOSOPHY AS A WAY OF LIFE. ''Metaphilosophy'', ''51''(2–3), 226–243. |
||
* Schmidt, James ( |
* Schmidt, James (2006–01). "What Enlightenment Was, What It Still Might Be, and Why Kant May Have Been Right After All". ''American Behavioral Scientist''. '''49''' (5): 647–663. |
||
* Smith, K. (2018). Descartes’ Life and Works. In ''Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy'' (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University. |
* Smith, K. (2018). Descartes’ Life and Works. In ''Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy'' (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University. |
||
* Spruyt, H. (2002). THEORIGINS, DEVELOPMENT, ANDPOSSIBLEDECLINE OF THEMODERNSTATE. ''Annual Review Of Political Science'', ''5''(1), 127–149. |
* Spruyt, H. (2002). THEORIGINS, DEVELOPMENT, ANDPOSSIBLEDECLINE OF THEMODERNSTATE. ''Annual Review Of Political Science'', ''5''(1), 127–149. |
||
Line 153: | Line 132: | ||
{{Philosophy topics}} |
{{Philosophy topics}} |
||
[[Category:Early |
[[Category:Early modern philosophy| ]] |
||
[[el:Φιλοσοφία των Νεότερων Χρόνων]] |
[[el:Φιλοσοφία των Νεότερων Χρόνων]] |
Latest revision as of 02:31, 12 December 2024
Part of a series on |
Philosophy |
---|
Early modern philosophy (also classical modern philosophy)[1][2] The early modern era of philosophy was a progressive movement of Western thought, exploring through theories and discourse such topics as mind and matter, is a period in the history of philosophy that overlaps with the beginning of the period known as modern philosophy. It succeeded the medieval era of philosophy. Early modern philosophy is usually thought to have occurred between the 16th and 18th centuries, though some philosophers and historians may put this period slightly earlier. During this time, influential philosophers included Descartes, Locke, Hume, and Kant, all of whom contributed to the current understanding of philosophy.
Overview
[edit]The early modern period in history is around c. 1500–1789, but the label "early modern philosophy" is typically used to refer to a narrower period of time.[3]
In the narrowest sense, the term is used to refer principally to the philosophy of the 17th century and 18th century, typically beginning with René Descartes. 17th-century philosophers typically included in such analyses are Thomas Hobbes, Blaise Pascal, Baruch Spinoza, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, and Isaac Newton. The 18th century, often known as the Age of Enlightenment, included such early modern figures as John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume.[2]
The term is sometimes used more broadly, including earlier thinkers from the 16th century such as Niccolò Machiavelli, Martin Luther, John Calvin, Michel de Montaigne, and Francis Bacon.[4] Some definitions also broaden the range of thinkers included under the "early modern" moniker, such as Voltaire, Giambattista Vico, Thomas Paine. By the broadest definition, the early modern period is said to have ended in 1804 with the death of Immanuel Kant. Considered in this way, the period extends from the last Renaissance philosophers to the final days of the Age of Enlightenment. Most scholars consider the period to begin with René Descartes’ Meditationes de Prima Philosophiae (Meditations on First Philosophy) in Paris in 1641 and conclude with the work of the German philosopher Immanuel Kant (Critique of Pure Reason) in the 1780s.[5]
At the time, various thinkers faced difficult philosophical challenges: reconciling the tenets of classical Aristotelian thought and Christian theology with the new technological advances that followed in the wake of Copernicus, Galileo, and Newton.[6] A modern mechanical image of the cosmos in which mathematically definable universal laws directed the motion of lifeless objects without the interference of something non-physical, specifically challenged established ways of thought about the mind, body and God. In response, philosophers, many of whom were involved in experimental advances, invented and perfected various perspectives on humans’ relationship to the cosmos.[7]
Three critical historical events that shaped Western thought profoundly were the Age of Discovery, the progress of modern science, and the Protestant reformation and its resulting civil wars.[8] The relationship between philosophy and scientific research was complicated, as many early modern scientists considered themselves philosophers, conflating the two disciplines.[9] These two fields would eventually separate. Contemporary philosophy's epistemological and methodological concerns about scientific certainty remained regardless of such a separation.[10]
The early modern intellectual era also contributed to the development of Western philosophy. New philosophical theories, such as the metaphysical, civic existence, epistemology, and rationalist thinking, were established.[11] There was a strong emphasis on the advancement and expansion of rationalism, which placed a premium on rationality, reasoning, and discovery to pursue reality.[12]
Enlightenment Period
[edit]The Enlightenment, also referred to as the Age of Enlightenment, was a philosophical movement that dominated the realm of ideas in 18th-century Europe. It was founded on the principle that reason is the fundamental source of power and legitimacy, and it promoted principles such as liberty, progress, tolerance, fraternity, constitutional governance, and church-state separation. The Enlightenment was defined by a focus on science and reductionism, as well as a growing suspicion of religious rigidity. The Enlightenment's ideals challenged the monarchy and the church, laying the groundwork for the political upheavals of the 18th and 19th centuries. According to French historians, the Age of Enlightenment began in 1715, the year Louis XIV died, and ended in 1789, the year of the French Revolution. According to some contemporary historians, the era begins in the 1620s, with the birth of the Scientific Revolution. However, during the first decades of the 18th century and the first decades of the 19th century, several national variations of the movement developed.
The Englishmen Francis Bacon and Thomas Hobbes, the Frenchman René Descartes, and the prominent natural philosophers of the Scientific Revolution, including Galileo Galilei, Johannes Kepler, and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, were significant 17th-century antecedents of the Enlightenment. Its origins are often ascribed to 1680s England, when Isaac Newton published his "Principia Mathematica" (1686) and John Locke wrote his "Essay Concerning Human Understanding" (1689)—two works that laid the groundwork for the Enlightenment's great advancements in science, mathematics, and philosophy.[13]
The Age Of Enlightenment was swiftly sweeping across Europe. In the late seventeenth century, scientists such as Isaac Newton and authors such as John Locke challenged the established order. Newton's principles of gravity and motion defined the universe in terms of natural principles that were independent of any spiritual source. Locke advocated the freedom of a people to replace a government that did not defend inherent rights to life, liberty, and property in the aftermath of England's political instability. People began to mistrust the possibility of a God capable of predestining human beings to everlasting damnation and empowering a despotic ruler to rule. These ideals would permanently alter Europe.
Major Enlightenment concepts
[edit]Europe had a burst of philosophical and scientific activity in the mid-18th century, challenging established theories and dogmas.[14] Voltaire and Jean-Jacques Rousseau headed the philosophic movement, arguing for a society founded on reason rather than religion and Catholic theology, for a new civic order based on natural law, and for science founded on experimentation and observation.[15] Montesquieu, a political philosopher, proposed the notion of a government's division of powers, which was enthusiastically accepted by the framers of the United States Constitution.[16]
Two separate schools of Enlightenment philosophy existed. Inspired by Spinoza's theory, the radical enlightenment argued for democracy, individual liberty, freedom of speech, and the abolition of religious authority.[17] A second, more moderate kind, championed by René Descartes, John Locke, Christian Wolff, and Isaac Newton, aimed to strike a balance between reform and old power and religious institutions.[18]
Science eventually began to dominate Enlightenment speech and thinking.[19] Numerous Enlightenment authors and intellectuals came from scientific backgrounds and equated scientific progress with the downfall of religion and conventional authority in favour of the growth of free speech and ideas.[20] In general, Enlightenment science placed a high premium on empiricism and logical reasoning, and was inextricably linked to the Enlightenment ideal of progression and development.[21] However, as was the case with the majority of Enlightenment ideals, the advantages of science were not widely recognized.[22]
The Enlightenment has traditionally been credited with laying the groundwork for current Western political and intellectual culture.[23] It ushered in a period of political modernization in the West, focused on democratic principles and institutions and resulting in the establishment of modern, liberal democracies. The fundamentals of European liberal thought include the individual right, natural equality of all men, separation of powers, the artificial nature of political order (which resulted in the later distinction between civil society and the state), the view that all legitimate political power must be "representative" and based on popular consent, and liberal interpretationism.[24]
Enlightenment-era criticism on religion was a reaction to Europe's previous century of religious turmoil.[25] Enlightenment intellectuals intended to limit organized religion's political dominance, so averting another period of intolerable religious violence.[26] Numerous unique concepts emerged, including deism (belief in God the Creator without reference to the Bible or other authoritative source) and atheism.[27] The latter was hotly debated but garnered few supporters. Many, like Voltaire, believed that without believing in a God who punishes wrong, society's moral order would be jeopardised.[28]
Characteristics
[edit]The early modern period arose from dramatic shifts in many fields of human endeavour. Among the most significant characteristics are the formalisation of science, the acceleration of scientific advancement, and the creation of secularised civic politics, law courts, and the nation-state.[29] There was some skepticism against traditional interpretive concepts associated with the modern era, such as the distinction between empiricists and rationalists, which represented a philosophical and historical shift away from ethics, political philosophy, and metaphysical epistemology.[30]
Individualism also emerged as a reaction to belief and authority, challenging the element of Christianity and Christianised philosophy united with whoever the desired political leader happened to be at the time.[31] The steady rise of the bourgeoisie would challenge the power of the Church and begin the journey towards the eventual separation of church and state. The political and economic situation of Modern Europe would have an influence on philosophical thought, mainly on ethics and political philosophy.[32]
The Scientific Revolution also gained legitimacy during this period. Early modern attempts to grapple with the philosophy of infinity focused on and discussed three fundamental disagreements about the infinite—differences that had their origins in the academic philosophical tradition.[33] Philosophers such as Leibniz and Spinoza used this distinction to distinguish God's qualitative infinity from the mathematically abstract concept of infinity.[34] Early modern thinkers differentiated between actual and potential infinity. Academic tradition has traditionally rejected the existence of actual infinities in the created world but has acknowledged potential infinities, following Aristotle's approach to Zeno's paradoxes.[35] Additionally, the advent of early modern thought was linked to changes in the period's intellectual and cultural context, such as the advancement of natural science, theological contradictions within and between the Catholic and Protestant churches, and the growth of the modern nation-state.[36]
Significant thinkers
[edit]Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Berkeley, Hume, Hobbes, and Kant, as well as philosophers such as Hugo Grotius, Pierre Gassendi, Antoine Arnauld, Nicolas Malebranche, Pierre Bayle, Samuel von Pufendorf, and Francis Hutcheson are all recognised as significant figures in early modern philosophy, for their discourses and theories developed throughout the various philosophical periods.
The political philosophy of natural law, developed by John Locke, was a common and significant concept in early modern thought. Natural law evolved into individual rights and subjective claims. Adding to Aristotle's already known philosophy, Locke suggested that the government give its citizens what they believe are fundamental and natural rights.[37] Thomas Hobbes, alternatively, asserted that natural law has a finite scope. Unchecked liberty led to a state of war where everybody struggled for life.[38] Hobbes encapsulated this state of violence in one of philosophy's most famous passages: "And the life of man, solitary, bad, nasty, brutish, and brief".[39] Thomas Hobbes' worldview concentrated on social and political order and how humans could coexist without danger or risk of civil war.[40]
Thomas Hobbes
[edit]Hobbes' moral and political theory includes a consideration of natural rights. Hobbes' natural rights notion also included man in a "state of nature". As he saw it, the basic natural (human) right was to use his power, as he will, to preserve his nature, which is to protect his life.[41]
Natural liberty is distinct from universal laws, which Hobbes referred to as precepts, or rules discovered by reason, which ban a man from doing something that will destroy his life or deprives him of the means to retain it.[42]
In Hobbes' view, life comprised just of freedoms and nothing else "Because of that, everyone has the right to anything, even to one another's body. Because of this, though, as long as inherent human rights to every commodity remain in place, there can be no long-term security for anybody."[43]
This would result in the condition called the "war of all against all," in which humans murder, steal, and enslave each other to remain alive. Hobbes theorised that human existence would be lonely, poor, ugly, brutish, and short in a state of chaos generated by unrestricted rights. As such, people would agree to give up many of their basic rights to build a political and civil society. Social contract theory was first articulated using this early argumentation.[44]
Natural or institutional laws are useless without first being established by a sovereign authority. Before you can talk about right and unjust, some coercive authority must compel folks to keep their promises. There is no such coercive force before the establishment of the state.[45] This coercive State would, in Hobbes' view, have the right to confiscate property in return for a guarantee of citizens' safety from one another and from foreign intervention.
According to social contract theory, "inalienable rights" are those rights that can't be relinquished by people to the sovereign.[46] These inherent rights were believed to be law-independent. Only the strongest could use their privileges in the state of nature.[47] Thereby, individuals give up their natural rights to get protection, and thus have the legal rights conferred by the power to do so.[48]
Many historical justifications for slavery and illiberal governance include consensual arrangements to relinquish inherent rights to freedom and self-determination. De facto inalienability arguments supplied the foundation for the anti-slavery movement to argue against all involuntary enslavement, not only slavery explicitly defined as such. An agreement to unlawfully divide a right would be void of law. Similarly, the argument was used by the democratic movement to reject explicit or implicit social covenants of subjection (e.g., pactum subjectionis) that subjugate a people, for example, in Leviathan by Thomas Hobbes. According to Ernst Cassirer:
There is, at least, one right that cannot be ceded or abandoned: the right to personality...They charged the great logician [Hobbes] with a contradiction in terms. If a man could give up his personality he would cease being a moral being. … There is no pactum subjectionis, no act of submission by which man can give up the state of free agent and enslave himself. For by such an act of renunciation he would give up that very character which constitutes his nature and essence: he would lose his humanity.[49]
Influence
[edit]Until the twenty-first century, standard accounts of early modern philosophy and traditional survey courses in Anglo-Saxon universities—presented histories dominated by Descartes, Leibniz, Locke, Spinoza, Berkeley, Hume, and Kant.[50]
Early modern theory has significantly impacted many modern developments, one of which is political philosophy. American political philosopher A. John Simmons examined two interrelated transitions in the early modern period. The first is a metaphysical contrast between political naturalism, which holds that human beings are political by birth, and political anti-naturalism, which holds that humankind's natural state is apolitical.[51] The second is the historical shift from "complex, bureaucratic systems with intertwined religious and contractual relationships" to political cultures that "take the form of independent, territorial states".[52] Observing how these transformations occur is important as the ideas advanced by early modern political theorists played an important role in the creation of political institutions that exist today.[53]
The evolution of early modern philosophy has been recognized as inextricably linked to developments in the period's intellectual and cultural environment through important developments in science, the Catholic and Protestant churches, and the rise of the new modern nation state.[54]
See also
[edit]Citations
[edit]- ^ Jeffrey Tlumak, Classical Modern Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction, Routledge, 2006, p. xi: "[Classical Modern Philosophy] is a guide through the systems of the seven brilliant seventeenth- and eighteenth-century European philosophers most regularly taught in college Modern Philosophy courses".
- ^ a b Richard Schacht, Classical Modern Philosophers: Descartes to Kant, Routledge, 2013, p. 1: "Seven men have come to stand out from all of their counterparts in what has come to be known as the 'modern' period in the history of philosophy (i.e., the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries): Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume and Kant".
- ^ Marshall Berman. 1982. All That Is Solid Melts into Air: The Experience of Modernity. New York: Simon and Schuster. ISBN 0-671-24602-X. London: Verso. pp. 16–17. ISBN 0-86091-785-1. Paperback reprint New York: Viking Penguin, 1988. ISBN 0-14-010962-5.
- ^ Brian Leiter (ed.), The Future for Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 44 n. 2.
- ^ Smith, Kurt (2018). "Descartes' Life and Works". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2021-05-19.
- ^ Levers, Merry-Jo D. (2013-01-01). "Philosophical Paradigms, Grounded Theory, and Perspectives on Emergence". SAGE Open. 3 (4): 2158244013517243. doi:10.1177/2158244013517243. ISSN 2158-2440.
- ^ Bica, Daian (2020-12-25). "Thinking with Mechanisms: Mechanical Philosophy and Early Modern Science". Journal of Early Modern Studies. 9: 133–141. doi:10.5840/jems2020916. S2CID 235002069. Retrieved 2021-05-19.
- ^ Garber, Daniel; Rutherford, Donald, eds. (2018). Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, Volume VIII. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198829294.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-186788-0.
{{cite book}}
:|journal=
ignored (help) - ^ Wu, Kun (December 2016). "The Interaction and Convergence of the Philosophy and Science of Information". Philosophies. 1 (3): 228–244. doi:10.3390/philosophies1030228.
- ^ Garber, Daniel; Rutherford, Donald, eds. (2012). Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy Volume VI. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199659593.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-174521-8.
{{cite book}}
:|journal=
ignored (help) - ^ Beatty, Joy E.; Leigh, Jennifer S. A.; Dean, Kathy Lund (2009-02-01). "Philosophy Rediscovered: Exploring the Connections Between Teaching Philosophies, Educational Philosophies, and Philosophy". Journal of Management Education. 33 (1): 99–114. doi:10.1177/1052562907310557. ISSN 1052-5629. S2CID 146478936.
- ^ Berchielli, Laura (2020). "Introduction: Ideas of Space and Their Relation to Experience in Early Modern Philosophy". In Berchielli, Laura (ed.). Empiricist Theories of Space. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. Vol. 54. Cham: Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–48. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-57620-2_1. ISBN 978-3-030-57619-6. S2CID 229272121. Retrieved 2021-05-19.
- ^ Schmidt, James (January 2006). "What Enlightenment Was, What It Still Might Be, and Why Kant May Have Been Right After All". American Behavioral Scientist. 49 (5): 647–663. doi:10.1177/0002764205282215. hdl:2144/3877. ISSN 0002-7642. S2CID 144140862.
- ^ Nickles, Thomas (2017). "Scientific Revolutions". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
- ^ "Enlightenment". encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
- ^ Douglass, Robin (2012-10-01). "Montesquieu and Modern Republicanism". Political Studies. 60 (3): 703–719. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2011.00932.x. ISSN 0032-3217. S2CID 142651026.
- ^ Colilli, Julian (2016). "Jonathan Israel's Enlightenment: The Case of Giambattista Vico". Italica. 93 (3): 469–493. ISSN 0021-3020. JSTOR 44504589.
- ^ Nicolaidis, Efthymios; Delli, Eudoxie; Livanos, Nikolaos; Tampakis, Kostas; Vlahakis, George (2016-09-20). "Science and Orthodox Christianity: An Overview". Isis. 107 (3): 542–566. doi:10.1086/688704. ISSN 0021-1753. PMID 28707856. S2CID 34598125.
- ^ Domínguez, Juan Pablo (2017-05-19). "Introduction: Religious toleration in the Age of Enlightenment". History of European Ideas. 43 (4): 273–287. doi:10.1080/01916599.2016.1203590. ISSN 0191-6599.
- ^ De Cruz, Helen (2019). "Religion and Science". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
- ^ Desai, Vandana; Potter, Rob (2014-03-21). The Companion to Development Studies. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-05159-5.
- ^ Reiss, Julian; Sprenger, Jan (2020). "Scientific Objectivity". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
- ^ Zafirovski, Milan (2011). The Enlightenment and Its Effects on Modern Society. New York, NY: Springer New York. doi:10.1007/978-1-4419-7387-0. ISBN 978-1-4419-7386-3.
- ^ Müßig, Ulrike (2018). "A New Order of the Ages. Normativity and Precedence". In Müßig, Ulrike (ed.). Reconsidering Constitutional Formation II Decisive Constitutional Normativity: From Old Liberties to New Precedence. Studies in the History of Law and Justice. Vol. 12. Cham: Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–97. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-73037-0_1. ISBN 978-3-319-73037-0.
- ^ sydney.primo.exlibrisgroup.com https://sydney.primo.exlibrisgroup.com/discovery/fulldisplay?docid=cdi_jstor_primary_43572323&context=PC&vid=61USYD_INST:sydney&lang=en&search_scope=MyInst_and_CI&adaptor=Primo%20Central&tab=Everything&query=any,contains,religious%20turmoil%20in%20europe%20during%20the%20early%20modern%20period&offset=0. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
{{cite web}}
: Missing or empty|title=
(help) - ^ Collins, Jeffrey R. (2009). "Redeeming the Enlightenment: New Histories of Religious Toleration". The Journal of Modern History. 81 (3): 607–636. doi:10.1086/599275. ISSN 0022-2801. JSTOR 10.1086/599275. S2CID 143375411.
- ^ Draper, Paul (2017). "Atheism and Agnosticism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
- ^ "Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern Word-Gaudium et Spes". vatican.va. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
- ^ "D. Rutherford (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy". Theoria. 73 (4): 334–339. 2007. doi:10.1111/j.1755-2567.2007.tb01212.x. ISSN 1755-2567.
- ^ Sellars, John (2020). "Renaissance Humanism and Philosophy as a Way of Life". Metaphilosophy. 51 (2–3): 226–243. doi:10.1111/meta.12409. ISSN 1467-9973.
- ^ Ash, Eric H. (2010). "Introduction: Expertise and the Early Modern State". Osiris. 25 (1): 1–24. doi:10.1086/657254. ISSN 0369-7827. JSTOR 10.1086/657254. S2CID 144330049.
- ^ "Hobbes, Thomas: Moral and Political Philosophy | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2021-05-19.
- ^ Schmitt, C. B.; Skinner, Quentin; Kessler, Eckhard; Kraye, Jill, eds. (1988). The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521251044. ISBN 978-0-521-25104-4. S2CID 170086821.
- ^ Schechtman, Anat (2019-10-01). "Three Infinities in Early Modern Philosophy". Mind. 128 (512): 1117–1147. doi:10.1093/mind/fzy034. ISSN 0026-4423.
- ^ Huggett, Nick (2002-04-30). "Zeno's Paradoxes". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
{{cite journal}}
: Cite journal requires|journal=
(help) - ^ Spruyt, Hendrik (2002-06-01). "The origins, development, and possible decline of the modern state". Annual Review of Political Science. 5 (1): 127–149. doi:10.1146/annurev.polisci.5.101501.145837. ISSN 1094-2939.
- ^ Uzgalis, William (2001-09-02). "John Locke". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
{{cite journal}}
: Cite journal requires|journal=
(help) - ^ Schmaltz, Tad M. (2002). Radical Cartesianism: The French Reception of Descartes. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-43425-6.
- ^ Lloyd, Sharon A.; Sreedhar, Susanne (2002-02-12). "Hobbes's Moral and Political Philosophy".
{{cite journal}}
: Cite journal requires|journal=
(help) - ^ Hampton, Jean (1988). Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-316-58325-8.
- ^ Carmichael, D. J. C. (March 1990). "Hobbes on Natural Right in Society: The Leviathan Account*". Canadian Journal of Political Science/Revue Canadienne de Science Politique. 23 (1): 3–21. doi:10.1017/S0008423900011598. ISSN 1744-9324. S2CID 154964034.
- ^ Estrada, Fernando (2012). "El Leviathan de Thomas Hobbes (The Leviathan of Thomas Hobbes)". SSRN Electronic Journal. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2127939. ISSN 1556-5068.
- ^ McCrudden, Christopher (2008-09-01). "Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights". European Journal of International Law. 19 (4): 655–724. doi:10.1093/ejil/chn043. ISSN 0938-5428.
- ^ Minogue, K. R. (October 1970). "The Logic of Leviathan". Philosophical Books. 11 (3): 10–12. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0149.1970.tb00060.x.
- ^ Skinner, Quentin (1966). "The Ideological Context of Hobbes's Political Thought". The Historical Journal. 9 (3): 286–317. doi:10.1017/S0018246X66000014. ISSN 0018-246X. JSTOR 2637983. S2CID 248825400.
- ^ Scott, John T. (September 2000). "The Sovereignless State and Locke's Language of Obligation". American Political Science Review. 94 (3): 547–561. doi:10.2307/2585830. ISSN 0003-0554. JSTOR 2585830. S2CID 144108638.
- ^ Bruner, Justin P. (2020-03-01). "Locke, Nozick and the state of nature". Philosophical Studies. 177 (3): 705–726. doi:10.1007/s11098-018-1201-9. ISSN 1573-0883. S2CID 171478513.
- ^ Tuckness, Alex (2020). "Locke's Political Philosophy". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2021-06-02.
- ^ Ellerman, David (September 2010). "Inalienable Rights: A Litmus Test for Liberal Theories of Justice". Law and Philosophy. 29 (5): 571–599. doi:10.1007/s10982-010-9076-8. ISSN 0167-5249. S2CID 52028430.
- ^ Broad, Jacqueline (2020-10-21). "Early Modern Philosophy: A Perverse Thought Experiment". Blog of the APA. Retrieved 2021-05-19.
- ^ Caro, Mario, 20 /21 Jh [Hrsg ] De; Caro, Mario De; Macarthur, David; Macarthur, Professor David; MacArthur, Douglas (2004). Naturalism in Question. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-01295-0.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link) CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link) - ^ "The Making of the Modern World". E-International Relations. 2016-12-26. Retrieved 2021-05-19.
- ^ Brooks, Thom (2013-05-01). "In Defence of Political Theory: Impact and Opportunities". Political Studies Review. 11 (2): 209–215. doi:10.1111/1478-9302.12007. ISSN 1478-9299.
- ^ Loewenstein, David; Shell, Alison (2019-07-03). "Early Modern Literature and England's Long Reformation". Reformation. 24 (2): 53–58. doi:10.1080/13574175.2019.1665264. ISSN 1357-4175.
References
[edit]- Ash, E. (2010). Introduction: Expertise and the Early Modern State. Osiris, 25(1), 1–24.
- Allhoff, F., Martinich, A., & Vaidya, A. (2007). Early modern philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub.
- Arblaster, P. (2017). Early Modern English Catholicism: Identity, Memory and Counter-Reformation. Reformation, 22(2), 147–148.
- Beatty, J., Leigh, J., & Dean, K. (2008). Philosophy Rediscovered. Journal Of Management Education, 33(1), 99–114.
- Bica, D. (2020). Thinking with Mechanisms: Mechanical Philosophy and Early Modern Science. Journal Of Early Modern Studies, 9(1), 133–141.
- Bojanowski, J. (2017). Thinking about cases: Applying Kant's universal law formula. European Journal Of Philosophy, 26(4), 1253–1268.
- Broad, J. (2020). Early Modern Philosophy: A Perverse Thought Experiment | Blog of the APA. Retrieved 18 April 2021, from https://blog.apaonline.org/2020/10/21/early-modern-philosophy-a-perverse-thought-experiment/
- Brooks, T. (2013). In Defence of Political Theory: Impact and Opportunities. Political Studies Review, 11(2), 209–215.
- Carmichael, D. (1990). Hobbes on Natural Right in Society: The Leviathan Account. Canadian Journal Of Political Science, 23(1), 3–21.
- Colilli, Julian (2016). "Jonathan Israel's Enlightenment: The Case of Giambattista Vico". Italica. 93 (3): 469–493. ISSN 0021-3020.
- Dickason, O., & Ellingson, T. (2002). The Myth of the Noble Savage. The Journal Of American History, 88(4), 1499.
- Domínguez, Juan Pablo (2017-05-19). "Introduction: Religious toleration in the Age of Enlightenment". History of European Ideas. 43 (4): 273–287. doi:10.1080/01916599.2016.1203590. ISSN 0191-6599.
- Douglass, Robin (2012-10-01). "Montesquieu and Modern Republicanism". Political Studies. 60 (3): 703–719. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2011.00932.x. ISSN 0032-3217.
- Desai, Vandana; Potter, Rob (2014-03-21). The Companion to Development Studies. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-05159-5.
- De Cruz, Helen (2019), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), "Religion and Science", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-05-27
- Early Modern Philosophy: Essential Readings with Commentary, ed. by Aloysius Martinich, Fritz Allhoff, Anand Vaidya (2006).
- Early Modern Philosophy: Mind, Matter, and Metaphysics, ed. by Christia Mercer and Eileen O'Neill (2005).
- "Enlightenment | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
- Estrada, F. (2012). El Leviathan de Thomas Hobbes (The Leviathan of Thomas Hobbes). SSRN Electronic Journal.
- Garber, D., & Nadler, S. (2005). Oxford studies in early modern philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Huggett, N. (2018). Zeno's Paradoxes. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University.
- Joy, L., Copenhaver, B., & Schmitt, C. (1993). Renaissance Philosophy. The Philosophical Quarterly, 43(173), 537.
- KATEB, G. (1989). Hobbes and the Irrationality of Politics. Political Theory, 17(3), 355–391. doi:10.1177/0090591789017003001
- Lærke, M., Smith, J., & Schliesser, E. (2013). Philosophy and its history. London: Oxford University.
- May, L., & Kavka, G. (1989). Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. Noûs, 23(4), 560.
- Matthew Hoye, J. (2019). Natural Justice, Law, and Virtue in Hobbes's Leviathan. Hobbes Studies, 32(2), 179–208.
- Lenz, M., & Waldow, A. (2013). Contemporary perspectives on early modern philosophy (1st ed., pp. 19–43). Sydney: The University of Sydney.
- Levers, M. (2013). Philosophical Paradigms, Grounded Theory, and Perspectives on Emergence. SAGE Open, 3(4).
- Lloyd, S., & Sreedhar, S. (2018). Hobbes's Moral and Political Philosophy. In Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University.
- Müßig, Ulrike (2018), Müßig, Ulrike (ed.), "A New Order of the Ages. Normativity and Precedence", Reconsidering Constitutional Formation II Decisive Constitutional Normativity: From Old Liberties to New Precedence, Studies in the History of Law and Justice, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 1–97, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-73037-0_1, ISBN 978-3-319-73037-0, retrieved 2021-05-27
- Mori, N. (2017). David Hume on Morals, Politics, and Society ed. by Angela Coventry and Andrew Valls. Hume Studies, 43(2), 110–112.
- Murphy, B. (2010). RATIONALISM AND EMPIRICISM: WILL THE DEBATE EVER END?. Think, 9(24), 35–46.
- Nachtomy, O., & Reed, R. (2019). INFINITY IN EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY. [New York City]: SPRINGER.
- Nicolaidis, Efthymios; Delli, Eudoxie; Livanos, Nikolaos; Tampakis, Kostas; Vlahakis, George (2016-09-20). "Science and Orthodox Christianity: An Overview". Isis. 107 (3): 542–566. doi:10.1086/688704. ISSN 0021-1753.
- Nicolas Rasmussen, N.A, & Catherine Wilson, C.W. (1997). "The Invisible World: Early Modern Philosophy And The Invention Of The Microscope.". Contemporary Sociology 25 (1): 123.
- Nickles, Thomas (2017), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), "Scientific Revolutions", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-05-27
- Nimbalkar, N. (2011). John locke on personal identityFNx08. Mens Sana Monographs, 9(1), 268.
- Reiss, Julian; Sprenger, Jan (2020), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), "Scientific Objectivity", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-05-27
- Rutherford, D. (2007). The Cambridge companion to early modern philosophy (1st ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Rutherford, D. (2008). D. Rutherford (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 73(4), 334–339.
- Salami, M. (2021). Philosophy has to be about more than white men. The Guardian. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian.com/education/commentisfree/2015/mar/23/philosophy-white-men-university-courses
- Sellars, J. (2020). RENAISSANCE HUMANISM AND PHILOSOPHY AS A WAY OF LIFE. Metaphilosophy, 51(2–3), 226–243.
- Schmidt, James (2006–01). "What Enlightenment Was, What It Still Might Be, and Why Kant May Have Been Right After All". American Behavioral Scientist. 49 (5): 647–663.
- Smith, K. (2018). Descartes’ Life and Works. In Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University.
- Spruyt, H. (2002). THEORIGINS, DEVELOPMENT, ANDPOSSIBLEDECLINE OF THEMODERNSTATE. Annual Review Of Political Science, 5(1), 127–149.
- Uzgalis, W. (2018). John Locke. In Stanford Encyclopaedia Of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University.
- Wilson, M. (2016). Ideas and Mechanism (2nd ed.). Newark: Princeton University.
- Wu, K. (2016). The Interaction and Convergence of the Philosophy and Science of Information. Philosophies, 1(3), 228–244.