Jump to content

Negative responsiveness: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
mNo edit summary
 
(32 intermediate revisions by 11 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{DEFAULTSORT:Monotonicity Criterion}}
[[Category:Electoral system criteria]]
[[Category:Electoral system criteria]]
{{Short description|Property of electoral systems}}{{Electoral systems sidebar|expanded=Paradox}}
{{Short description|Property of electoral systems}}{{Electoral systems sidebar|expanded=Paradox}}
[[File:IRV_Yee.svg|alt=A diagram showing who would win an IRV election for different electorates. The win region for each candidate is erratic, with random pixels dotting the image and jagged, star-shaped (convex) regions occupying much of the image. Moving the electorate to the left can cause a right-wing candidate to win, and vice versa.|thumb|300x300px|A 4-candidate [https://electowiki.org/wiki/Yee_diagram Yee diagram] under IRV. The diagram shows who would win an IRV election if the electorate is centered at a particular point. Moving the electorate to the left can cause a right-wing candidate to win, and vice versa. Black lines show the [[Voronoi diagram|optimal solution]] (achieved by [[Condorcet method|Condorcet]] or [[Score voting|score]] voting).]]
[[File:IRV_Yee.svg|alt=A diagram showing who would win an IRV election for different electorates. The win region for each candidate is erratic, with random pixels dotting the image and jagged, star-shaped (convex) regions occupying much of the image. Moving the electorate to the left can cause a right-wing candidate to win, and vice versa.|thumb|300x300px|A 4-candidate Yee diagram under IRV. The diagram shows who would win an IRV election if the electorate is centered at a particular point. Moving the electorate to the left can cause a right-wing candidate to win, and vice versa. Black lines show the [[Voronoi diagram|optimal solution]] (achieved by [[Condorcet method|Condorcet]] or [[Score voting|score]] voting).]]
In [[Social choice theory|social choice]], '''perversity''',<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Doron |first1=Gideon |last2=Kronick |first2=Richard |date=1977 |title=Single Transferrable Vote: An Example of a Perverse Social Choice Function |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2110496 |journal=American Journal of Political Science |volume=21 |issue=2 |pages=303–311 |doi=10.2307/2110496 |issn=0092-5853 |jstor=2110496}}</ref> '''negative responsiveness''',<ref>{{Cite journal |last=May |first=Kenneth O. |date=1952 |title=A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decision |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/1907651 |journal=Econometrica |volume=20 |issue=4 |pages=680–684 |doi=10.2307/1907651 |issn=0012-9682 |jstor=1907651}}</ref>'''<ref name=":4222">{{Cite book |last=Pukelsheim |first=Friedrich |url=http://archive.org/details/proportionalrepr0000puke |title=Proportional representation: apportionment methods and their applications |date=2014 |publisher=Cham; New York : Springer |others=Internet Archive |isbn=978-3-319-03855-1}}</ref>''' or the '''additional support paradox<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal |last=Felsenthal |first=Dan S. |date=April 2010 |title=Review of paradoxes afflicting various voting procedures where one out of m candidates (m ≥ 2) must be elected |url=https://eprints.lse.ac.uk/27685/ |language=en |location=GBR |pages=1–52}}</ref>''' is a [[Pathological (mathematics)#In voting and social choice|pathological behavior]] of some [[Electoral system|voting rules]], where a candidate loses as a result of having "too much support" from some voters, or wins because they had "too much opposition". In other words, increasing (decreasing) a candidate's [[Ranked voting|ranking]] or [[Rated voting|rating]] causes that candidate to lose (win),<ref name=":0" /> contrary to common sense. Electoral systems that do not exhibit perversity are said to satisfy the '''positive response''' or [[Monotonic function|'''monotonicity''']] '''criterion'''.<ref name="Woodall-Monotonicity222">D R Woodall, [http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE6/P4.HTM "Monotonicity and Single-Seat Election Rules"], ''[[Voting matters]]'', Issue 6, 1996</ref>
In [[Social choice theory|social choice]], the '''negative responsiveness''',<ref>{{Cite journal |last=May |first=Kenneth O. |date=1952 |title=A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decision |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/1907651 |journal=Econometrica |volume=20 |issue=4 |pages=680–684 |doi=10.2307/1907651 |issn=0012-9682 |jstor=1907651}}</ref>'''<ref name=":4222">{{Cite book |last=Pukelsheim |first=Friedrich |url=http://archive.org/details/proportionalrepr0000puke |title=Proportional representation: apportionment methods and their applications |date=2014 |publisher=Cham; New York : Springer |others=Internet Archive |isbn=978-3-319-03855-1}}</ref>''' '''perversity''',<ref name="jstor.org">{{Cite journal |last1=Doron |first1=Gideon |last2=Kronick |first2=Richard |date=1977 |title=Single Transferrable Vote: An Example of a Perverse Social Choice Function |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2110496 |journal=American Journal of Political Science |volume=21 |issue=2 |pages=303–311 |doi=10.2307/2110496 |issn=0092-5853 |jstor=2110496}}</ref> or '''additional support paradox<ref name=":0">{{Cite web <!--Is this a conference?--> |last=Felsenthal |first=Dan S. |date=April 2010 |title=Review of paradoxes afflicting various voting procedures where one out of m candidates (m ≥ 2) must be elected |url=https://eprints.lse.ac.uk/27685/ |language=en |location=GBR |pages=1–52}}</ref>''' is a [[Pathological (mathematics)#In voting and social choice|pathological behavior]] of some [[Electoral system|voting rules]], where a candidate loses as a result of having "too much support" from some voters, or wins because they had "too much opposition". In other words, increasing (decreasing) a candidate's [[Ranked voting|ranking]] or [[Rated voting|rating]] causes that candidate to lose (win).<ref name=":0" /> Electoral systems that do not exhibit perversity are said to satisfy the '''positive response''' or [[Monotonic function|''monotonicity'']] ''criterion''.<ref name="Woodall-Monotonicity222">D R Woodall, [http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE6/P4.HTM "Monotonicity and Single-Seat Election Rules"], ''[[Voting matters]]'', Issue 6, 1996</ref>


Perversity is often described by [[Social choice theory|social choice theorists]] as an exceptionally severe kind of [[Pathological (mathematics)#In voting and social choice|electoral pathology]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Felsenthal |first1=Dan S. |last2=Tideman |first2=Nicolaus |date=2014-01-01 |title=Interacting double monotonicity failure with direction of impact under five voting methods |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0165489613000723 |journal=Mathematical Social Sciences |volume=67 |pages=57–66 |doi=10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2013.08.001 |issn=0165-4896}}</ref><ref name=":12">{{Cite book |last=Arrow |first=Kenneth J. |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.12987/9780300186987 |title=Social Choice and Individual Values |date=2017-12-13 |isbn=978-0-300-18698-7 |doi=10.12987/9780300186987 |quote=Since we are trying to describe social welfare and not some sort of illfare, we must assume that the social welfare function is such that the social ordering responds positively to alterations in individual values, or at least not negatively. Hence, if one alternative social state rises or remains still in the ordering of every individual without any other change in those orderings, we expect that it rises, or at least does not fall, in the social ordering.}}</ref> Systems that allow for perverse response can create situations where a voter's ballot has a reversed effect on the election, thus treating the [[Social welfare function|well-being of some voters]] as "less than worthless".<ref name=":12" /> Similar arguments have led to constitutional prohibitions on such systems as violating the right to [[One man, one vote|equal and direct suffrage]].<ref name=":42322">{{Cite book |last=Pukelsheim |first=Friedrich |url=http://archive.org/details/proportionalrepr0000puke |title=Proportional representation : apportionment methods and their applications |date=2014 |publisher=Cham; New York : Springer |others=Internet Archive |isbn=978-3-319-03855-1}}</ref><ref name=":0322">{{Cite news |last=dpa |date=2013-02-22 |title=Bundestag beschließt neues Wahlrecht |url=https://www.zeit.de/politik/deutschland/2013-02/bundestag-wahlrecht-beschluss |access-date=2024-05-02 |work=Die Zeit |language=de-DE |issn=0044-2070}}</ref> Negative response is often cited as an example of a [[perverse incentive]], as voting rules with perverse response incentivize politicians to take unpopular or [[Center squeeze|extreme]] positions in an attempt to shed excess votes.
Perversity is often described by [[Social choice theory|social choice theorists]] as an exceptionally severe kind of [[Pathological (mathematics)#In voting and social choice|electoral pathology]].<ref name="Felsenthal-severe">{{Cite journal |last1=Felsenthal |first1=Dan S. |last2=Tideman |first2=Nicolaus |date=2014-01-01 |title=Interacting double monotonicity failure with direction of impact under five voting methods |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0165489613000723 |journal=Mathematical Social Sciences |volume=67 |pages=57–66 |doi=10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2013.08.001 |issn=0165-4896 |quote=it is generally agreed among social choice theorists that a voting method that is susceptible to any type of monotonicity failure suffers from a particularly serious defect.}}</ref> Systems that allow for perverse response can create situations where a voter's ballot has a reversed effect on the election, thus treating the [[Social welfare function|well-being of some voters]] as "less than worthless".<ref name="Arrow">{{Cite book |last=Arrow |first=Kenneth J. |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.12987/9780300186987 |title=Social Choice and Individual Values |date=2017-12-13 |isbn=978-0-300-18698-7 |doi=10.12987/9780300186987 |p=25 |quote=Since we are trying to describe social welfare and not some sort of illfare, we must assume that the social welfare function is such that the social ordering responds positively to alterations in individual values, or at least not negatively. Hence, if one alternative social state rises or remains still in the ordering of every individual without any other change in those orderings, we expect that it rises, or at least does not fall, in the social ordering.}}</ref> Similar arguments have led to constitutional prohibitions on such systems as violating the right to [[One man, one vote|equal and direct suffrage]].<ref name=":42322">{{Cite book |last=Pukelsheim |first=Friedrich |url=http://archive.org/details/proportionalrepr0000puke |title=Proportional representation : apportionment methods and their applications |date=2014 |publisher=Cham; New York : Springer |others=Internet Archive |isbn=978-3-319-03855-1}}</ref><ref name=":0322">{{Cite news |last=dpa |date=2013-02-22 |title=Bundestag beschließt neues Wahlrecht |url=https://www.zeit.de/politik/deutschland/2013-02/bundestag-wahlrecht-beschluss |access-date=2024-05-02 |work=Die Zeit |language=de-DE |issn=0044-2070}}</ref> Negative response is often cited as an example of a [[perverse incentive]], as voting rules with perverse response incentivize politicians to take unpopular or [[Center squeeze|extreme]] positions in an attempt to shed excess votes.


Most [[Ranked voting|ranked methods]] (including [[Borda count|Borda]] and all common [[Round-robin voting|round-robin rules]]) satisfy positive response,<ref name="Woodall-Monotonicity222" /> as do all common [[rated voting]] methods (including [[Approval voting|approval]], [[Highest median voting rules|highest medians]], and [[Score voting|score]]).{{NoteTag|Apart from majority judgment, these systems satisfy an even stronger form of positive responsiveness: if there is a tie, any increase in a candidate's rating will break the tie in that candidate's favor.}}
Most [[Ranked voting|ranked methods]] (including [[Borda count|Borda]] and all common [[Round-robin voting|round-robin rules]]) satisfy positive response,<ref name="Woodall-Monotonicity222" /> as do all common [[rated voting]] methods (including [[Approval voting|approval]], [[Highest median voting rules|highest medians]], and [[Score voting|score]]).{{NoteTag|Apart from majority judgment, these systems satisfy an even stronger form of positive responsiveness: if there is a tie, any increase in a candidate's rating will break the tie in that candidate's favor.}}


Perversity occurs in [[instant-runoff voting]],<ref name=":3222">{{Cite journal |last1=Ornstein |first1=Joseph T. |last2=Norman |first2=Robert Z. |date=2014-10-01 |title=Frequency of monotonicity failure under Instant Runoff Voting: estimates based on a spatial model of elections |journal=Public Choice |language=en |volume=161 |issue=1–2 |pages=1–9 |doi=10.1007/s11127-013-0118-2 |issn=0048-5829 |s2cid=30833409}}</ref> the [[single transferable vote]],<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Doron |first1=Gideon |last2=Kronick |first2=Richard |date=1977 |title=Single Transferrable Vote: An Example of a Perverse Social Choice Function |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2110496 |journal=American Journal of Political Science |volume=21 |issue=2 |pages=303–311 |doi=10.2307/2110496 |issn=0092-5853 |jstor=2110496}}</ref> and [[Quota method|quota-based apportionment methods]].<ref name=":4222" /> The paradox is especially common in [[Ranked-choice voting|ranked-choice voting (RCV-IRV)]] and the [[two-round system]],<ref name=":332">{{Cite journal |last1=Ornstein |first1=Joseph T. |last2=Norman |first2=Robert Z. |date=2014-10-01 |title=Frequency of monotonicity failure under Instant Runoff Voting: estimates based on a spatial model of elections |journal=Public Choice |language=en |volume=161 |issue=1–2 |pages=1–9 |doi=10.1007/s11127-013-0118-2 |issn=0048-5829 |s2cid=30833409}}</ref> a behavior which causes the rule [[Center squeeze|to favor extremists]].<ref name=":83222">{{Cite journal |last1=McGann |first1=Anthony J. |last2=Koetzle |first2=William |last3=Grofman |first3=Bernard |date=2002 |title=How an Ideologically Concentrated Minority Can Trump a Dispersed Majority: Nonmedian Voter Results for Plurality, Run-off, and Sequential Elimination Elections |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/3088418 |journal=American Journal of Political Science |volume=46 |issue=1 |pages=134–147 |doi=10.2307/3088418 |issn=0092-5853 |jstor=3088418 |quote=}}</ref> The [[Maximal lotteries|randomized Condorcet method]] can violate monotonicity in the case of [[Condorcet cycle|cyclic ties]].
Perversity occurs in [[instant-runoff voting]] (IRV),<ref name="Ornstein">{{Cite journal |last1=Ornstein |first1=Joseph T. |last2=Norman |first2=Robert Z. |date=2014-10-01 |title=Frequency of monotonicity failure under Instant Runoff Voting: estimates based on a spatial model of elections |journal=Public Choice |language=en |volume=161 |issue=1–2 |pages=1–9 |doi=10.1007/s11127-013-0118-2 |issn=0048-5829 |s2cid=30833409}}</ref> the [[single transferable vote]],<ref name="jstor.org"/> and [[Quota method|quota-based apportionment methods]].<ref name=":4222" /> According to statistical culture models of elections, the paradox is especially common in RCV/IRV and the [[two-round system]].{{Citation needed|date=October 2024}} The [[Maximal lotteries|randomized Condorcet method]] can violate monotonicity in the case of [[Condorcet cycle|cyclic ties]].


The [[participation criterion]] is a closely-related, but different, concept. While positive responsiveness deals with a voter changing their opinion (or vote), participation deals with situations where a voter choosing to ''cast'' a ballot has a reversed effect on the election.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Dančišin |first=Vladimír |date=2017-01-01 |title=No-show paradox in Slovak party-list proportional system |url=https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/humaff-2017-0002/html?lang=en |journal=Human Affairs |language=en |volume=27 |issue=1 |pages=15–21 |doi=10.1515/humaff-2017-0002 |issn=1337-401X}}</ref>
The [[participation criterion]] is a closely-related, but different, concept. While positive responsiveness deals with a voter changing their opinion (or vote), participation deals with situations where a voter choosing to ''cast'' a ballot has a reversed effect on the election.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Dančišin |first=Vladimír |date=2017-01-01 |title=No-show paradox in Slovak party-list proportional system |url=https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/humaff-2017-0002/html?lang=en |journal=Human Affairs |language=en |volume=27 |issue=1 |pages=15–21 |doi=10.1515/humaff-2017-0002 |issn=1337-401X}}</ref>

==Definition==
Miller defined two main classes of monotonicity failure in 2012, which have been repeated in later papers:<ref name="Miller2012"><!--Kinda think we should replace this one with the PDF version, but I can't tell if it's too different-->{{Cite book |last=Miller |first=Nicholas R. |url=https://userpages.umbc.edu/~nmiller/RESEARCH/MF&IRV.pptx |title=Monotonicity Failure in IRV Elections With Three Candidates |year=2012 |pages=23 |type=PowerPoint |quote=Impartial Culture Profiles: All, Total MF: 15.0%}}</ref><ref name="Felsenthal-severe"/>
{{bq|
''Upward monotonicity failure'': Given the use of voting method V and a ballot profile B in which candidate X is the winner, X may nevertheless lose in ballot profile B' that differs from B only in that some voters rank X higher in B' than in B{{pb}}
''Downward monotonicity failure'': Given the use of voting method V and a ballot profile B in which candidate X is a loser, X may nevertheless win in ballot profile B' that differs from B only in that some voters rank X lower in B' than in B.
}}
In simpler terms, an upward failure occurs when a winner loses from more support, and a downward failure occurs when a loser wins with less support.


== By method ==
== By method ==
=== [[Instant-runoff voting|Runoff voting]] ===
=== Runoff voting ===
Runoff-based voting systems such as [[Instant-runoff voting|ranked choice voting (RCV)]] are typically vulnerable to perverse response. A notable example is the [[2009 Burlington mayoral election]], the United States' second [[Instant-runoff voting|instant-runoff election]] in the modern era, where [[Bob Kiss]] won the election as a result of 750 ballots ranking him in last place.<ref name=":522">{{Cite journal |last1=Graham-Squire |first1=Adam T. |last2=McCune |first2=David |date=2023-06-12 |title=An Examination of Ranked-Choice Voting in the United States, 2004–2022 |journal=Representation |language=en |pages=1–19 |arxiv=2301.12075 |doi=10.1080/00344893.2023.2221689}}</ref> Another example is given by the [[2022 Alaska's at-large congressional district special election|2022 Alaska at-large special election]].
[[Instant-runoff voting|Runoff-based voting]] systems such as [[Instant-runoff voting|ranked choice voting (RCV)]] are typically vulnerable to perverse response. A notable example is the [[2009 Burlington mayoral election]], the United States' second [[Instant-runoff voting|instant-runoff election]] in the modern era, where [[Bob Kiss]] won the election as a result of 750 ballots ranking him in last place.<ref name=":522">{{Cite journal |last1=Graham-Squire |first1=Adam T. |last2=McCune |first2=David |date=2023-06-12 |title=An Examination of Ranked-Choice Voting in the United States, 2004–2022 |journal=Representation |language=en |pages=1–19 |arxiv=2301.12075 |doi=10.1080/00344893.2023.2221689}}</ref> Another example is given by the [[2022 Alaska's at-large congressional district special election|2022 Alaska at-large special election]].


An example with three parties (Top, Center, Bottom) is shown below. In this scenario, the Bottom party initially loses. However, they are ''elected'' after running an ''un''successful campaign and adopting an ''un''popular platform, which pushes their supporters away from the party and into the Top party.
An example with three parties (Top, Center, Bottom) is shown below. In this scenario, the Bottom party initially loses. However, they are ''elected'' after running an ''un''successful campaign and adopting an ''un''popular platform, which pushes their supporters away from the party and into the Top party.
Line 56: Line 63:
|'''54% {{Tick}}'''
|'''54% {{Tick}}'''
|}
|}
This election is an example of a [[center-squeeze]], a class of elections where instant-runoff and [[Plurality voting|plurality]] have difficulties electing the majority-preferred candidate, because the first-round vote is split between an extremist and a moderate. Here, the loss of support for Bottom policies makes the Top party more popular, allowing it to defeat the Center party in the first round.
This election is an example of a [[center-squeeze]], a class of elections where instant-runoff and [[Plurality voting|plurality]] have difficulties electing the majority-preferred candidate. Here, the loss of support for Bottom policies makes the Top party more popular, allowing it to defeat the Center party in the first round.


=== Quota rules ===
=== Proportional rules ===
[[Proportional representation]] systems using [[Largest remainder method|largest remainders]] for [[Apportionment (politics)|apportionment]] do not pass the positive response criterion. This happened in the [[2005 German federal election]], when [[Christian Democratic Union of Germany|CDU]] voters in [[Dresden]] were instructed to vote for the [[Free Democratic Party (Germany)|FDP]], a strategy that allowed the CDU to win an additional seat.<ref name=":4222" /> As a result, the [[Federal Constitutional Court]] ruled that negative voting weights violate the [[Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany|German constitution]]'s guarantee of [[One man, one vote|equal and direct suffrage]].<ref name=":022">{{Cite news |last=dpa |date=2013-02-22 |title=Bundestag beschließt neues Wahlrecht |url=https://www.zeit.de/politik/deutschland/2013-02/bundestag-wahlrecht-beschluss |access-date=2024-05-02 |work=Die Zeit |language=de-DE |issn=0044-2070}}</ref>
Some [[proportional representation]] systems can exhibit negative responsiveness. These include the [[single transferable vote]] and some implementations of [[mixed-member proportional representation]], generally as a result of poorly-designed [[Overhang seat|overhang rules]]. An example can be found in the [[2005 German federal election]], where [[Christian Democratic Union of Germany|CDU]] supporters in [[Dresden]] were instructed to vote for the [[Free Democratic Party (Germany)|FDP]], a strategy that allowed the CDU to win an additional seat.<ref name=":4222" /> This led the [[Federal Constitutional Court]] to rule that negative responsiveness violates the [[Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany|German constitution]]'s guarantee of [[One man, one vote|equal and direct suffrage]].<ref name=":0322"/>


== Frequency of violations ==
== Frequency of violations ==
For electoral methods failing positive value, the frequency of less-is-more paradoxes will depend on the electoral method, the candidates, and the distribution of outcomes. Negative voting weights tend to be most common with [[Instant-runoff voting|instant-runoff]], with what some researchers have described as an "unacceptably high" frequency.<ref name=":332" />
For electoral methods failing positive value, the frequency of less-is-more paradoxes will depend on the electoral method, the candidates, and the distribution of outcomes. Social choice theorists generally agree that non-monotonicity is a particularly serious defect.<ref name="Felsenthal-severe"/> Gallagher, in 2013, writes that for some social choice theorists, vulnerability to monotonicity violations is sufficient to disapprove of runoff based electoral methods, while political scientists and some other social choice theorists tend to be less concerned.<ref name="Gallagher"/>


===Empirical analysis===
=== Theoretical models ===
In the US, a 2021 analysis of [[Instant-runoff voting|instant-runoff]] elections in California between 2008 and 2016, as well as the [[2009 Burlington, Vermont mayoral election]], found an upward monotonicity anomaly rate of 0.74% (1/135) in all elections, 2.71% (1/37) when limited to elections going to a second round of counting and 7.7% (1/13) of elections with three competitive candidates.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Graham-Squire |first1=Adam |last2=Zayatz |first2=N. |title=Lack of Monotonicity Anomalies in Empirical Data of Instant-runoff Elections |journal=Representation |date=2 October 2021 |volume=57 |issue=4 |pages=565–573 |doi=10.1080/00344893.2020.1785536}}</ref><ref name="McCune"/> A more comprehensive 2023 survey of 182 American IRV elections where no candidate was ranked first by a majority of voters found seven total examples of non-monotonicity (3.8%), broken down into 2.2% (4/182) examples of upward monotonicity, 1.6% (3/182) of downward montonicity and 0.5% (1/182) of no-show or truncation (one example was both an upward and downward monotonicity failure).<ref name=":522" /><ref name="McCune">{{cite journal |last1=McCune |first1=David |last2=Graham-Squire |first2=Adam |title=Monotonicity anomalies in Scottish local government elections |journal=Social Choice and Welfare |date=August 2024 |volume=63 |issue=1 |pages=69–101 |doi=10.1007/s00355-024-01522-5 |doi-access=free}}</ref> Two of those elections are also noted as specific examples below.
Results using the [[impartial culture]] model estimate about 15% of elections with 3 candidates;<ref>{{Cite web |last=Miller |first=Nicholas R. |date=2016 |title=Monotonicity Failure in IRV Elections with Three Candidates: Closeness Matters |url=https://userpages.umbc.edu/~nmiller/MONFAILURE.R2.NRM.pdf |access-date=2020-07-26 |website=University of Maryland Baltimore County |at=Table 2 |language=en |quote=Impartial Culture Profiles: All, TMF: 15.1% |edition=2nd}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Miller |first=Nicholas R. |url=https://userpages.umbc.edu/~nmiller/RESEARCH/MF&IRV.pptx |title=Monotonicity Failure in IRV Elections With Three Candidates |year=2012 |pages=23 |type=PowerPoint |quote=Impartial Culture Profiles: All, Total MF: 15.0%}}</ref> however, the true probability may be much higher, especially when restricting observation to close elections.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Quas |first=Anthony |date=2004-03-01 |title=Anomalous Outcomes in Preferential Voting |url=https://www.worldscientific.com/doi/abs/10.1142/S0219493704000912 |journal=Stochastics and Dynamics |language=en |volume=04 |issue=1 |pages=95–105 |doi=10.1142/S0219493704000912 |issn=0219-4937}}</ref> For moderate numbers of candidates, the probability of a less-is-more paradoxes quickly approaches 100%.{{citation needed|date=March 2024}}


====Semi-empirical====
A 2013 study using a two-dimensional [[spatial model of voting]] estimated at least 15% of IRV elections would be nonmonotonic in the best-case scenario (with only three equally-competitive candidates). The researchers concluded that "three-way competitive races will exhibit unacceptably frequent monotonicity failures" and "In light of these results, those seeking to implement a fairer multi-candidate election system should be wary of adopting IRV."<ref name=":332" />
Some empirical research do not have access to full ballot preference data, and thus make probabilistic estimates of transfer patterns. A 2013 survey of Irish elections using IRV and [[PR-STV]] found plausible non-monotonicity in 20 out of 1326 elections between 1922 and 2011.<ref name="Gallagher">{{Cite conference |last=Gallagher |first=Michael |date=September 2013 |title=Monotonicity and non-monotonicity at PR-STV elections |url=https://www.lancaster.ac.uk/fass/events/epop2013/docs/MGallagherMonotonicityEPOP13.pdf |conference=Annual conference of the elections, public opinion and parties (EPOP) specialist group, University of Lancaster |volume=13}}</ref>


Data from the five UK general elections between 1992 and 2010 showed 2642 three candidate elections in English constituencies. With second preferences imputed from survey data, 1.7% of all elections appeared vulnerable to monotonicity anomalies (1.4% upward, 0.3% downward), significantly lower than simulated datasets from the same paper. However, when limited to the 4.2% of elections considered three-way competitive<!--This should be the 111 elections where PL support >25% but might need to check that, also probably get consensus that it's correct per CALC-->, 40.2% appeared vulnerable (33% upward, 7.1% downward), and further increasing with closer competition, a result closer to the simulations.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Miller |first=Nicholas R. |date=October 2017 |title=Closeness matters: monotonicity failure in IRV elections with three candidates |journal=Public Choice |volume=173 |issue=1-2 |pages=91–108 |doi=10.1007/s11127-017-0465-5 |hdl=11603/20938 |hdl-access=free}}</ref>
=== Real-world situations ===

A 2022 analysis out of the 10 French presidential elections (conducted under the [[two-round system]]) 2 had results where monotonicity violations were not mathematically possible, another 6 where violations were unlikely given the evidence, leaving 2 elections ([[2002 French presidential election|2002]] and [[2007 French presidential election|2007]]) where an upward monotonicity violation was probable and likely respectively.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Keskin |first1=Umut |last2=Sanver |first2=M. Remzi |last3=Tosunlu |first3=H. Berkay |url=https://hal.science/hal-03413280/document |title=Monotonicity violations under plurality with a runoff: the case of French presidential elections |journal=Social Choice and Welfare |date=August 2022 |volume=59 |issue=2 |pages=305–333 |doi=10.1007/s00355-022-01397-4}}</ref>

=== Theoretical models===
Results using the [[impartial culture]] model estimate about 15% of elections with 3 candidates;<ref>{{Cite web |last=Miller |first=Nicholas R. |date=2016 |title=Monotonicity Failure in IRV Elections with Three Candidates: Closeness Matters |url=https://userpages.umbc.edu/~nmiller/MONFAILURE.R2.NRM.pdf |access-date=2020-07-26 |website=University of Maryland Baltimore County |at=Table 2 |language=en |quote=Impartial Culture Profiles: All, TMF: 15.1% |edition=2nd}}</ref><ref name="Miller2012"/> however, the true probability may be much higher, especially when restricting observation to close elections.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Quas |first=Anthony |date=2004-03-01 |title=Anomalous Outcomes in Preferential Voting |url=https://www.worldscientific.com/doi/abs/10.1142/S0219493704000912 |journal=Stochastics and Dynamics |language=en |volume=04 |issue=1 |pages=95–105 |doi=10.1142/S0219493704000912 |issn=0219-4937}}</ref>

A 2013 study using a two-dimensional [[spatial model of voting]] estimated at least 15% of IRV elections would be nonmonotonic in the best-case scenario (with only three equally-competitive candidates). The researchers concluded that "three-way competitive races will exhibit unacceptably frequent monotonicity failures" and "In light of these results, those seeking to implement a fairer multi-candidate election system should be wary of adopting IRV."<ref name="Ornstein" />

=== Specific examples ===
==== Alaska 2022 ====
==== Alaska 2022 ====
[[2022 Alaska's at-large congressional district special election|Alaska's first-ever instant-runoff election]] resulted in negative vote weights for many [[Republican Party (United States)|Republican]] supporters of [[Sarah Palin]], who could have defeated [[Mary Peltola]] by placing her first on their ballots.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Graham-Squire |first1=Adam |last2=McCune |first2=David |date=2024-01-02 |title=Ranked Choice Wackiness in Alaska |url=https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/10724117.2023.2224675 |journal=Math Horizons |language=en |volume=31 |issue=1 |pages=24–27 |doi=10.1080/10724117.2023.2224675 |issn=1072-4117}}</ref>
[[2022 Alaska's at-large congressional district special election|Alaska's first-ever instant-runoff election]] resulted in a victory for [[Mary Peltola]], but had many [[Republican Party (United States)|Republican]] voters ranked Peltola first, Peltola would have lost.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Graham-Squire |first1=Adam |last2=McCune |first2=David |date=2024-01-02 |title=Ranked Choice Wackiness in Alaska |url=https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/10724117.2023.2224675 |journal=Math Horizons |language=en |volume=31 |issue=1 |pages=24–27 |doi=10.1080/10724117.2023.2224675 |issn=1072-4117}}</ref>


==== Burlington, Vermont ====
==== Burlington, Vermont ====
In [[2009 Burlington, Vermont mayoral election|Burlington's second IRV election]], incumbent [[Bob Kiss]] was re-elected, despite losing in a head-to-head matchup with Democrat Andy Montroll (the [[Condorcet winner]]). However, if Kiss had gained more support from Wright voters, Kiss would have lost.<ref name=":522" />
In [[2009 Burlington, Vermont mayoral election|Burlington's second IRV election]], incumbent [[Bob Kiss]] was re-elected, despite losing in a head-to-head matchup with Democrat Andy Montroll (the [[Condorcet winner]]). However, if Kiss had gained more support from Wright voters, Kiss would have lost.<ref name=":522" />

==== Survey of nonmonotonic elections ====
A survey of 185 American [[Instant-runoff voting|instant-runoff]] elections where no candidate was ranked first by a majority of voters found five additional perverse elections (a total of seven).<ref name=":522" />


==== 2005 German Election in Dresden ====
==== 2005 German Election in Dresden ====
A negative voting weight event famously resulted in the abolition of [[Hamilton's method]] for apportionment in Germany after the [[2005 German federal election|2005 federal election]]. [[Christian Democratic Union of Germany|CDU]] voters in [[Dresden]] were instructed to strategically vote for the [[Free Democratic Party (Germany)|FDP]], a strategy that allowed the party to earn an additional seat, causing substantial controversy. As a result, the [[Federal Constitutional Court]] ruled that negative voting weights violate the [[Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany|German constitution]]'s guarantee of [[One man, one vote|equal and direct suffrage]].<ref name=":4222" />
Some [[proportional representation]] systems can exhibit negative responsiveness. These include the [[single transferable vote]] and some implementations of [[mixed-member proportional representation]], generally as a result of poorly-designed [[Overhang seat|overhang rules]]. An example can be found in the [[2005 German federal election]], where [[Christian Democratic Union of Germany|CDU]] supporters in [[Dresden]] were instructed to vote for the [[Free Democratic Party (Germany)|FDP]], a strategy that allowed the CDU to win an additional seat.<ref name=":4222" /> This led the [[Federal Constitutional Court]] to rule that negative responsiveness violates the [[Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany|German constitution]]'s guarantee of [[One man, one vote|equal and direct suffrage]].<ref name=":0322"/>


== See also ==
== See also ==
Line 97: Line 111:
<references responsive="1"></references>
<references responsive="1"></references>
{{voting systems}}
{{voting systems}}

[[Category:Electoral system criteria]]

Latest revision as of 22:18, 18 December 2024

A diagram showing who would win an IRV election for different electorates. The win region for each candidate is erratic, with random pixels dotting the image and jagged, star-shaped (convex) regions occupying much of the image. Moving the electorate to the left can cause a right-wing candidate to win, and vice versa.
A 4-candidate Yee diagram under IRV. The diagram shows who would win an IRV election if the electorate is centered at a particular point. Moving the electorate to the left can cause a right-wing candidate to win, and vice versa. Black lines show the optimal solution (achieved by Condorcet or score voting).

In social choice, the negative responsiveness,[1][2] perversity,[3] or additional support paradox[4] is a pathological behavior of some voting rules, where a candidate loses as a result of having "too much support" from some voters, or wins because they had "too much opposition". In other words, increasing (decreasing) a candidate's ranking or rating causes that candidate to lose (win).[4] Electoral systems that do not exhibit perversity are said to satisfy the positive response or monotonicity criterion.[5]

Perversity is often described by social choice theorists as an exceptionally severe kind of electoral pathology.[6] Systems that allow for perverse response can create situations where a voter's ballot has a reversed effect on the election, thus treating the well-being of some voters as "less than worthless".[7] Similar arguments have led to constitutional prohibitions on such systems as violating the right to equal and direct suffrage.[8][9] Negative response is often cited as an example of a perverse incentive, as voting rules with perverse response incentivize politicians to take unpopular or extreme positions in an attempt to shed excess votes.

Most ranked methods (including Borda and all common round-robin rules) satisfy positive response,[5] as do all common rated voting methods (including approval, highest medians, and score).[note 1]

Perversity occurs in instant-runoff voting (IRV),[10] the single transferable vote,[3] and quota-based apportionment methods.[2] According to statistical culture models of elections, the paradox is especially common in RCV/IRV and the two-round system.[citation needed] The randomized Condorcet method can violate monotonicity in the case of cyclic ties.

The participation criterion is a closely-related, but different, concept. While positive responsiveness deals with a voter changing their opinion (or vote), participation deals with situations where a voter choosing to cast a ballot has a reversed effect on the election.[11]

Definition

[edit]

Miller defined two main classes of monotonicity failure in 2012, which have been repeated in later papers:[12][6]

Upward monotonicity failure: Given the use of voting method V and a ballot profile B in which candidate X is the winner, X may nevertheless lose in ballot profile B' that differs from B only in that some voters rank X higher in B' than in B

Downward monotonicity failure: Given the use of voting method V and a ballot profile B in which candidate X is a loser, X may nevertheless win in ballot profile B' that differs from B only in that some voters rank X lower in B' than in B.

In simpler terms, an upward failure occurs when a winner loses from more support, and a downward failure occurs when a loser wins with less support.

By method

[edit]

Runoff voting

[edit]

Runoff-based voting systems such as ranked choice voting (RCV) are typically vulnerable to perverse response. A notable example is the 2009 Burlington mayoral election, the United States' second instant-runoff election in the modern era, where Bob Kiss won the election as a result of 750 ballots ranking him in last place.[13] Another example is given by the 2022 Alaska at-large special election.

An example with three parties (Top, Center, Bottom) is shown below. In this scenario, the Bottom party initially loses. However, they are elected after running an unsuccessful campaign and adopting an unpopular platform, which pushes their supporters away from the party and into the Top party.

Popular Bottom Unpopular Bottom
Round 1 Round 2 Round 1 Round 2
Top 25% ☒N +6% Top 31% 46%
Center 30% 55% checkY Center 30% ☒N
Bottom 45% 45% -6% Bottom 39% 54% checkY

This election is an example of a center-squeeze, a class of elections where instant-runoff and plurality have difficulties electing the majority-preferred candidate. Here, the loss of support for Bottom policies makes the Top party more popular, allowing it to defeat the Center party in the first round.

Proportional rules

[edit]

Some proportional representation systems can exhibit negative responsiveness. These include the single transferable vote and some implementations of mixed-member proportional representation, generally as a result of poorly-designed overhang rules. An example can be found in the 2005 German federal election, where CDU supporters in Dresden were instructed to vote for the FDP, a strategy that allowed the CDU to win an additional seat.[2] This led the Federal Constitutional Court to rule that negative responsiveness violates the German constitution's guarantee of equal and direct suffrage.[9]

Frequency of violations

[edit]

For electoral methods failing positive value, the frequency of less-is-more paradoxes will depend on the electoral method, the candidates, and the distribution of outcomes. Social choice theorists generally agree that non-monotonicity is a particularly serious defect.[6] Gallagher, in 2013, writes that for some social choice theorists, vulnerability to monotonicity violations is sufficient to disapprove of runoff based electoral methods, while political scientists and some other social choice theorists tend to be less concerned.[14]

Empirical analysis

[edit]

In the US, a 2021 analysis of instant-runoff elections in California between 2008 and 2016, as well as the 2009 Burlington, Vermont mayoral election, found an upward monotonicity anomaly rate of 0.74% (1/135) in all elections, 2.71% (1/37) when limited to elections going to a second round of counting and 7.7% (1/13) of elections with three competitive candidates.[15][16] A more comprehensive 2023 survey of 182 American IRV elections where no candidate was ranked first by a majority of voters found seven total examples of non-monotonicity (3.8%), broken down into 2.2% (4/182) examples of upward monotonicity, 1.6% (3/182) of downward montonicity and 0.5% (1/182) of no-show or truncation (one example was both an upward and downward monotonicity failure).[13][16] Two of those elections are also noted as specific examples below.

Semi-empirical

[edit]

Some empirical research do not have access to full ballot preference data, and thus make probabilistic estimates of transfer patterns. A 2013 survey of Irish elections using IRV and PR-STV found plausible non-monotonicity in 20 out of 1326 elections between 1922 and 2011.[14]

Data from the five UK general elections between 1992 and 2010 showed 2642 three candidate elections in English constituencies. With second preferences imputed from survey data, 1.7% of all elections appeared vulnerable to monotonicity anomalies (1.4% upward, 0.3% downward), significantly lower than simulated datasets from the same paper. However, when limited to the 4.2% of elections considered three-way competitive, 40.2% appeared vulnerable (33% upward, 7.1% downward), and further increasing with closer competition, a result closer to the simulations.[17]

A 2022 analysis out of the 10 French presidential elections (conducted under the two-round system) 2 had results where monotonicity violations were not mathematically possible, another 6 where violations were unlikely given the evidence, leaving 2 elections (2002 and 2007) where an upward monotonicity violation was probable and likely respectively.[18]

Theoretical models

[edit]

Results using the impartial culture model estimate about 15% of elections with 3 candidates;[19][12] however, the true probability may be much higher, especially when restricting observation to close elections.[20]

A 2013 study using a two-dimensional spatial model of voting estimated at least 15% of IRV elections would be nonmonotonic in the best-case scenario (with only three equally-competitive candidates). The researchers concluded that "three-way competitive races will exhibit unacceptably frequent monotonicity failures" and "In light of these results, those seeking to implement a fairer multi-candidate election system should be wary of adopting IRV."[10]

Specific examples

[edit]

Alaska 2022

[edit]

Alaska's first-ever instant-runoff election resulted in a victory for Mary Peltola, but had many Republican voters ranked Peltola first, Peltola would have lost.[21]

Burlington, Vermont

[edit]

In Burlington's second IRV election, incumbent Bob Kiss was re-elected, despite losing in a head-to-head matchup with Democrat Andy Montroll (the Condorcet winner). However, if Kiss had gained more support from Wright voters, Kiss would have lost.[13]

2005 German Election in Dresden

[edit]

Some proportional representation systems can exhibit negative responsiveness. These include the single transferable vote and some implementations of mixed-member proportional representation, generally as a result of poorly-designed overhang rules. An example can be found in the 2005 German federal election, where CDU supporters in Dresden were instructed to vote for the FDP, a strategy that allowed the CDU to win an additional seat.[2] This led the Federal Constitutional Court to rule that negative responsiveness violates the German constitution's guarantee of equal and direct suffrage.[9]

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Apart from majority judgment, these systems satisfy an even stronger form of positive responsiveness: if there is a tie, any increase in a candidate's rating will break the tie in that candidate's favor.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ May, Kenneth O. (1952). "A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decision". Econometrica. 20 (4): 680–684. doi:10.2307/1907651. ISSN 0012-9682. JSTOR 1907651.
  2. ^ a b c d Pukelsheim, Friedrich (2014). Proportional representation: apportionment methods and their applications. Internet Archive. Cham; New York : Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-03855-1.
  3. ^ a b Doron, Gideon; Kronick, Richard (1977). "Single Transferrable Vote: An Example of a Perverse Social Choice Function". American Journal of Political Science. 21 (2): 303–311. doi:10.2307/2110496. ISSN 0092-5853. JSTOR 2110496.
  4. ^ a b Felsenthal, Dan S. (April 2010). "Review of paradoxes afflicting various voting procedures where one out of m candidates (m ≥ 2) must be elected". GBR. pp. 1–52.
  5. ^ a b D R Woodall, "Monotonicity and Single-Seat Election Rules", Voting matters, Issue 6, 1996
  6. ^ a b c Felsenthal, Dan S.; Tideman, Nicolaus (2014-01-01). "Interacting double monotonicity failure with direction of impact under five voting methods". Mathematical Social Sciences. 67: 57–66. doi:10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2013.08.001. ISSN 0165-4896. it is generally agreed among social choice theorists that a voting method that is susceptible to any type of monotonicity failure suffers from a particularly serious defect.
  7. ^ Arrow, Kenneth J. (2017-12-13). Social Choice and Individual Values. p. 25. doi:10.12987/9780300186987. ISBN 978-0-300-18698-7. Since we are trying to describe social welfare and not some sort of illfare, we must assume that the social welfare function is such that the social ordering responds positively to alterations in individual values, or at least not negatively. Hence, if one alternative social state rises or remains still in the ordering of every individual without any other change in those orderings, we expect that it rises, or at least does not fall, in the social ordering.
  8. ^ Pukelsheim, Friedrich (2014). Proportional representation : apportionment methods and their applications. Internet Archive. Cham; New York : Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-03855-1.
  9. ^ a b c dpa (2013-02-22). "Bundestag beschließt neues Wahlrecht". Die Zeit (in German). ISSN 0044-2070. Retrieved 2024-05-02.
  10. ^ a b Ornstein, Joseph T.; Norman, Robert Z. (2014-10-01). "Frequency of monotonicity failure under Instant Runoff Voting: estimates based on a spatial model of elections". Public Choice. 161 (1–2): 1–9. doi:10.1007/s11127-013-0118-2. ISSN 0048-5829. S2CID 30833409.
  11. ^ Dančišin, Vladimír (2017-01-01). "No-show paradox in Slovak party-list proportional system". Human Affairs. 27 (1): 15–21. doi:10.1515/humaff-2017-0002. ISSN 1337-401X.
  12. ^ a b Miller, Nicholas R. (2012). Monotonicity Failure in IRV Elections With Three Candidates (PowerPoint). p. 23. Impartial Culture Profiles: All, Total MF: 15.0%
  13. ^ a b c Graham-Squire, Adam T.; McCune, David (2023-06-12). "An Examination of Ranked-Choice Voting in the United States, 2004–2022". Representation: 1–19. arXiv:2301.12075. doi:10.1080/00344893.2023.2221689.
  14. ^ a b Gallagher, Michael (September 2013). Monotonicity and non-monotonicity at PR-STV elections (PDF). Annual conference of the elections, public opinion and parties (EPOP) specialist group, University of Lancaster. Vol. 13.
  15. ^ Graham-Squire, Adam; Zayatz, N. (2 October 2021). "Lack of Monotonicity Anomalies in Empirical Data of Instant-runoff Elections". Representation. 57 (4): 565–573. doi:10.1080/00344893.2020.1785536.
  16. ^ a b McCune, David; Graham-Squire, Adam (August 2024). "Monotonicity anomalies in Scottish local government elections". Social Choice and Welfare. 63 (1): 69–101. doi:10.1007/s00355-024-01522-5.
  17. ^ Miller, Nicholas R. (October 2017). "Closeness matters: monotonicity failure in IRV elections with three candidates". Public Choice. 173 (1–2): 91–108. doi:10.1007/s11127-017-0465-5. hdl:11603/20938.
  18. ^ Keskin, Umut; Sanver, M. Remzi; Tosunlu, H. Berkay (August 2022). "Monotonicity violations under plurality with a runoff: the case of French presidential elections". Social Choice and Welfare. 59 (2): 305–333. doi:10.1007/s00355-022-01397-4.
  19. ^ Miller, Nicholas R. (2016). "Monotonicity Failure in IRV Elections with Three Candidates: Closeness Matters" (PDF). University of Maryland Baltimore County (2nd ed.). Table 2. Retrieved 2020-07-26. Impartial Culture Profiles: All, TMF: 15.1%
  20. ^ Quas, Anthony (2004-03-01). "Anomalous Outcomes in Preferential Voting". Stochastics and Dynamics. 04 (1): 95–105. doi:10.1142/S0219493704000912. ISSN 0219-4937.
  21. ^ Graham-Squire, Adam; McCune, David (2024-01-02). "Ranked Choice Wackiness in Alaska". Math Horizons. 31 (1): 24–27. doi:10.1080/10724117.2023.2224675. ISSN 1072-4117.