Jump to content

Structural rule: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Iovoid (talk | contribs)
m Missing space
m v2.05b - Bot T20 CW#61 - Fix errors for CW project (Reference before punctuation)
 
(2 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Rule of mathematical logic}}
{{Short description|Rule of mathematical logic}}
{{for|the type of rule used in linguistics|phrase structure rule}}
{{for|the type of rule used in linguistics|phrase structure rule}}
In the [[formal logic|logical]] discipline of [[proof theory]], a '''structural rule''' is an [[inference rule]] of a [[sequent calculus]] that does not refer to any [[logical connective]] but instead operates on the [[sequent]]s directly.<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal |last=Gentzen |first=Gerhard |date=1935 |title=Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen. I, Mathematische Zeitschrift |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/BF01201353 |journal=Mathematische Zeitschrift |language=de |volume=39 |issue=1 |pages=176–210 |doi=10.1007/BF01201353 |issn=0025-5874}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Szabo |first=M. E. |title=Collected papers of Gerhard Gentzen |date=1969 |publisher=Elsevier |isbn=978-0-444-53419-4 |location=Place of publication not identified}}</ref> Structural rules often mimic the intended meta-theoretic properties of the logic. Logics that deny one or more of the structural rules are classified as [[substructural logic]]s.
{{Unreferenced|date=December 2009}}
In the [[formal logic|logical]] discipline of [[proof theory]], a '''structural rule''' is an [[inference rule]] of a [[sequent calculus]] that does not refer to any [[logical connective]] but instead operates on the [[sequent]]s directly. Structural rules often mimic the intended meta-theoretic properties of the logic. Logics that deny one or more of the structural rules are classified as [[substructural logic]]s.


==Common structural rules==
==Common structural rules==
Three common structural rules are:<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Jacobs |first=Bart |date=1994 |title=Semantics of weakening and contraction |url=https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/0168007294900205 |journal=Annals of Pure and Applied Logic |language=en |volume=69 |issue=1 |pages=73–106 |doi=10.1016/0168-0072(94)90020-5}}</ref>
Three common structural rules are:


* {{Anchor|Weakening}}'''Weakening''', where the hypotheses or conclusion of a sequence may be extended with additional members. In symbolic form weakening rules can be written as <math>\frac{\Gamma \vdash \Sigma}{\Gamma, A \vdash \Sigma}</math> on the left of the [[Turnstile (symbol)|turnstile]], and <math>\frac{\Gamma \vdash \Sigma}{\Gamma \vdash \Sigma, A}</math> on the right. Known as [[monotonicity of entailment]] in classical logic.
* {{Anchor|Weakening}}'''Weakening''', where the hypotheses or conclusion of a sequence may be extended with additional members. In symbolic form weakening rules can be written as <math>\frac{\Gamma \vdash \Sigma}{\Gamma, A \vdash \Sigma}</math> on the left of the [[Turnstile (symbol)|turnstile]], and <math>\frac{\Gamma \vdash \Sigma}{\Gamma \vdash \Sigma, A}</math> on the right. Known as [[monotonicity of entailment]] in classical logic.
Line 14: Line 13:
A logic without any of the above structural rules would interpret the sides of a sequent as pure [[sequence]]s; with exchange, they can be considered to be [[multiset]]s; and with both contraction and exchange they can be considered to be [[set (mathematics)|set]]s.
A logic without any of the above structural rules would interpret the sides of a sequent as pure [[sequence]]s; with exchange, they can be considered to be [[multiset]]s; and with both contraction and exchange they can be considered to be [[set (mathematics)|set]]s.


These are not the only possible structural rules. A famous structural rule is known as '''[[cut rule|cut]]'''. Considerable effort is spent by proof theorists in showing that cut rules are superfluous in various logics. More precisely, what is shown is that cut is only (in a sense) a tool for abbreviating proofs, and does not add to the theorems that can be proved. The successful 'removal' of cut rules, known as ''[[Cut-elimination theorem|cut elimination]]'', is directly related to the philosophy of ''[[computation]] as normalization'' (see [[Curry–Howard correspondence]]); it often gives a good indication of the [[computational complexity theory|complexity]] of [[decision problem|deciding]] a given logic.
These are not the only possible structural rules. A famous structural rule is known as '''[[cut rule|cut]]'''.<ref name=":0" /> Considerable effort is spent by proof theorists in showing that cut rules are superfluous in various logics. More precisely, what is shown is that cut is only (in a sense) a tool for abbreviating proofs, and does not add to the theorems that can be proved. The successful 'removal' of cut rules, known as ''[[Cut-elimination theorem|cut elimination]]'', is directly related to the philosophy of ''[[computation]] as normalization'' (see [[Curry–Howard correspondence]]); it often gives a good indication of the [[computational complexity theory|complexity]] of [[decision problem|deciding]] a given logic.


==See also==
==See also==
Line 22: Line 21:
*{{annotated link|Relevance logic}}
*{{annotated link|Relevance logic}}
*{{annotated link|Separation logic}}
*{{annotated link|Separation logic}}

==References==
{{Reflist}}


{{Non-classical logic}}
{{Non-classical logic}}

Latest revision as of 10:34, 28 April 2024

In the logical discipline of proof theory, a structural rule is an inference rule of a sequent calculus that does not refer to any logical connective but instead operates on the sequents directly.[1][2] Structural rules often mimic the intended meta-theoretic properties of the logic. Logics that deny one or more of the structural rules are classified as substructural logics.

Common structural rules

[edit]

Three common structural rules are:[3]

  • Weakening, where the hypotheses or conclusion of a sequence may be extended with additional members. In symbolic form weakening rules can be written as on the left of the turnstile, and on the right. Known as monotonicity of entailment in classical logic.
  • Contraction, where two equal (or unifiable) members on the same side of a sequent may be replaced by a single member (or common instance). Symbolically: and . Also known as factoring in automated theorem proving systems using resolution. Known as idempotency of entailment in classical logic.
  • Exchange, where two members on the same side of a sequent may be swapped. Symbolically: and . (This is also known as the permutation rule.)

A logic without any of the above structural rules would interpret the sides of a sequent as pure sequences; with exchange, they can be considered to be multisets; and with both contraction and exchange they can be considered to be sets.

These are not the only possible structural rules. A famous structural rule is known as cut.[1] Considerable effort is spent by proof theorists in showing that cut rules are superfluous in various logics. More precisely, what is shown is that cut is only (in a sense) a tool for abbreviating proofs, and does not add to the theorems that can be proved. The successful 'removal' of cut rules, known as cut elimination, is directly related to the philosophy of computation as normalization (see Curry–Howard correspondence); it often gives a good indication of the complexity of deciding a given logic.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b Gentzen, Gerhard (1935). "Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen. I, Mathematische Zeitschrift". Mathematische Zeitschrift (in German). 39 (1): 176–210. doi:10.1007/BF01201353. ISSN 0025-5874.
  2. ^ Szabo, M. E. (1969). Collected papers of Gerhard Gentzen. Place of publication not identified: Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-444-53419-4.
  3. ^ Jacobs, Bart (1994). "Semantics of weakening and contraction". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 69 (1): 73–106. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(94)90020-5.