Uncertainty principle: Difference between revisions
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|Foundational principle in quantum physics}} |
|||
{{Quantum mechanics|cTopic=Fundamental concepts}} |
|||
{{Other uses}} |
|||
In [[quantum physics]], the [[Werner Heisenberg|Heisenberg]] '''uncertainty principle''' is the statement that locating a particle in a small region of space makes the momentum of the particle uncertain; and conversely, that measuring the momentum of a particle precisely makes the position uncertain. |
|||
{{Use American English|date=January 2019}} |
|||
{{Quantum mechanics}} |
|||
[[File:Werner Heisenberg - Canonical commutation rule for position and momentum variables of a particle - Uncertainty principle, 1927.jpg|thumb|Canonical commutation rule for position ''q'' and momentum ''p'' variables of a particle, 1927. ''pq'' − ''qp'' = ''h''/(2''πi''). Uncertainty principle of Heisenberg, 1927.]] |
|||
In quantum mechanics, the position and momentum of particles do not have precise values, but have a probability distribution. There are no states in which a particle has both a definite position and a definite momentum. The narrower the probability distribution is in position, the wider it is in momentum. |
|||
The '''uncertainty principle''', also known as '''Heisenberg's indeterminacy principle''', is a fundamental concept in [[quantum mechanics]]. It states that there is a limit to the precision with which certain pairs of physical properties, such as position and [[momentum]], can be simultaneously known. In other words, the more accurately one property is measured, the less accurately the other property can be known. |
|||
Physically, the uncertainty principle requires that when the position of an atom is measured with a [[photon]], the reflected photon will change the momentum of the atom by an uncertain amount inversely proportional to the accuracy of the position measurement. The amount of uncertainty can never be reduced below the limit set by the principle, regardless of the experimental setup. |
|||
More formally, the uncertainty principle is any of a variety of [[Inequality (mathematics)|mathematical inequalities]] asserting a fundamental limit to the product of the accuracy of certain related pairs of measurements on a quantum system, such as [[Position (vector)|position]], ''x'', and momentum, ''p''.<ref name=Sen2014>{{Cite journal | last1 = Sen | first1 = D. | title = The Uncertainty relations in quantum mechanics | url = http://www.currentscience.ac.in/Volumes/107/02/0203.pdf | journal = Current Science | volume = 107 | issue = 2 | year = 2014 | pages = 203–218 | access-date = 2016-02-14 | archive-date = 2019-09-24 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20190924115453/https://www.currentscience.ac.in/Volumes/107/02/0203.pdf | url-status = live }}</ref> Such paired-variables are known as [[Complementarity (physics)|complementary variables]] or [[Canonical coordinates|canonically conjugate variables]]. |
|||
A mathematical statement of the principle is that every quantum state has the property that the [[root-mean-square]] (RMS) deviation of the position from its mean (the [[standard deviation]] of the X-distribution): |
|||
:<math>\Delta X = \sqrt{\langle X^2 \rangle-\langle X \rangle ^2 } \,</math> |
|||
First introduced in 1927 by German physicist [[Werner Heisenberg]],<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal |last=Heisenberg |first=W. |orig-date=1927-03-01 |title=Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01397280 |journal=Zeitschrift für Physik |date=1927 |language=de |volume=43 |issue=3 |pages=172–198 |bibcode=1927ZPhy...43..172H |doi=10.1007/BF01397280 |issn=0044-3328 |s2cid=122763326 }}{{Cite journal |last=Heisenberg |first=W |year=1983 |orig-date=1927 |title=The actual content of quantum theoretical kinematics and mechanics |url=https://ntrs.nasa.gov/citations/19840008978 |journal=No. NAS 1.15: 77379. 1983. |volume=43 |issue=3–4 |page=172 |bibcode=1983ZhPhy..43..172H |quote=English translation of Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik |access-date=2023-08-28 |archive-date=2023-09-02 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230902112403/https://ntrs.nasa.gov/citations/19840008978 |url-status=live }}</ref><ref>Werner Heisenberg (1989), ''Encounters with Einstein and Other Essays on People, Places and Particles'', [[Princeton University Press]], p. 53. {{ISBN?}}</ref><ref>{{cite book | doi=10.1515/9781400889167 | title=The Tests of Time | year=2003 | isbn=978-1400889167 | editor-last1=Dolling | editor-last2=Gianelli | editor-last3=Statile | editor-first1=Lisa M. | editor-first2=Arthur F. | editor-first3=Glenn N. }}</ref><ref>Kumar, Manjit. ''Quantum: Einstein, Bohr, and the great debate about the nature of reality.'' 1st American ed., 2008. Chap. 10, Note 37. {{ISBN?}}</ref> the formal inequality relating the [[standard deviation]] of position ''σ<sub>x</sub>'' and the standard deviation of momentum ''σ<sub>p</sub>'' was derived by [[Earle Hesse Kennard]]<ref name="Kennard">{{Citation |first=E. H. |last=Kennard |title=Zur Quantenmechanik einfacher Bewegungstypen |language=de|journal=Zeitschrift für Physik |volume=44 |issue=4–5 |year=1927 |pages=326–352 |doi=10.1007/BF01391200 |postscript=. |bibcode = 1927ZPhy...44..326K |s2cid=121626384 }}</ref> later that year and by [[Hermann Weyl]]<ref name="Weyl1928">{{Cite book |last=Weyl |first=H. |title=Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik |lang=de |year=1928 |publisher=Hirzel |location=Leipzig}}{{page?|date=February 2024}}</ref> in 1928: |
|||
times the RMS deviation of the momentum from its mean (the standard deviation of P): |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
:<math>\Delta P = \sqrt{\langle P^2 \rangle-\langle P \rangle ^2} \,</math> |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation = <math> \sigma_{x}\sigma_{p} \geq \frac{\hbar}{2}</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
where <math>\hbar = \frac{h}{2\pi}</math> is the [[reduced Planck constant]]. |
|||
The quintessentially quantum mechanical uncertainty principle comes in many forms other than position–momentum. The energy–time relationship is widely used to relate quantum state lifetime to measured energy widths but its formal derivation is fraught with confusing issues about the nature of time. The basic principle has been extended in numerous directions; it must be considered in many kinds of fundamental physical measurements. |
|||
can never be smaller than a small fixed multiple of [[Planck's constant]]: |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\Delta X \Delta P \ge {\hbar \over 2} |
|||
</math> |
|||
==Position–momentum== |
|||
The mathematical statement implies the physical statement. Once an observer measures the position of a particle with accuracy <math>\Delta X </math>, the state of the particle immediately after the measurement has <math>\scriptstyle \Delta P \ge \hbar /(2\Delta X) </math>. |
|||
{{Main article|Introduction to quantum mechanics}} |
|||
[[File:Sequential superposition of plane waves.gif|360px|right|thumb|The superposition of several plane waves to form a wave packet. This wave packet becomes increasingly localized with the addition of many waves. The Fourier transform is a mathematical operation that separates a wave packet into its individual plane waves. The waves shown here are [[real function|real]] for illustrative purposes only; in quantum mechanics the wave function is generally [[complex function|complex]].]] |
|||
The uncertainty principle is related to the [[observer effect]], with which it is often conflated. In the [[Copenhagen interpretation]] of quantum mechanics, the uncertainty principle is a theoretical limitation of how small this observer effect can be. A precise position measurement must alter the momentum by a large indeterminate amount, and vice-versa. |
|||
It is vital to illustrate how the principle applies to relatively intelligible physical situations since it is indiscernible on the macroscopic<ref>{{cite journal | last1=Jaeger|first1=Gregg|title=What in the (quantum) world is macroscopic?|journal=American Journal of Physics|date=September 2014 | volume=82|issue=9|pages=896–905|doi=10.1119/1.4878358|bibcode = 2014AmJPh..82..896J }}</ref> scales that humans experience. Two alternative frameworks for quantum physics offer different explanations for the uncertainty principle. The [[Schrödinger equation|wave mechanics]] picture of the uncertainty principle is more visually intuitive, but the more abstract [[matrix mechanics]] picture formulates it in a way that generalizes more easily. |
|||
While this is true in all interpretations, in many modern interpretations of quantum mechanics ([[Many-worlds interpretation|many-worlds]] and variants), the quantum state itself is the fundamental physical quantity, not the position or momentum. Taking this perspective, while the momentum and position are still uncertain, the uncertainty is an effect caused not just by observation, but by any [[entanglement]] with the environment. |
|||
Mathematically, in wave mechanics, the uncertainty relation between position and momentum arises because the expressions of the wavefunction in the two corresponding [[orthonormal]] [[basis (linear algebra)|bases]] in [[Hilbert space]] are [[Fourier transforms]] of one another (i.e., position and momentum are [[conjugate variables]]). A nonzero function and its Fourier transform cannot both be sharply localized at the same time.<ref>See Appendix B in {{citation |title=Why photons cannot be sharply localized |first1=Iwo |last1=Bialynicki-Birula |first2=Zofia |last2=Bialynicka-Birula |journal=Physical Review A |date=2009 |volume=79 |issue=3 |pages=7–8|doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.79.032112 |arxiv=0903.3712 |bibcode=2009PhRvA..79c2112B |s2cid=55632217 }}</ref> A similar tradeoff between the variances of Fourier conjugates arises in all systems underlain by Fourier analysis, for example in sound waves: A pure tone is a [[Dirac delta function|sharp spike]] at a single frequency, while its Fourier transform gives the shape of the sound wave in the time domain, which is a completely delocalized sine wave. In quantum mechanics, the two key points are that the position of the particle takes the form of a matter wave, and momentum is its Fourier conjugate, assured by the [[Matter wave|de Broglie relation]] {{math|''p'' {{=}} ''ħk''}}, where {{mvar|k}} is the [[wavenumber]]. |
|||
== Historical Introduction == |
|||
In [[matrix mechanics]], the [[mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics#Postulates of quantum mechanics|mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics]], any pair of non-[[commutator|commuting]] [[self-adjoint operator]]s representing [[observable]]s are subject to similar uncertainty limits. An eigenstate of an observable represents the state of the wavefunction for a certain measurement value (the eigenvalue). For example, if a measurement of an observable {{mvar|A}} is performed, then the system is in a particular eigenstate {{mvar|Ψ}} of that observable. However, the particular eigenstate of the observable {{mvar|A}} need not be an eigenstate of another observable {{mvar|B}}: If so, then it does not have a unique associated measurement for it, as the system is not in an eigenstate of that observable.<ref>{{Citation|author1=Claude Cohen-Tannoudji | author2=Bernard Diu | author3=Franck Laloë |title=Quantum mechanics|year=1996|publisher=Wiley|location=Wiley-Interscience | isbn=978-0-471-56952-7 | pages=231–233}}</ref> |
|||
{{main|Introduction to quantum mechanics}} |
|||
===Visualization=== |
|||
[[Werner Heisenberg]] formulated the uncertainty principle in [[Niels Bohr]]'s institute at Copenhagen, while working on the mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics. |
|||
The uncertainty principle can be visualized using the position- and momentum-space wavefunctions for one spinless particle with mass in one dimension. |
|||
The more localized the position-space wavefunction, the more likely the particle is to be found with the position coordinates in that region, and correspondingly the momentum-space wavefunction is less localized so the possible momentum components the particle could have are more widespread. Conversely, the more localized the momentum-space wavefunction, the more likely the particle is to be found with those values of momentum components in that region, and correspondingly the less localized the position-space wavefunction, so the position coordinates the particle could occupy are more widespread. These wavefunctions are [[Fourier transform]]s of each other: mathematically, the uncertainty principle expresses the relationship between conjugate variables in the transform. |
|||
In 1925, following pioneering work with [[Hendrik Kramers]], Heisenberg developed [[matrix mechanics]], which replaced the ad-hoc [[old quantum theory]] with modern quantum mechanics. The central assumption was that the classical motion was not precise at the quantum level, and [[electrons]] in an atom did not travel on sharply defined orbits. Rather, the motion was smeared out in a strange way: the time [[Fourier transform]] only involving those frequencies which could be seen in quantum jumps. |
|||
[[File:Quantum mechanics travelling wavefunctions wavelength.svg|center|thumb|502px|Position ''x'' and momentum ''p'' wavefunctions corresponding to quantum particles. The colour opacity of the particles corresponds to the [[probability density]] of finding the particle with position ''x'' or momentum component ''p''.<br/> |
|||
Heisenberg's paper did not admit any unobservable quantities, like the exact position of the electron in an orbit at any time, he only allowed the theorist to talk about the Fourier components of the motion. Since the Fourier components were not defined at the classical frequencies, they could not be used to construct an exact trajectory, so that the formalism could not answer certain overly precise questions about where the electron was or how fast it was going. |
|||
'''Top:''' If wavelength ''λ'' is unknown, so are momentum ''p'', wave-vector ''k'' and energy ''E'' (de Broglie relations). As the particle is more localized in position space, Δ''x'' is smaller than for Δ''p<sub>x</sub>''.<br/> |
|||
The most striking property of Heisenberg's infinite matrices for the position and momentum is that they do not commute. His central result was the [[canonical commutation relation]]: |
|||
'''Bottom:''' If ''λ'' is known, so are ''p'', ''k'', and ''E''. As the particle is more localized in momentum space, Δ''p'' is smaller than for Δ''x''.]] |
|||
:<math> [X,P] = X P - P X = i \hbar </math>. |
|||
{{Clear}} |
|||
and this result does not have a clear physical interpretation. |
|||
===Wave mechanics interpretation=== |
|||
In March 1926, working in Bohr's institute, Heisenberg formulated the principle of uncertainty thereby laying the foundation of what became known as the [[Copenhagen interpretation]] of quantum mechanics. Heisenberg showed that the commutation relations implies an uncertainty, or in Bohr's language a [[complementarity]], between X and P. Any two variables which do not commute cannot be measured simultaneously--- the more precisely one is known, the less precisely the other can be known. |
|||
{{Main article|Wave packet|Schrödinger equation}} |
|||
{{multiple image |
|||
| align = right |
|||
| direction = vertical |
|||
| footer = Propagation of [[matter wave|de Broglie waves]] in 1d—real part of the [[complex number|complex]] amplitude is blue, imaginary part is green. The probability (shown as the colour [[opacity (optics)|opacity]]) of finding the particle at a given point ''x'' is spread out like a waveform, there is no definite position of the particle. As the amplitude increases above zero the [[curvature]] reverses sign, so the amplitude begins to decrease again, and vice versa—the result is an alternating amplitude: a wave. |
|||
| image1 = Propagation of a de broglie plane wave.svg |
|||
| caption1 = [[Plane wave]] |
|||
| width1 = 250 |
|||
| image2 = Propagation of a de broglie wavepacket.svg |
|||
| caption2 = [[Wave packet]] |
|||
| width2 = 250 |
|||
}} |
|||
According to the [[Matter wave|de Broglie hypothesis]], every object in the universe is associated with a [[wave]]. Thus every object, from an elementary particle to atoms, molecules and on up to planets and beyond are subject to the uncertainty principle. |
|||
The time-independent wave function of a single-moded plane wave of wavenumber ''k''<sub>0</sub> or momentum ''p''<sub>0</sub> is<ref>{{Citation | last = Hall | first = B. C. | title = Quantum Theory for Mathematicians | publisher = Springer | year = 2013 | pages = 60 | bibcode = 2013qtm..book.....H }}</ref> |
|||
== Uncertainty principle and observer effect == |
|||
<math display="block">\psi(x) \propto e^{ik_0 x} = e^{ip_0 x/\hbar} ~.</math> |
|||
The [[Born rule]] states that this should be interpreted as a [[probability density function|probability density amplitude function]] in the sense that the probability of finding the particle between ''a'' and ''b'' is |
|||
The uncertainty principle is often explained as the statement that the measurement of position necessarily disturbs a particle's momentum, and vice versa—i.e., that the uncertainty principle is a manifestation of the [[observer effect]]. |
|||
<math display="block"> \operatorname P [a \leq X \leq b] = \int_a^b |\psi(x)|^2 \, \mathrm{d}x ~.</math> |
|||
In the case of the single-mode plane wave, <math>|\psi(x)|^2</math> is ''1'' if <math>X=x</math> and ''0'' otherwise. In other words, the particle position is extremely uncertain in the sense that it could be essentially anywhere along the wave packet. |
|||
This explanation is sometimes misleading in a modern context, because it makes it seem that the disturbances are somehow conceptually avoidable--- that there are states of the particle with definite position and momentum, but the experimental devices we have today are just not good enough to produce those states. In fact, states with both definite position and momentum just do not exist in quantum mechanics, so it is not the measurement equipment that is at fault. |
|||
On the other hand, consider a wave function that is a [[superposition principle|sum of many waves]], which we may write as |
|||
It is also misleading in another way, because sometimes it is a ''failure'' to measure the particle that produces the disturbance. For example, if a perfect photographic film contains a small hole, and an incident photon is ''not'' observed, then its momentum becomes uncertain by a large amount. By not observing the photon, we discover that it went through the hole. |
|||
<math display="block">\psi(x) \propto \sum_n A_n e^{i p_n x/\hbar}~, </math> |
|||
where ''A''<sub>''n''</sub> represents the relative contribution of the mode ''p''<sub>''n''</sub> to the overall total. The figures to the right show how with the addition of many plane waves, the wave packet can become more localized. We may take this a step further to the [[continuum limit]], where the wave function is an [[integral]] over all possible modes |
|||
<math display="block">\psi(x) = \frac{1}{\sqrt{2 \pi \hbar}} \int_{-\infty}^\infty \varphi(p) \cdot e^{i p x/\hbar} \, dp ~, </math> |
|||
with <math>\varphi(p)</math> representing the amplitude of these modes and is called the wave function in [[momentum space]]. In mathematical terms, we say that <math>\varphi(p)</math> is the ''[[Fourier transform]]'' of <math>\psi(x)</math> and that ''x'' and ''p'' are [[conjugate variables]]. Adding together all of these plane waves comes at a cost, namely the momentum has become less precise, having become a mixture of waves of many different momenta.<ref name="L&L">{{cite book |first1=Lev Davidovich |last1=Landau|authorlink1=Lev Landau|first2=Evgeny Mikhailovich|last2=Lifshitz|authorlink2= Evgeny Lifshitz|year=1977 |title=Quantum Mechanics: Non-Relativistic Theory |edition=3rd |volume=3 |publisher=[[Pergamon Press]] |isbn=978-0-08-020940-1|url=https://archive.org/details/QuantumMechanics_104}}</ref> |
|||
One way to quantify the precision of the position and momentum is the [[standard deviation]] ''σ''. Since <math>|\psi(x)|^2</math> is a probability density function for position, we calculate its standard deviation. |
|||
It is misleading in yet another way, because sometimes the measurement can be performed far away. If two photons are emitted in opposite directions from the decay of positronium, the momentum of the two photons is opposite. By measuring the momentum of one particle, the momentum of the other is determined. This case is subtler, because it is impossible to introduce more uncertainties by measuring a distant particle, but it is possible to restrict the uncertainties in different ways, with different statistical properties, depending on what property of the distant particle you choose to measure. By restricting the uncertainty in p to be very small by a distant measurement, the remaining uncertainty in x stays large. |
|||
The precision of the position is improved, i.e. reduced ''σ''<sub>''x''</sub>, by using many plane waves, thereby weakening the precision of the momentum, i.e. increased ''σ''<sub>''p''</sub>. Another way of stating this is that ''σ''<sub>''x''</sub> and ''σ''<sub>''p''</sub> have an [[inverse relationship]] or are at least bounded from below. This is the uncertainty principle, the exact limit of which is the Kennard bound. |
|||
But Heisenberg did not focus on the mathematics of quantum mechanics, he was primarily concerned with establishing that the uncertainty is actually a property of the world--- that it is in fact physically impossible to measure the position and momentum of a particle to a precision better than that allowed by quantum mechanics. To do this, he used physical arguments based on the existence of quanta, but not the full quantum mechanical formalism. |
|||
===Proof of the Kennard inequality using wave mechanics=== |
|||
The reason is that this was a surprising prediction of quantum mechanics, which was not yet accepted. Many people would have considered it a flaw that there are no states of definite position and momentum. Heisenberg was trying to show that this was not a bug, but a feature--- a deep, surprising aspect of the universe. In order to do this, he could not just use the mathematical formalism, because it was the mathematical formalism itself that he was trying to justify. |
|||
We are interested in the [[variance]]s of position and momentum, defined as |
|||
===Heisenberg's microscope=== |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2 = \int_{-\infty}^\infty x^2 \cdot |\psi(x)|^2 \, dx - \left( \int_{-\infty}^\infty x \cdot |\psi(x)|^2 \, dx \right)^2</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_p^2 = \int_{-\infty}^\infty p^2 \cdot |\varphi(p)|^2 \, dp - \left( \int_{-\infty}^\infty p \cdot |\varphi(p)|^2 \, dp \right)^2~.</math> |
|||
[[Without loss of generality]], we will assume that the [[expected value|means]] vanish, which just amounts to a shift of the origin of our coordinates. (A more general proof that does not make this assumption is given below.) This gives us the simpler form |
|||
[[Image:Heisenberg gamma ray microscope.png|thumb|200px|right|Heisenberg's gamma-ray microscope for locating an electron (shown in blue). The incoming gamma ray (shown in green) is scattered by the electron up into the microscope's aperture angle θ. The scattered gamma-ray is shown in red. Classical [[optics]] shows that the electron position can be resolved only up to an uncertainty Δx that depends on θ and the wavelength λ of the incoming light.]] |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2 = \int_{-\infty}^\infty x^2 \cdot |\psi(x)|^2 \, dx</math> |
|||
{{main|Heisenberg's microscope}} |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_p^2 = \int_{-\infty}^\infty p^2 \cdot |\varphi(p)|^2 \, dp~.</math> |
|||
The function <math>f(x) = x \cdot \psi(x)</math> can be interpreted as a [[vector space|vector]] in a [[function space]]. We can define an [[inner product]] for a pair of functions ''u''(''x'') and ''v''(''x'') in this vector space: |
|||
One way in which Heisenberg originally argued for the uncertainty principle is by using an imaginary microscope as a measuring device <ref> Heisenberg W. (1930) ''Die Physikalischen Prinzipien der Quantenmechanik'' (Leipzig: Hirzel). English translation ''The Physical Principles of Quantum Theory'' (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1930).</ref> he imagines an experimenter trying to measure the position and momentum of an [[electron]] by shooting a [[photon]] at it. |
|||
<math display="block">\langle u \mid v \rangle = \int_{-\infty}^\infty u^*(x) \cdot v(x) \, dx,</math> |
|||
where the asterisk denotes the [[complex conjugate]]. |
|||
With this inner product defined, we note that the variance for position can be written as |
|||
If the photon has a short [[wavelength]], and therefore a large momentum, the position can be measured accurately. But the photon will be scattered in a random direction, transferring a large and uncertain amount of momentum to the electron. If the photon has a long [[wavelength]] and low momentum, the collision will not disturb the electron's momentum very much, but the scattering will reveal its position only vaguely. |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2 = \int_{-\infty}^\infty |f(x)|^2 \, dx = \langle f \mid f \rangle ~.</math> |
|||
We can repeat this for momentum by interpreting the function <math>\tilde{g}(p)=p \cdot \varphi(p)</math> as a vector, but we can also take advantage of the fact that <math>\psi(x)</math> and <math>\varphi(p)</math> are Fourier transforms of each other. We evaluate the inverse Fourier transform through [[integration by parts]]: |
|||
If a large [[aperture]] is used for the microscope, the electron's location can be well resolved (see [[Rayleigh criterion]]); but by the principle of [[conservation of momentum]], the transverse momentum of the incoming photon and hence the new momentum of the electron will be poorly resolved. If a small aperture is used, the accuracy of the two resolutions is the other way around. |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
g(x) &= \frac{1}{\sqrt{2 \pi \hbar}} \cdot \int_{-\infty}^\infty \tilde{g}(p) \cdot e^{ipx/\hbar} \, dp \\ |
|||
&= \frac{1}{\sqrt{2 \pi \hbar}} \int_{-\infty}^\infty p \cdot \varphi(p) \cdot e^{ipx/\hbar} \, dp \\ |
|||
&= \frac{1}{2 \pi \hbar} \int_{-\infty}^\infty \left[ p \cdot \int_{-\infty}^\infty \psi(\chi) e^{-ip\chi/\hbar} \, d\chi \right] \cdot e^{ipx/\hbar} \, dp \\ |
|||
&= \frac{i}{2 \pi} \int_{-\infty}^\infty \left[ \cancel{ \left. \psi(\chi) e^{-ip\chi/\hbar} \right|_{-\infty}^\infty } - \int_{-\infty}^\infty \frac{d\psi(\chi)}{d\chi} e^{-ip\chi/\hbar} \, d\chi \right] \cdot e^{ipx/\hbar} \, dp \\ |
|||
&= -i \int_{-\infty}^\infty \frac{d\psi(\chi)}{d\chi} \left[ \frac{1}{2 \pi}\int_{-\infty}^\infty \, e^{ip(x - \chi)/\hbar} \, dp \right]\, d\chi\\ |
|||
&= -i \int_{-\infty}^\infty \frac{d\psi(\chi)}{d\chi} \left[ \delta\left(\frac{x - \chi }{\hbar}\right) \right]\, d\chi\\ |
|||
&= -i \hbar \int_{-\infty}^\infty \frac{d\psi(\chi)}{d\chi} \left[ \delta\left(x - \chi \right) \right]\, d\chi\\ |
|||
&= -i \hbar \frac{d\psi(x)}{dx} \\ |
|||
&= \left( -i \hbar \frac{d}{dx} \right) \cdot \psi(x) , |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
where <math>v=\frac{\hbar}{-ip}e^{-ip\chi/\hbar}</math> in the integration by parts, the cancelled term vanishes because the wave function vanishes at infinity, and then use the [[Dirac delta function#History|Dirac delta function]] which is valid because <math>\dfrac{d\psi(\chi)}{d\chi}</math> does not depend on ''p'' . |
|||
The term <math display="inline">-i \hbar \frac{d}{dx}</math> is called the [[momentum operator]] in position space. Applying [[Plancherel theorem|Plancherel's theorem]], we see that the variance for momentum can be written as |
|||
The trade-offs imply that no matter what photon wavelength and aperture size are used, the product of the uncertainty in measured position and measured momentum is greater than or equal to a lower bound, which is up to a small numerical factor equal to [[Planck's constant]].<ref>{{cite book|last=Tipler|first=Paul A.|coauthors=Ralph A. Llewellyn|title=Modern Physics|edition=3rd Ed.|publisher=W. H. Freeman and Co.|year=1999|isbn=1-5725-9164-1|chapter=5-5}}</ref> Heisenberg did not care to formulate the uncertainty principle as an exact bound, and preferred to use it as a heuristic quantitative statement, correct up to small numerical factors. |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_p^2 = \int_{-\infty}^\infty |\tilde{g}(p)|^2 \, dp = \int_{-\infty}^\infty |g(x)|^2 \, dx = \langle g \mid g \rangle.</math> |
|||
The [[Cauchy–Schwarz inequality]] asserts that |
|||
===Modern understanding=== |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2 \sigma_p^2 = \langle f \mid f \rangle \cdot \langle g \mid g \rangle \ge |\langle f \mid g \rangle|^2 ~.</math> |
|||
The [[modulus squared]] of any complex number ''z'' can be expressed as |
|||
The Uncertainty Principle is a property of [[quantum state]]s, corresponding to the statistical properties of [[measurement in quantum mechanics]]. To clarify this point, consider the Heisenberg microscope experiment again. |
|||
<math display="block">|z|^{2} = \Big(\text{Re}(z)\Big)^{2}+\Big(\text{Im}(z)\Big)^{2} \geq \Big(\text{Im}(z)\Big)^{2} = \left(\frac{z-z^{\ast}}{2i}\right)^{2}. </math> |
|||
we let <math>z=\langle f|g\rangle</math> and <math>z^{*}=\langle g\mid f\rangle</math> and substitute these into the equation above to get |
|||
<math display="block">|\langle f\mid g\rangle|^2 \geq \left(\frac{\langle f\mid g\rangle-\langle g \mid f \rangle}{2i}\right)^2 ~.</math> |
|||
All that remains is to evaluate these inner products. |
|||
Suppose that a physicist has a way to prepare an electron in a particular quantum state. The physicist repeats this procedure 200 times, and for 100 times measures the ''position'', and 100 times measures the ''momentum''. The answers will be different in each of the first 100 and second 100 experiments, and they will cluster around some mean with some spread, measured by the [[standard deviation]]. |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
The standard deviation of the position times the standard deviation of the momentum is never less than <math>\scriptstyle \hbar/2</math>. |
|||
\langle f\mid g\rangle-\langle g\mid f\rangle &= \int_{-\infty}^\infty \psi^*(x) \, x \cdot \left(-i \hbar \frac{d}{dx}\right) \, \psi(x) \, dx - \int_{-\infty}^\infty \psi^*(x) \, \left(-i \hbar \frac{d}{dx}\right) \cdot x \, \psi(x) \, dx \\ |
|||
&= i \hbar \cdot \int_{-\infty}^\infty \psi^*(x) \left[ \left(-x \cdot \frac{d\psi(x)}{dx}\right) + \frac{d(x \psi(x))}{dx} \right] \, dx \\ |
|||
&= i \hbar \cdot \int_{-\infty}^\infty \psi^*(x) \left[ \left(-x \cdot \frac{d\psi(x)}{dx}\right) + \psi(x) + \left(x \cdot \frac{d\psi(x)}{dx}\right)\right] \, dx \\ |
|||
&= i \hbar \cdot \int_{-\infty}^\infty \psi^*(x) \psi(x) \, dx \\ |
|||
&= i \hbar \cdot \int_{-\infty}^\infty |\psi(x)|^2 \, dx \\ |
|||
&= i \hbar |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
Plugging this into the above inequalities, we get |
|||
[[Richard Feynman]] gives a simple argument for understanding the uncertainty in momentum and position. He starts with a particle which passes through a small hole, and then encounters a N detectors, covering each possible exit direction arranged in concentric hemispheres. He notes that when the innermost hemisphere of those counters records a particle, then the momentum of the particle and its past trajectory is known, in particular, it may be deduced that the particle left the small hole with the momentum that will be inferred later. |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2 \sigma_p^2 \ge |\langle f \mid g \rangle|^2 \ge \left(\frac{\langle f\mid g\rangle-\langle g\mid f\rangle}{2i}\right)^2 = \left(\frac{i \hbar}{2 i}\right)^2 = \frac{\hbar^2}{4}</math> |
|||
and taking the square root |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x \sigma_p \ge \frac{\hbar}{2}~.</math> |
|||
with equality if and only if ''p'' and ''x'' are linearly dependent. Note that the only ''physics'' involved in this proof was that <math>\psi(x)</math> and <math>\varphi(p)</math> are wave functions for position and momentum, which are Fourier transforms of each other. A similar result would hold for ''any'' pair of conjugate variables. |
|||
This is actually not in contradition with the uncertainty relation. Rather, once the detector detects the particle, the next detection involves a different counter further out, and to determine which one is impossible. This is the Heisenberg uncertainty relation, and the uncertainty translates to an uncertainty of prediction. |
|||
===Matrix mechanics interpretation=== |
|||
== Derivations == |
|||
{{Main article|Matrix mechanics}} |
|||
In matrix mechanics, observables such as position and momentum are represented by self-adjoint operators.<ref name="L&L"/> When considering pairs of observables, an important quantity is the ''[[commutator]]''. For a pair of operators {{mvar|Â}} and <math>\hat{B}</math>, one defines their commutator as |
|||
<math display="block">[\hat{A},\hat{B}]=\hat{A}\hat{B}-\hat{B}\hat{A}.</math> |
|||
In the case of position and momentum, the commutator is the [[canonical commutation relation]] |
|||
<math display="block">[\hat{x},\hat{p}]=i \hbar.</math> |
|||
The physical meaning of the non-commutativity can be understood by considering the effect of the commutator on position and momentum [[eigenstate]]s. Let <math>|\psi\rangle</math> be a right eigenstate of position with a constant eigenvalue {{math|''x''<sub>0</sub>}}. By definition, this means that <math>\hat{x}|\psi\rangle = x_0 |\psi\rangle.</math> Applying the commutator to <math>|\psi\rangle</math> yields |
|||
The uncertainty principle has a straightforward mathematical derivation. The key step is an application of the [[Cauchy-Schwarz inequality]], one of the most useful theorems of [[linear algebra]]. |
|||
<math display="block">[\hat{x},\hat{p}] | \psi \rangle = (\hat{x}\hat{p}-\hat{p}\hat{x}) | \psi \rangle = (\hat{x} - x_0 \hat{I}) \hat{p} \, | \psi \rangle = i \hbar | \psi \rangle,</math> |
|||
where {{mvar|Î}} is the [[identity matrix|identity operator]]. |
|||
Suppose, for the sake of [[proof by contradiction]], that <math>|\psi\rangle</math> is also a right eigenstate of momentum, with constant eigenvalue {{mvar|''p''<sub>0</sub>}}. If this were true, then one could write |
|||
For two arbitrary [[Self-adjoint operator|Hermitian operators]] ''A'': ''H'' → ''H'' and ''B'': ''H'' → ''H'', and any element ''x'' of ''H'', then |
|||
<math display="block">(\hat{x} - x_0 \hat{I}) \hat{p} \, | \psi \rangle = (\hat{x} - x_0 \hat{I}) p_0 \, | \psi \rangle = (x_0 \hat{I} - x_0 \hat{I}) p_0 \, | \psi \rangle=0.</math> |
|||
On the other hand, the above canonical commutation relation requires that |
|||
<math display="block">[\hat{x},\hat{p}] | \psi \rangle=i \hbar | \psi \rangle \ne 0.</math> |
|||
This implies that no quantum state can simultaneously be both a position and a momentum eigenstate. |
|||
When a state is measured, it is projected onto an eigenstate in the basis of the relevant observable. For example, if a particle's position is measured, then the state amounts to a position eigenstate. This means that the state is ''not'' a momentum eigenstate, however, but rather it can be represented as a sum of multiple momentum basis eigenstates. In other words, the momentum must be less precise. This precision may be quantified by the standard deviations, |
|||
In an [[inner product space]] the Cauchy-Schwarz inequality holds. |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x=\sqrt{\langle \hat{x}^2 \rangle-\langle \hat{x}\rangle^2}</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_p=\sqrt{\langle \hat{p}^2 \rangle-\langle \hat{p}\rangle^2}.</math> |
|||
As in the wave mechanics interpretation above, one sees a tradeoff between the respective precisions of the two, quantified by the uncertainty principle. |
|||
:<math>\left|\langle B x | A x \rangle\right |^2 \leq \|A x \|^2 \|B x \|^2 </math> |
|||
===Quantum harmonic oscillator stationary states=== |
|||
Rearranging this formula leads to: |
|||
{{Main article|Quantum harmonic oscillator|Stationary state}} |
|||
Consider a one-dimensional quantum harmonic oscillator. It is possible to express the position and momentum operators in terms of the [[creation and annihilation operators]]: |
|||
<math display="block">\hat x = \sqrt{\frac{\hbar}{2m\omega}}(a+a^\dagger)</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\hat p = i\sqrt{\frac{m \omega\hbar}{2}}(a^\dagger-a).</math> |
|||
Using the standard rules for creation and annihilation operators on the energy eigenstates, |
|||
:<math> |
|||
<math display="block">a^{\dagger}|n\rangle=\sqrt{n+1}|n+1\rangle</math> |
|||
\begin{align} |
|||
<math display="block">a|n\rangle=\sqrt{n}|n-1\rangle, </math> |
|||
\|A x \|^2 \|B x \|^2 \geq \left|\langle B x | A x \rangle\right |^2 &\geq \left|\mathrm{Im}\{\langle B x | A x \rangle\}\right |^2 \\ |
|||
the variances may be computed directly, |
|||
&= \frac{1}{4} \left|2 \, \mathrm{Im}\{\langle B x | A x \rangle\}\right |^2 \\ |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2 = \frac{\hbar}{m\omega} \left( n+\frac{1}{2}\right)</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_p^2 = \hbar m\omega \left( n+\frac{1}{2}\right)\, .</math> |
|||
&= \frac{1}{4} \left| \langle B x | A x \rangle - \langle A x | B x \rangle \right |^2 \\ |
|||
The product of these standard deviations is then |
|||
&= \frac{1}{4} \left| \langle A B x | x \rangle - \langle B A x | x \rangle \right |^2 \\ |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x \sigma_p = \hbar \left(n+\frac{1}{2}\right) \ge \frac{\hbar}{2}.~</math> |
|||
&= \frac{1}{4} |\langle (AB - BA)x | x \rangle|^2 |
|||
\end{align} |
|||
</math> |
|||
In particular, the above Kennard bound<ref name="Kennard" /> is saturated for the [[ground state]] {{math|''n''{{=}}0}}, for which the probability density is just the [[normal distribution]]. |
|||
This gives one form of the Robertson-Schrödinger relation, a general form of the Uncertainty Principle: |
|||
:<math>\frac{1}{4} |\langle [A,B]x | x \rangle|^2\leq \| A x \|^2 \| B x \|^2,</math> |
|||
where the operator [''A'',''B''] = ''AB'' - ''BA'' denotes the [[Commutator#Ring theory|commutator]] of ''A'' and ''B''. |
|||
To make the physical meaning of this inequality more directly apparent, it is often written in the equivalent form: |
|||
=== Quantum harmonic oscillators with Gaussian initial condition === |
|||
:<math> |
|||
{{multiple image |
|||
\Delta_{\psi} A \, \Delta_{\psi} B \ge \frac{1}{2} \left|\left\langle\left[{A},{B}\right]\right\rangle_\psi\right| |
|||
| align = right |
|||
</math> |
|||
| direction = vertical |
|||
| footer = |
|||
Position (blue) and momentum (red) probability densities for an initial Gaussian distribution. From top to bottom, the animations show the cases {{nowrap|1=Ω = ''ω''}}, {{nowrap|1=Ω = 2''ω''}}, and {{nowrap|1=Ω = ''ω''/2}}. Note the tradeoff between the widths of the distributions. |
|||
| width1 = 360 |
|||
| image1 = Position_and_momentum_of_a_Gaussian_initial_state_for_a_QHO,_balanced.gif |
|||
| width2 = 360 |
|||
| image2 = Position_and_momentum_of_a_Gaussian_initial_state_for_a_QHO,_narrow.gif |
|||
| width3 = 360 |
|||
| image3 = Position_and_momentum_of_a_Gaussian_initial_state_for_a_QHO,_wide.gif |
|||
}} |
|||
In a quantum harmonic oscillator of characteristic angular frequency ''ω'', place a state that is offset from the bottom of the potential by some displacement ''x''<sub>0</sub> as |
|||
where |
|||
<math display="block">\psi(x)=\left(\frac{m \Omega}{\pi \hbar}\right)^{1/4} \exp{\left( -\frac{m \Omega (x-x_0)^2}{2\hbar}\right)},</math> |
|||
where Ω describes the width of the initial state but need not be the same as ''ω''. Through integration over the [[Propagator#Basic examples: propagator of free particle and harmonic oscillator|propagator]], we can solve for the {{Not a typo|full time}}-dependent solution. After many cancelations, the probability densities reduce to |
|||
<math display="block">|\Psi(x,t)|^2 \sim \mathcal{N}\left( x_0 \cos{(\omega t)} , \frac{\hbar}{2 m \Omega} \left( \cos^2(\omega t) + \frac{\Omega^2}{\omega^2} \sin^2{(\omega t)} \right)\right)</math> |
|||
<math display="block">|\Phi(p,t)|^2 \sim \mathcal{N}\left( -m x_0 \omega \sin(\omega t), \frac{\hbar m \Omega}{2} \left( \cos^2{(\omega t)} + \frac{\omega^2}{\Omega^2} \sin^2{(\omega t)} \right)\right),</math> |
|||
where we have used the notation <math>\mathcal{N}(\mu, \sigma^2)</math> to denote a normal distribution of mean ''μ'' and variance ''σ''<sup>2</sup>. Copying the variances above and applying [[list of trigonometric identities|trigonometric identities]], we can write the product of the standard deviations as |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
\sigma_x \sigma_p&=\frac{\hbar}{2}\sqrt{\left( \cos^2{(\omega t)} + \frac{\Omega^2}{\omega^2} \sin^2{(\omega t)} \right)\left( \cos^2{(\omega t)} + \frac{\omega^2}{\Omega^2} \sin^2{(\omega t)} \right)} \\ |
|||
&= \frac{\hbar}{4}\sqrt{3+\frac{1}{2}\left(\frac{\Omega^2}{\omega^2}+\frac{\omega^2}{\Omega^2}\right)-\left(\frac{1}{2}\left(\frac{\Omega^2}{\omega^2}+\frac{\omega^2}{\Omega^2}\right)-1\right) \cos{(4 \omega t)}} |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
From the relations |
|||
:<math>\left\langle X \right\rangle_\psi = \left\langle \psi | X \psi \right\rangle</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\frac{\Omega^2}{\omega^2}+\frac{\omega^2}{\Omega^2} \ge 2, \quad |\cos(4 \omega t)| \le 1,</math> |
|||
we can conclude the following (the right most equality holds only when {{nowrap|1=Ω = ''ω''}}): |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x \sigma_p \ge \frac{\hbar}{4}\sqrt{3+\frac{1}{2} \left(\frac{\Omega^2}{\omega^2}+\frac{\omega^2}{\Omega^2}\right)-\left(\frac{1}{2} \left(\frac{\Omega^2}{\omega^2}+\frac{\omega^2}{\Omega^2}\right)-1\right)} = \frac{\hbar}{2}. </math> |
|||
===Coherent states=== |
|||
is the operator [[mean]] of observable ''X'' in the system state ψ and |
|||
{{Main article|Coherent state}} |
|||
A coherent state is a right eigenstate of the [[annihilation operator]], |
|||
<math display="block">\hat{a}|\alpha\rangle=\alpha|\alpha\rangle,</math> |
|||
which may be represented in terms of [[Fock state]]s as |
|||
<math display="block">|\alpha\rangle =e^{-{|\alpha|^2\over2}} \sum_{n=0}^\infty {\alpha^n \over \sqrt{n!}}|n\rangle</math> |
|||
In the picture where the coherent state is a massive particle in a quantum harmonic oscillator, the position and momentum operators may be expressed in terms of the annihilation operators in the same formulas above and used to calculate the variances, |
|||
:<math>\Delta_{\psi} X = \sqrt{\langle {X}^2\rangle_\psi - \langle {X}\rangle_\psi ^2}</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2 = \frac{\hbar}{2 m \omega},</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_p^2 = \frac{\hbar m \omega}{2}.</math> |
|||
Therefore, every coherent state saturates the Kennard bound |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x \sigma_p = \sqrt{\frac{\hbar}{2 m \omega}} \, \sqrt{\frac{\hbar m \omega}{2}} = \frac{\hbar}{2}. </math> |
|||
with position and momentum each contributing an amount <math display="inline">\sqrt{\hbar/2}</math> in a "balanced" way. Moreover, every [[squeezed coherent state]] also saturates the Kennard bound although the individual contributions of position and momentum need not be balanced in general. |
|||
===Particle in a box=== |
|||
is the operator [[standard deviation]] of observable ''X'' in the system state ψ. This formulation can be derived from the above formulation by plugging in <math>A - \lang A\rang_\psi</math> for ''A'' and <math>B - \lang B\rang_\psi</math> for ''B'', and using the fact that |
|||
{{Main article|Particle in a box}} |
|||
Consider a particle in a one-dimensional box of length <math>L</math>. The [[Particle in a box#Wavefunctions|eigenfunctions in position and momentum space]] are |
|||
<math display="block">\psi_n(x,t) =\begin{cases} |
|||
A \sin(k_n x)\mathrm{e}^{-\mathrm{i}\omega_n t}, & 0 < x < L,\\ |
|||
0, & \text{otherwise,} |
|||
\end{cases}</math> |
|||
and |
|||
<math display="block">\varphi_n(p,t)=\sqrt{\frac{\pi L}{\hbar}}\,\,\frac{n\left(1-(-1)^ne^{-ikL} \right) e^{-i \omega_n t}}{\pi ^2 n^2-k^2 L^2},</math> |
|||
where <math display="inline">\omega_n=\frac{\pi^2 \hbar n^2}{8 L^2 m}</math> and we have used the [[de Broglie relation]] <math>p=\hbar k</math>. The variances of <math>x</math> and <math>p</math> can be calculated explicitly: |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2=\frac{L^2}{12}\left(1-\frac{6}{n^2\pi^2}\right)</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_p^2=\left(\frac{\hbar n\pi}{L}\right)^2. </math> |
|||
The product of the standard deviations is therefore |
|||
:<math>[A,B]=[A - \lang A\rang, B - \lang B\rang].</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x \sigma_p = \frac{\hbar}{2} \sqrt{\frac{n^2\pi^2}{3}-2}.</math> |
|||
For all <math>n=1, \, 2, \, 3,\, \ldots</math>, the quantity <math display="inline">\sqrt{\frac{n^2\pi^2}{3}-2}</math> is greater than 1, so the uncertainty principle is never violated. For numerical concreteness, the smallest value occurs when <math>n = 1</math>, in which case |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x \sigma_p = \frac{\hbar}{2} \sqrt{\frac{\pi^2}{3}-2} \approx 0.568 \hbar > \frac{\hbar}{2}.</math> |
|||
===Constant momentum=== |
|||
This formulation acquires its physical interpretation, indicated by the suggestive terminology "mean" and "standard deviation", due to the properties of [[measurement in quantum mechanics]]. The precise position-momentum uncertainty principle is found when A be X and B be P, so that the commutator is <math>\scriptstyle i\hbar</math>. And one should definitely note that the inequality is rigorous. |
|||
{{Main article|Wave packet}} |
|||
[[File:Guassian Dispersion.gif|360 px|thumb|right|Position space probability density of an initially Gaussian state moving at minimally uncertain, constant momentum in free space]] |
|||
Assume a particle initially has a [[momentum space]] wave function described by a normal distribution around some constant momentum ''p''<sub>0</sub> according to |
|||
<math display="block">\varphi(p) = \left(\frac{x_0}{\hbar \sqrt{\pi}} \right)^{1/2} \exp\left(\frac{-x_0^2 (p-p_0)^2}{2\hbar^2}\right),</math> |
|||
where we have introduced a reference scale <math display="inline">x_0=\sqrt{\hbar/m\omega_0}</math>, with <math>\omega_0>0</math> describing the width of the distribution—cf. [[nondimensionalization]]. If the state is allowed to evolve in free space, then the time-dependent momentum and position space wave functions are |
|||
<math display="block">\Phi(p,t) = \left(\frac{x_0}{\hbar \sqrt{\pi}} \right)^{1/2} \exp\left(\frac{-x_0^2 (p-p_0)^2}{2\hbar^2}-\frac{ip^2 t}{2m\hbar}\right),</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\Psi(x,t) = \left(\frac{1}{x_0 \sqrt{\pi}} \right)^{1/2} \frac{e^{-x_0^2 p_0^2 /2\hbar^2}}{\sqrt{1+i\omega_0 t}} \, \exp\left(-\frac{(x-ix_0^2 p_0/\hbar)^2}{2x_0^2 (1+i\omega_0 t)}\right).</math> |
|||
Since <math> \langle p(t) \rangle = p_0</math> and <math>\sigma_p(t) = \hbar /(\sqrt{2}x_0)</math>, this can be interpreted as a particle moving along with constant momentum at arbitrarily high precision. On the other hand, the standard deviation of the position is |
|||
=== Matrix mechanics === |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x = \frac{x_0}{\sqrt{2}} \sqrt{1+\omega_0^2 t^2}</math> |
|||
such that the uncertainty product can only increase with time as |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x(t) \sigma_p(t) = \frac{\hbar}{2} \sqrt{1+\omega_0^2 t^2}</math> |
|||
==Mathematical formalism== |
|||
In [[matrix mechanics]], the commutator of the matrices X and P is always nonzero, it is a constant multiple <math>\scriptstyle i\hbar</math> of the [[identity matrix]]. This means that it is impossible for a state to have a definite values x for X and p for P, since then XP would be equal to the number xp and would equal PX. |
|||
Starting with Kennard's derivation of position-momentum uncertainty, [[Howard Percy Robertson]] developed<ref name="Robertson1929">{{Citation|last=Robertson|first=H. P.|title=The Uncertainty Principle|journal=Phys. Rev. | year=1929|volume=34|issue=1|pages=163–164|bibcode = 1929PhRv...34..163R |doi = 10.1103/PhysRev.34.163 }}</ref><ref name=Sen2014/> a formulation for arbitrary [[Self-adjoint operator|Hermitian operator]] operators |
|||
<math>\hat{\mathcal{O}}</math> expressed in terms of their standard deviation |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_{\mathcal{O}} = \sqrt{\langle \hat{\mathcal{O}}^2 \rangle-\langle \hat{\mathcal{O}}\rangle^2},</math> |
|||
where the brackets <math>\langle\hat{\mathcal{O}}\rangle</math> indicate an [[expectation value (quantum mechanics)|expectation value]] of the observable represented by operator <math>\hat{\mathcal{O}}</math>. For a pair of operators <math>\hat{A}</math> and <math>\hat{B}</math>, define their commutator as |
|||
<math display="block">[\hat{A},\hat{B}]=\hat{A}\hat{B}-\hat{B}\hat{A},</math> |
|||
and the Robertson uncertainty relation is given by<ref>{{Citation | last = Hall | first = B. C. | title = Quantum Theory for Mathematicians | publisher = Springer | year = 2013 | pages = 242–243 | bibcode = 2013qtm..book.....H }}</ref> |
|||
The commutator of two matrices is unchanged when they are shifted by a constant multiple of the identity--- for any two real numbers x and p |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_A \sigma_B \geq \left| \frac{1}{2i}\langle[\hat{A},\hat{B}]\rangle \right| = \frac{1}{2}\left|\langle[\hat{A},\hat{B}]\rangle \right|.</math> |
|||
[[Erwin Schrödinger]]<ref>Schrödinger, E., Zum Heisenbergschen Unschärfeprinzip, Berliner Berichte, 1930, pp. 296–303.</ref> showed how to allow for correlation between the operators, giving a stronger inequality, known as the '''Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation''',<ref name="Schrodinger1930">{{Citation | last = Schrödinger |first = E. | title = Zum Heisenbergschen Unschärfeprinzip | journal = Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-mathematische Klasse | volume = 14 | pages = 296–303 | year = 1930}}</ref><ref name=Sen2014/> |
|||
:<math>[X-x, P- p] = [X,P] = i\hbar \,</math> |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
Given any quantum state <math>\psi</math>, define the number x |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation = <math>\sigma_A^2\sigma_B^2 \geq \left| \frac{1}{2}\langle\{\hat{A}, \hat{B}\}\rangle - \langle \hat{A} \rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle \right|^2+ \left|\frac{1}{2i} \langle[ \hat{A}, \hat{B}] \rangle\right|^2,</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
where the anticommutator, <math>\{\hat{A},\hat{B}\}=\hat{A}\hat{B}+\hat{B}\hat{A}</math> is used. |
|||
{{math proof |
|||
:<math>x=\langle \psi|X|\psi\rangle = \sum_{ij} \psi^*_i X_{ij} \psi_j </math> |
|||
|title=Proof of the [[Erwin Schrödinger|Schrödinger]] uncertainty relation |
|||
|proof= |
|||
The derivation shown here incorporates and builds off of those shown in Robertson,<ref name="Robertson1929" /> Schrödinger<ref name="Schrodinger1930" /> and standard textbooks such as Griffiths.<ref name="GriffithsSchroeter2018">{{Cite book |last1=Griffiths |first1=David J. |url=https://www.cambridge.org/highereducation/product/9781316995433/book |title=Introduction to Quantum Mechanics |last2=Schroeter |first2=Darrell F. |year=2018 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-316-99543-3 |edition=3rd |doi=10.1017/9781316995433 |bibcode=2018iqm..book.....G |access-date=2024-01-27 |archive-date=2024-02-23 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240223160131/https://www.cambridge.org/highereducation/books/introduction-to-quantum-mechanics/990799CA07A83FC5312402AF6860311E#overview |url-status=live }}</ref>{{rp|138}} For any Hermitian operator <math>\hat{A}</math>, based upon the definition of [[variance]], we have |
|||
<math display="block"> \sigma_A^2 = \langle(\hat{A}-\langle \hat{A} \rangle)\Psi|(\hat{A}-\langle \hat{A} \rangle)\Psi\rangle. </math> |
|||
we let <math>|f\rangle=|(\hat{A}-\langle \hat{A} \rangle)\Psi\rangle </math> and thus |
|||
<math display="block"> \sigma_A^2 = \langle f\mid f\rangle\, .</math> |
|||
Similarly, for any other Hermitian operator <math> \hat{B} </math> in the same state |
|||
to be the expected value of the position, and |
|||
<math display="block"> \sigma_B^2 = \langle(\hat{B}-\langle \hat{B} \rangle)\Psi|(\hat{B}-\langle \hat{B} \rangle)\Psi\rangle = \langle g\mid g\rangle </math> |
|||
for <math> |g\rangle=|(\hat{B}-\langle \hat{B} \rangle)\Psi \rangle.</math> |
|||
The product of the two deviations can thus be expressed as |
|||
:<math>p=\langle \psi|P|\psi\rangle= \sum_{ij} \psi^*_i P_{ij} \psi_j</math> |
|||
{{NumBlk|:|<math> \sigma_A^2\sigma_B^2 = \langle f\mid f\rangle\langle g\mid g\rangle. </math>|{{EquationRef|1}}}} |
|||
to be the expected value of the momentum. The quantities <math>\scriptstyle \hat X = X-x </math> and <math>\scriptstyle \hat P = P-p </math> are only nonzero to the extent that the position and momentum are uncertain, to the extent that the state contains some values of X and P which deviate from the mean. The expected value of the commutator |
|||
In order to relate the two vectors <math>|f\rangle</math> and <math>|g\rangle</math>, we use the [[Cauchy–Schwarz inequality]]<ref name="Riley2006">{{Citation | last = Riley | first = K. F. | author2 = M. P. Hobson and S. J. Bence | title = Mathematical Methods for Physics and Engineering | publisher = Cambridge | year = 2006 | page = 246 }}{{ISBN?}}</ref> which is defined as |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\langle \ |
<math display="block">\langle f\mid f\rangle\langle g\mid g\rangle \geq |\langle f\mid g\rangle|^2, </math> |
||
and thus Equation ({{EquationNote|1}}) can be written as |
|||
\, </math> |
|||
{{NumBlk|:|<math>\sigma_A^2\sigma_B^2 \geq |\langle f\mid g\rangle|^2.</math>|{{EquationRef|2}}}} |
|||
can only be nonzero if the deviations in X in the state <math>\scriptstyle |\psi\rangle</math> times the deviations in P are large enough. |
|||
Since <math> \langle f\mid g\rangle</math> is in general a complex number, we use the fact that the modulus squared of any complex number <math>z</math> is defined as <math>|z|^2=zz^{*}</math>, where <math>z^{*}</math> is the complex conjugate of <math>z</math>. The modulus squared can also be expressed as |
|||
The size of the typical matrix elements can be estimated by summing the squares over the energy states <math>\scriptstyle |i\rangle</math>: |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\sum_i |\langle \psi| \hat X |i\rangle |^2 = \sum_i \langle \psi|\hat X |i\rangle\langle i|\hat X |\psi\rangle = \langle \psi| \hat X^2 |\psi\rangle = \Delta X^2 |
|||
\,</math> |
|||
and this is equal to the square of the deviation, matrix elements have a size approximately given by the deviation. |
|||
{{NumBlk|:|<math> |z|^2 = \Big(\operatorname{Re}(z)\Big)^2+\Big(\operatorname{Im}(z)\Big)^2 = \Big(\frac{z+z^\ast}{2}\Big)^2 +\Big(\frac{z-z^\ast}{2i}\Big)^2. </math>|{{EquationRef|3}}}} |
|||
So in order to produce the canonical commutation relations, the product of the deviations in any state has to be about <math>\scriptstyle \hbar</math>. |
|||
we let <math>z=\langle f\mid g\rangle</math> and <math>z^{*}=\langle g \mid f \rangle </math> and substitute these into the equation above to get |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\Delta X \Delta P \gtrapprox \hbar |
|||
</math> |
|||
{{NumBlk|:|<math>|\langle f\mid g\rangle|^2 = \bigg(\frac{\langle f\mid g\rangle+\langle g\mid f\rangle}{2}\bigg)^2 + \bigg(\frac{\langle f\mid g\rangle-\langle g\mid f\rangle}{2i}\bigg)^2 </math>|{{EquationRef|4}}}} |
|||
This heuristic estimate can be made into a precise inequality using the [[Cauchy-Schwartz inequality]], exactly as before. The inner product of the two vectors in parentheses: |
|||
The inner product <math>\langle f\mid g\rangle </math> is written out explicitly as |
|||
:<math> |
|||
<math display="block">\langle f\mid g\rangle = \langle(\hat{A}-\langle \hat{A} \rangle)\Psi|(\hat{B}-\langle \hat{B} \rangle)\Psi\rangle,</math> |
|||
and using the fact that <math>\hat{A}</math> and <math>\hat{B}</math> are Hermitian operators, we find |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\begin{align} |
|||
\langle f\mid g\rangle & = \langle\Psi|(\hat{A}-\langle \hat{A}\rangle)(\hat{B}-\langle \hat{B}\rangle)\Psi\rangle \\[4pt] |
|||
& = \langle\Psi\mid(\hat{A}\hat{B}-\hat{A}\langle \hat{B}\rangle - \hat{B}\langle \hat{A}\rangle + \langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle)\Psi\rangle \\[4pt] |
|||
& = \langle\Psi\mid\hat{A}\hat{B}\Psi\rangle-\langle\Psi\mid\hat{A}\langle \hat{B}\rangle\Psi\rangle |
|||
-\langle\Psi\mid\hat{B}\langle \hat{A}\rangle\Psi\rangle+\langle\Psi\mid\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle\Psi\rangle \\[4pt] |
|||
& =\langle \hat{A}\hat{B}\rangle-\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle-\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle+\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle \\[4pt] |
|||
& =\langle \hat{A}\hat{B}\rangle-\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle. |
|||
\end{align} |
|||
</math> |
</math> |
||
Similarly it can be shown that <math>\langle g\mid f\rangle = \langle \hat{B}\hat{A}\rangle-\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle.</math> |
|||
is bounded above by the product of the lengths of each vector: |
|||
Thus, we have |
|||
:<math> |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
|(\langle \psi|\hat X)(\hat P |\psi\rangle)|^2 \le \Delta X^2 \Delta P^2 |
|||
\langle f\mid g\rangle-\langle g\mid f\rangle = \langle \hat{A}\hat{B}\rangle-\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle-\langle \hat{B}\hat{A}\rangle+\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle = \langle [\hat{A},\hat{B}]\rangle |
|||
</math> |
</math> |
||
and |
|||
<math display="block">\langle f\mid g\rangle+\langle g\mid f\rangle = \langle \hat{A}\hat{B}\rangle-\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle+\langle \hat{B}\hat{A}\rangle-\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle = \langle \{\hat{A},\hat{B}\}\rangle -2\langle \hat{A}\rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle. </math> |
|||
We now substitute the above two equations above back into Eq. ({{EquationNote|4}}) and get |
|||
so, rigorously, for any state: |
|||
<math display="block">|\langle f\mid g\rangle|^2=\Big(\frac{1}{2}\langle\{\hat{A},\hat{B}\}\rangle - \langle \hat{A} \rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle\Big)^2 + \Big(\frac{1}{2i} \langle[\hat{A},\hat{B}]\rangle\Big)^{2}\, .</math> |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\Delta X \Delta P \ge \langle \psi | \hat X \hat P |\psi \rangle |
|||
Substituting the above into Equation ({{EquationNote|2}}) we get the Schrödinger uncertainty relation |
|||
</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_A\sigma_B \geq \sqrt{\Big(\frac{1}{2}\langle\{\hat{A},\hat{B}\}\rangle - \langle \hat{A} \rangle\langle \hat{B}\rangle\Big)^2 + \Big(\frac{1}{2i} \langle[\hat{A},\hat{B}]\rangle\Big)^2}.</math> |
|||
This proof has an issue<ref>{{Citation|last=Davidson|first=E. R.|title=On Derivations of the Uncertainty Principle|journal=J. Chem. Phys.|volume=42|year=1965|doi=10.1063/1.1696139|bibcode = 1965JChPh..42.1461D|issue=4|pages=1461–1462 }}</ref> related to the domains of the operators involved. For the proof to make sense, the vector <math> \hat{B} |\Psi \rangle</math> has to be in the domain of the [[unbounded operator]] <math> \hat{A}</math>, which is not always the case. In fact, the Robertson uncertainty relation is false if <math>\hat{A}</math> is an angle variable and <math>\hat{B}</math> is the derivative with respect to this variable. In this example, the commutator is a nonzero constant—just as in the Heisenberg uncertainty relation—and yet there are states where the product of the uncertainties is zero.<ref name="Hall2013"/> (See the counterexample section below.) This issue can be overcome by using a [[variational method]] for the proof,<ref name="Jackiw">{{Citation|last=Jackiw| first=Roman|title=Minimum Uncertainty Product, Number-Phase Uncertainty Product, and Coherent States|journal=J. Math. Phys.|volume=9|year=1968|doi=10.1063/1.1664585|bibcode = 1968JMP.....9..339J|issue=3|pages=339–346 }}</ref><ref name="CarruthersNieto">{{Citation|first1=P. |last1=Carruthers|last2= Nieto|first2=M. M.|title=Phase and Angle Variables in Quantum Mechanics|journal=Rev. Mod. Phys.|volume=40|year=1968|doi=10.1103/RevModPhys.40.411|bibcode = 1968RvMP...40..411C|issue=2|pages=411–440 }}</ref> or by working with an exponentiated version of the canonical commutation relations.<ref name="Hall2013"/> |
|||
Note that in the general form of the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation, there is no need to assume that the operators <math>\hat{A}</math> and <math>\hat{B}</math> are [[Self-adjoint operator#Self-adjoint operators|self-adjoint operators]]. It suffices to assume that they are merely [[Self-adjoint operator#Symmetric operators|symmetric operators]]. (The distinction between these two notions is generally glossed over in the physics literature, where the term ''Hermitian'' is used for either or both classes of operators. See Chapter 9 of Hall's book<ref>{{Citation | last = Hall | first = B. C. | title = Quantum Theory for Mathematicians | publisher = Springer | year = 2013 | bibcode = 2013qtm..book.....H }}</ref> for a detailed discussion of this important but technical distinction.) |
|||
}} |
|||
===Phase space=== |
|||
In the [[phase space formulation]] of quantum mechanics, the Robertson–Schrödinger relation follows from a positivity condition on a real star-square function. Given a [[Wigner quasi-probability distribution|Wigner function]] <math>W(x,p)</math> with [[Moyal product|star product]] ★ and a function ''f'', the following is generally true:<ref>{{Cite journal | last1 = Curtright | first1 = T. |last2= Zachos | first2= C. | title = Negative Probability and Uncertainty Relations| journal = Modern Physics Letters A | volume = 16 | issue = 37 | pages = 2381–2385 | doi = 10.1142/S021773230100576X | year = 2001 |arxiv = hep-th/0105226 |bibcode = 2001MPLA...16.2381C | s2cid = 119669313 }}</ref> |
|||
<math display="block">\langle f^* \star f \rangle =\int (f^* \star f) \, W(x,p) \, dx \, dp \ge 0 ~.</math> |
|||
Choosing <math>f = a + bx + cp</math>, we arrive at |
|||
<math display="block">\langle f^* \star f \rangle =\begin{bmatrix}a^* & b^* & c^* \end{bmatrix}\begin{bmatrix}1 & \langle x \rangle & \langle p \rangle \\ \langle x \rangle & \langle x \star x \rangle & \langle x \star p \rangle \\ \langle p \rangle & \langle p \star x \rangle & \langle p \star p \rangle \end{bmatrix}\begin{bmatrix}a \\ b \\ c\end{bmatrix} \ge 0 ~.</math> |
|||
Since this positivity condition is true for ''all'' ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'', it follows that all the eigenvalues of the matrix are non-negative. |
|||
The non-negative eigenvalues then imply a corresponding non-negativity condition on the [[determinant]], |
|||
<math display="block">\det\begin{bmatrix}1 & \langle x \rangle & \langle p \rangle \\ \langle x \rangle & \langle x \star x \rangle & \langle x \star p \rangle \\ \langle p \rangle & \langle p \star x \rangle & \langle p \star p \rangle \end{bmatrix} |
|||
= \det\begin{bmatrix}1 & \langle x \rangle & \langle p \rangle \\ \langle x \rangle & \langle x^2 \rangle & \left\langle xp + \frac{i\hbar}{2} \right\rangle \\ \langle p \rangle & \left\langle xp - \frac{i\hbar}{2} \right\rangle & \langle p^2 \rangle \end{bmatrix} |
|||
\ge 0~,</math> |
|||
or, explicitly, after algebraic manipulation, |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x^2 \sigma_p^2 = \left( \langle x^2 \rangle - \langle x \rangle^2 \right)\left( \langle p^2 \rangle - \langle p \rangle^2 \right)\ge \left( \langle xp \rangle - \langle x \rangle \langle p \rangle \right)^2 + \frac{\hbar^2}{4} ~.</math> |
|||
===Examples=== |
|||
Since the Robertson and Schrödinger relations are for general operators, the relations can be applied to any two observables to obtain specific uncertainty relations. A few of the most common relations found in the literature are given below. |
|||
* '''Position–linear momentum uncertainty relation''': for the position and linear momentum operators, the canonical commutation relation <math>[\hat{x}, \hat{p}] = i\hbar</math> implies the Kennard inequality from above: <math display="block">\sigma_x \sigma_p \geq \frac{\hbar}{2}.</math> |
|||
* '''Angular momentum uncertainty relation''': For two orthogonal components of the [[angular momentum|total angular momentum]] operator of an object: <math display="block">\sigma_{J_i} \sigma_{J_j} \geq \frac{\hbar}{2} \big|\langle J_k\rangle\big|,</math> where ''i'', ''j'', ''k'' are distinct, and ''J''<sub>''i''</sub> denotes angular momentum along the ''x''<sub>''i''</sub> axis. This relation implies that unless all three components vanish together, only a single component of a system's angular momentum can be defined with arbitrary precision, normally the component parallel to an external (magnetic or electric) field. Moreover, for <math>[J_x, J_y] = i \hbar \varepsilon_{xyz} J_z</math>, a choice <math>\hat{A} = J_x</math>, <math>\hat{B} = J_y</math>, in angular momentum multiplets, ''ψ'' = |''j'', ''m''⟩, bounds the [[Casimir invariant]] (angular momentum squared, <math>\langle J_x^2+ J_y^2 + J_z^2 \rangle</math>) from below and thus yields useful constraints such as {{nobr|''j''(''j'' + 1) ≥ ''m''(''m'' + 1)}}, and hence ''j'' ≥ ''m'', among others. |
|||
* For the number of electrons in a [[superconductor]] and the [[Phase factor|phase]] of its [[Ginzburg–Landau theory|Ginzburg–Landau order parameter]]<ref>{{Citation |last=Likharev |first=K. K. |author2=A. B. Zorin |title=Theory of Bloch-Wave Oscillations in Small Josephson Junctions |journal=J. Low Temp. Phys. |volume=59 |issue=3/4 |pages=347–382 |year=1985 |doi=10.1007/BF00683782 |bibcode=1985JLTP...59..347L|s2cid=120813342 }}</ref><ref>{{Citation |first=P. W. |last=Anderson |editor-last=Caianiello |editor-first=E. R. |contribution=Special Effects in Superconductivity |title=Lectures on the Many-Body Problem, Vol. 2 |year=1964 |place=New York |publisher=Academic Press}}</ref> <math display="block"> \Delta N \, \Delta \varphi \geq 1. </math> |
|||
===Limitations=== |
|||
The derivation of the Robertson inequality for operators <math>\hat{A}</math> and <math>\hat{B}</math> requires <math>\hat{A}\hat{B}\psi</math> and <math>\hat{B}\hat{A}\psi</math> to be defined. There are quantum systems where these conditions are not valid.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Davidson |first=Ernest R. |date=1965-02-15 |title=On Derivations of the Uncertainty Principle |url=https://pubs.aip.org/jcp/article/42/4/1461/208937/On-Derivations-of-the-Uncertainty-Principle |journal=The Journal of Chemical Physics |language=en |volume=42 |issue=4 |pages=1461–1462 |doi=10.1063/1.1696139 |bibcode=1965JChPh..42.1461D |issn=0021-9606 |access-date=2024-01-20 |archive-date=2024-02-23 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240223160247/https://pubs.aip.org/aip/jcp/article-abstract/42/4/1461/208937/On-Derivations-of-the-Uncertainty-Principle?redirectedFrom=fulltext |url-status=live }}</ref> |
|||
One example is a quantum [[particle in a ring|particle on a ring]], where the wave function depends on an angular variable <math>\theta</math> in the interval <math>[0,2\pi]</math>. Define "position" and "momentum" operators <math>\hat{A}</math> and <math>\hat{B}</math> by |
|||
<math display="block">\hat{A}\psi(\theta)=\theta\psi(\theta),\quad \theta\in [0,2\pi],</math> |
|||
and |
|||
<math display="block">\hat{B}\psi=-i\hbar\frac{d\psi}{d\theta},</math> |
|||
with periodic boundary conditions on <math>\hat{B}</math>. The definition of <math>\hat{A}</math> depends the <math>\theta</math> range from 0 to <math>2\pi</math>. These operators satisfy the usual commutation relations for position and momentum operators, <math>[\hat{A},\hat{B}]=i\hbar</math>. More precisely, <math>\hat{A}\hat{B}\psi-\hat{B}\hat{A}\psi=i\hbar\psi</math> whenever both <math>\hat{A}\hat{B}\psi</math> and <math>\hat{B}\hat{A}\psi</math> are defined, and the space of such <math>\psi</math> is a dense subspace of the quantum Hilbert space.<ref>{{Citation | last = Hall | first = B. C. | title = Quantum Theory for Mathematicians | publisher = Springer | year = 2013 | page = 245 | bibcode = 2013qtm..book.....H }}</ref> |
|||
Now let <math>\psi</math> be any of the eigenstates of <math>\hat{B}</math>, which are given by <math>\psi(\theta)=e^{2\pi in\theta}</math>. These states are normalizable, unlike the eigenstates of the momentum operator on the line. Also the operator <math>\hat{A}</math> is bounded, since <math>\theta</math> ranges over a bounded interval. Thus, in the state <math>\psi</math>, the uncertainty of <math>B</math> is zero and the uncertainty of <math>A</math> is finite, so that |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_A\sigma_B=0.</math> |
|||
The Robertson uncertainty principle does not apply in this case: <math>\psi</math> is not in the domain of the operator <math>\hat{B}\hat{A}</math>, since multiplication by <math>\theta</math> disrupts the periodic boundary conditions imposed on <math>\hat{B}</math>.<ref name="Hall2013">{{Citation | last = Hall | first = B. C. | title = Quantum Theory for Mathematicians | publisher = Springer | year = 2013 | pages = 245 | bibcode = 2013qtm..book.....H }}</ref> |
|||
For the usual position and momentum operators <math>\hat{X}</math> and <math>\hat{P}</math> on the real line, no such counterexamples can occur. As long as <math>\sigma_x</math> and <math>\sigma_p</math> are defined in the state <math>\psi</math>, the Heisenberg uncertainty principle holds, even if <math>\psi</math> fails to be in the domain of <math>\hat{X}\hat{P}</math> or of <math>\hat{P}\hat{X}</math>.<ref>{{Citation | last = Hall | first = B. C. | title = Quantum Theory for Mathematicians | publisher = Springer | year = 2013 | pages = 246 | bibcode = 2013qtm..book.....H }}</ref> |
|||
===Mixed states=== |
|||
The Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty can be improved noting that it must hold for all components <math>\varrho_k</math> in any decomposition of the [[density matrix]] given as |
|||
the real part of a matrix M is <math>\scriptstyle (M+M^\dagger)/2 </math>, so that the real part of the product of two Hermitian matrices <math>\scriptstyle \hat X \hat P </math> is: |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\varrho=\sum_k p_k \varrho_k. |
|||
\mathrm{Re} (\hat X \hat P) = { \hat X \hat P + \hat X \hat P \over 2 } = {\{X,P\}\over 2} |
|||
</math> |
</math> |
||
Here, for the probabilities <math>p_k\ge0</math> and <math>\sum_k p_k=1</math> hold. Then, using the relation |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\sum_k a_k \sum_k b_k \ge \left(\sum_k \sqrt{a_k b_k}\right)^2 |
|||
</math> |
|||
for <math> a_k,b_k\ge 0</math>, |
|||
it follows that<ref name="PhysRevResearch21">{{cite journal |last1=Tóth |first1=Géza |last2=Fröwis |first2=Florian |title=Uncertainty relations with the variance and the quantum Fisher information based on convex decompositions of density matrices |journal=Physical Review Research |date=31 January 2022 |volume=4 |issue=1 |pages=013075 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevResearch.4.013075|arxiv=2109.06893 |bibcode=2022PhRvR...4a3075T |s2cid=237513549 }}</ref> |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\sigma_A^2 \sigma_B^2 \geq \left[\sum_k p_k L(\varrho_k)\right]^2, |
|||
</math> |
|||
where the function in the bound is defined |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
L(\varrho) = \sqrt{\left | \frac{1}{2}\operatorname{tr}(\rho\{A,B\}) - \operatorname{tr}(\rho A)\operatorname{tr}(\rho B)\right |^2 +\left | \frac{1}{2i} \operatorname{tr}(\rho[A,B])\right | ^2}. |
|||
</math> |
|||
The above relation very often has a bound larger than that of the original Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation. Thus, we need to calculate the bound of the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty for the mixed components of the quantum state rather than for the quantum state, and compute an average of their square roots. The following expression is stronger than the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\sigma_A^2 \sigma_B^2 \geq \left[\max_{p_k,\varrho_k} \sum_k p_k L(\varrho_k)\right]^2, |
|||
</math> |
|||
where on the right-hand side there is a concave roof over the decompositions of the density matrix. |
|||
The improved relation above is saturated by all single-qubit quantum states.<ref name="PhysRevResearch21" /> |
|||
With similar arguments, one can derive a relation with a convex roof on the right-hand side<ref name="PhysRevResearch21" /> |
|||
while the imaginary part is |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\sigma_A^2 F_Q[\varrho,B] \geq 4 \left[\min_{p_k,\Psi_k} \sum_k p_k L(\vert \Psi_k\rangle\langle \Psi_k\vert)\right]^2 |
|||
\mathrm{Im} (\hat X \hat P) = {\hat X \hat P - \hat X \hat P \over 2i } = { [\hat X,\hat P] \over 2i }= { \hbar \over 2}. |
|||
</math> |
</math> |
||
where <math>F_Q[\varrho,B]</math> denotes the [[quantum Fisher information]] and the density matrix is decomposed to pure states as |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\varrho=\sum_k p_k \vert \Psi_k\rangle \langle \Psi_k\vert. |
|||
</math> |
|||
The derivation takes advantage of the fact that the [[quantum Fisher information]] is the convex roof of the variance times four.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Tóth |first1=Géza |last2=Petz |first2=Dénes |title=Extremal properties of the variance and the quantum Fisher information |journal=Physical Review A |date=20 March 2013 |volume=87 |issue=3 |pages=032324 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.87.032324|bibcode=2013PhRvA..87c2324T |arxiv=1109.2831 |s2cid=55088553 }}</ref><ref>{{cite arXiv |last1=Yu |first1=Sixia |title=Quantum Fisher Information as the Convex Roof of Variance |date=2013 |eprint=1302.5311|class=quant-ph }}</ref> |
|||
A simpler inequality follows without a convex roof<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Fröwis |first1=Florian |last2=Schmied |first2=Roman |last3=Gisin |first3=Nicolas |title=Tighter quantum uncertainty relations following from a general probabilistic bound |journal=Physical Review A |date=2 July 2015 |volume=92 |issue=1 |pages=012102 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.92.012102|arxiv=1409.4440 |bibcode=2015PhRvA..92a2102F |s2cid=58912643 }}</ref> |
|||
The magnitude of <math>\scriptstyle \langle \psi | \hat X \hat P |\psi \rangle </math> is bigger than the magnitude of its imaginary part, which is the expected value of the imaginary part of the matrix: |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\sigma_A^2 F_Q[\varrho,B] \geq \vert \langle i[A,B]\rangle\vert^2, |
|||
\Delta X \Delta P \ge | \langle \psi | \hat X \hat P |\psi \rangle | \ge | \langle \psi | \mathrm{Im} (\hat X \hat P ) |\psi\rangle | = {\hbar \over 2}. |
|||
</math> |
</math> |
||
which is stronger than the Heisenberg uncertainty relation, since for the quantum Fisher information we have |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
F_Q[\varrho,B]\le 4 \sigma_B, |
|||
</math> |
|||
while for pure states the equality holds. |
|||
===The Maccone–Pati uncertainty relations=== |
|||
Note that the uncertainty product is for the same reason bounded below by the expected value of the anticommutator, which adds a term to the uncertainty relation. The extra term is not as useful for the uncertainty of position and momentum, because it has zero expected value in a gaussian wavepacket, like the ground state of a harmonic oscillator. The anticommutator term is useful for bounding the uncertainty of spin operators though. |
|||
The Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation can be trivial if the state of the system is chosen to be eigenstate of one of the observable. The stronger uncertainty relations proved by Lorenzo Maccone and [[Arun K. Pati]] give non-trivial bounds on the sum of the variances for two incompatible observables.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Maccone|first1=Lorenzo|last2=Pati|first2=Arun K.|title=Stronger Uncertainty Relations for All Incompatible Observables|journal=Physical Review Letters|date=31 December 2014|volume=113| issue=26|page=260401|doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.113.260401|pmid=25615288|arxiv=1407.0338|bibcode=2014PhRvL.113z0401M|s2cid=21334130 }}</ref> (Earlier works on uncertainty relations formulated as the sum of variances include, e.g., Ref.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Huang |first1=Yichen |title=Variance-based uncertainty relations |journal=Physical Review A |date=10 August 2012 |volume=86 |issue=2 |page=024101 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.86.024101|arxiv=1012.3105 |bibcode=2012PhRvA..86b4101H |s2cid=118507388 }}</ref> due to Yichen Huang.) For two non-commuting observables <math>A</math> and <math>B</math> the first stronger uncertainty relation is given by |
|||
<math display="block"> \sigma_{A}^2 + \sigma_{ B}^2 \ge \pm i \langle \Psi\mid [A, B]|\Psi \rangle + \mid \langle \Psi\mid(A \pm i B)\mid{\bar \Psi} \rangle|^2, </math> |
|||
where <math> \sigma_{A}^2 = \langle \Psi |A^2 |\Psi \rangle - \langle \Psi \mid A \mid \Psi \rangle^2 </math>, <math> \sigma_{B}^2 = \langle \Psi |B^2 |\Psi \rangle - \langle \Psi \mid B \mid\Psi \rangle^2 </math>, <math>|{\bar \Psi} \rangle </math> is a normalized vector that is orthogonal to the state of the system <math>|\Psi \rangle </math> and one should choose the sign of <math>\pm i \langle \Psi\mid[A, B]\mid\Psi \rangle </math> to make this real quantity a positive number. |
|||
The second stronger uncertainty relation is given by |
|||
=== Wave mechanics === |
|||
<math display="block"> \sigma_A^2 + \sigma_B^2 \ge \frac{1}{2}| \langle {\bar \Psi}_{A+B} \mid(A + B)\mid \Psi \rangle|^2 </math> |
|||
where <math>| {\bar \Psi}_{A+B} \rangle </math> is a state orthogonal to <math> |\Psi \rangle </math>. |
|||
The form of <math>| {\bar \Psi}_{A+B} \rangle </math> implies that the right-hand side of the new uncertainty relation is nonzero unless <math>| \Psi\rangle </math> is an eigenstate of <math>(A + B)</math>. One may note that <math>|\Psi \rangle </math> can be an eigenstate of <math>( A+ B)</math> without being an eigenstate of either <math> A</math> or <math> B </math>. However, when <math> |\Psi \rangle </math> is an eigenstate of one of the two observables the Heisenberg–Schrödinger uncertainty relation becomes trivial. But the lower bound in the new relation is nonzero unless <math> |\Psi \rangle </math> is an eigenstate of both. |
|||
== Energy–time == |
|||
In Schrödinger's [[Schrödinger's equation|wave mechanics]] The quantum mechanical wavefunction contains information about both the position and the momentum of the particle. The position of the particle is where the wave is concentrated, while the momentum is the typical wavelength. |
|||
{{anchor|Time–energy uncertainty relation}} |
|||
An energy–time uncertainty relation like |
|||
<math display="block"> \Delta E \Delta t \gtrsim \hbar/2,</math> has a long, controversial history; the meaning of <math>\Delta t</math> and <math>\Delta E</math> varies and different formulations have different arenas of validity.<ref name="Busch2002">{{Cite book |last=Busch |first=Paul |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/3-540-45846-8_3 |title=Time in Quantum Mechanics. Lecture Notes in Physics |date=2002 |publisher=Springer Berlin Heidelberg |isbn=978-3-540-43294-4 |editor-last=Muga |editor-first=J. G. |volume=72 |location=Berlin, Heidelberg |pages=69–98 |language=en |chapter=The Time-Energy Uncertainty Relation |doi=10.1007/3-540-45846-8_3 |editor-last2=Mayato |editor-first2=R. Sala |editor-last3=Egusquiza |editor-first3=I. L.}}</ref> However, one well-known application is both well established<ref>{{Cite book |last=Wigner |first=E. P. |chapter=On the Time–Energy Uncertainty Relation |date=1997 |editor-last=Wightman |editor-first=Arthur S. |title=Part I: Particles and Fields. Part II: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics |chapter-url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-3-662-09203-3_58 |language=en |location=Berlin, Heidelberg |publisher=Springer Berlin Heidelberg |pages=538–548 |doi=10.1007/978-3-662-09203-3_58 |isbn=978-3-642-08179-8}}</ref><ref name=Hilgevoord/> and experimentally verified:<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Lynch |first1=F. J. |last2=Holland |first2=R. E. |last3=Hamermesh |first3=M. |date=1960-10-15 |title=Time Dependence of Resonantly Filtered Gamma Rays from Fe 57 |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRev.120.513 |journal=Physical Review |language=en |volume=120 |issue=2 |pages=513–520 |doi=10.1103/PhysRev.120.513 |issn=0031-899X}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |
|||
| last = Frauenfelder |first=H. |
|||
| year = 1962 |
|||
| title = The Mössbauer Effect |
|||
| url = https://archive.org/details/mssbauereffec00frau | publisher = [[W. A. Benjamin]] |
|||
| lccn = 61018181|page=66 |
|||
}}</ref> the connection between the life-time of a resonance state, <math>\tau_{\sqrt{1/2}}</math> and its energy width <math>\Delta E</math>: |
|||
<math display=block>\tau_{\sqrt{1/2}} \Delta E = \pi\hbar/4.</math> |
|||
In particle-physics, widths from experimental fits to the [[Relativistic Breit–Wigner distribution|Breit–Wigner energy distribution]] are used to characterize the lifetime of quasi-stable or decaying states.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Bohm |first1=Arno R. |last2=Sato |first2=Yoshihiro |date=2005-04-28 |title=Relativistic resonances: Their masses, widths, lifetimes, superposition, and causal evolution |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.71.085018 |journal=Physical Review D |language=en |volume=71 |issue=8 |page=085018 |arxiv=hep-ph/0412106 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.71.085018 |bibcode=2005PhRvD..71h5018B |s2cid=119417992 |issn=1550-7998}}</ref> |
|||
An informal, heuristic meaning of the principle is the following:<ref>Karplus, Martin, and Porter, Richard Needham (1970). ''Atoms and Molecules''. California: Benjamin Cummings. p. 68 {{ISBN|978-0805352184}}. {{oclc|984466711}}</ref> A state that only exists for a short time cannot have a definite energy. To have a definite energy, the frequency of the state must be defined accurately, and this requires the state to hang around for many cycles, the reciprocal of the required accuracy. For example, in [[Electromagnetic spectroscopy|spectroscopy]], excited states have a finite lifetime. By the time–energy uncertainty principle, they do not have a definite energy, and, each time they decay, the energy they release is slightly different. The average energy of the outgoing photon has a peak at the theoretical energy of the state, but the distribution has a finite width called the [[Spectral linewidth|''natural linewidth'']]. Fast-decaying states have a broad linewidth, while slow-decaying states have a narrow linewidth.<ref>The broad linewidth of fast-decaying states makes it difficult to accurately measure the energy of the state, and researchers have even used detuned microwave cavities to slow down the decay rate, to get sharper peaks. {{Cite journal |last=Gabrielse |first=Gerald |author2=H. Dehmelt |title=Observation of Inhibited Spontaneous Emission |journal=Physical Review Letters |volume=55 |pages=67–70 |year=1985 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.55.67 |pmid=10031682 |issue=1 |bibcode=1985PhRvL..55...67G}}</ref> The same linewidth effect also makes it difficult to specify the [[rest mass]] of unstable, fast-decaying particles in [[particle physics]]. The faster the [[particle decay]]s (the shorter its lifetime), the less certain is its mass (the larger the particle's [[Resonance (particle physics)|width]]). |
|||
The wavelength of a localized wave cannot be determined very well. If the wave extends over a region of size L and the wavelength is approximately <math>\lambda</math>, the number of cycles in the region is approximately <math> L/\lambda </math>. The wavelength can be changed by about <math>1/L</math> without changing the number of cycles in the region by a full unit, and this is approximately the uncertainty in the wavelength. |
|||
===Time in quantum mechanics=== |
|||
:<math> \Delta \lambda = {1\over L} </math> |
|||
The concept of "time" in quantum mechanics offers many challenges.<ref name=HilgevoordConfusion/> There is no quantum theory of time measurement; relativity is both fundamental to time and difficult to include in quantum mechanics.<ref name="Busch2002"/> While position and momentum are associated with a single particle, time is a system property: it has no operator needed for the Robertson–Schrödinger relation.<ref name=Sen2014/> The mathematical treatment of stable and unstable quantum systems differ.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Bohm |first=Arno |date=January 2011 |title=Resonances/decaying states and the mathematics of quantum physics |url=https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S0034487711600189 |journal=Reports on Mathematical Physics |language=en |volume=67 |issue=3 |pages=279–303 |doi=10.1016/S0034-4877(11)60018-9 |bibcode=2011RpMP...67..279B |access-date=2024-01-24 |archive-date=2023-12-04 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231204062259/https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S0034487711600189 |url-status=live }}</ref> These factors combine to make energy–time uncertainty principles controversial. |
|||
Three notions of "time" can be distinguished:<ref name="Busch2002"/> external, intrinsic, and observable. External or laboratory time is seen by the experimenter; intrinsic time is inferred by changes in dynamic variables, like the hands of a clock or the motion of a free particle; observable time concerns time as an observable, the measurement of time-separated events. |
|||
This is an exact counterpart to a well known result in [[signal processing]] --- the shorter a pulse in time, the less well defined the frequency. The width of a pulse in frequency space is inversely proportional to the width in time. It is a fundamental result in [[Fourier analysis]], the narrower the peak of a function, the broader the Fourier transform. |
|||
An external-time energy–time uncertainty principle might say that measuring the energy of a quantum system to an accuracy <math>\Delta E</math> requires a time interval <math>\Delta t > h/\Delta E</math>.<ref name=Hilgevoord>{{Cite journal |last=Hilgevoord |first=Jan |date=1996-12-01 |title=The uncertainty principle for energy and time |url=https://pubs.aip.org/ajp/article/64/12/1451/1054748/The-uncertainty-principle-for-energy-and-time |journal=American Journal of Physics |language=en |volume=64 |issue=12 |pages=1451–1456 |doi=10.1119/1.18410 |bibcode=1996AmJPh..64.1451H |issn=0002-9505 |access-date=2023-11-12 |archive-date=2024-02-23 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240223155750/https://pubs.aip.org/aapt/ajp/article-abstract/64/12/1451/1054748/The-uncertainty-principle-for-energy-and-time?redirectedFrom=fulltext |url-status=live }}</ref> However, [[Yakir Aharonov]] and [[David Bohm]]<ref>{{Cite journal |url=http://148.216.10.84/archivoshistoricosMQ/ModernaHist/Aharonov%20a.pdf |title=Time in the Quantum Theory and the Uncertainty Relation for Time and Energy |journal=Physical Review |volume=122 |issue=5 |date=June 1, 1961 |first1=Y. |last1=Aharonov |first2=D. |last2=Bohm |pages=1649–1658 |doi=10.1103/PhysRev.122.1649 |bibcode=1961PhRv..122.1649A |access-date=2012-01-21 |archive-date=2014-01-09 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140109081758/http://148.216.10.84/archivoshistoricosMQ/ModernaHist/Aharonov%20a.pdf |url-status=dead }}</ref><ref name="Busch2002"/> have shown that, in some quantum systems, energy can be measured accurately within an arbitrarily short time: external-time uncertainty principles are not universal. |
|||
multiplying by <math>h</math>, and identifying <math>\Delta P = h \Delta \lambda</math>, and identifying <math>\Delta X = L</math>. |
|||
Intrinsic time is the basis for several formulations of energy–time uncertainty relations, including the Mandelstam–Tamm relation discussed in the next section. A physical system with an intrinsic time closely matching the external laboratory time is called a "clock".<ref name=HilgevoordConfusion>{{Cite journal |last=Hilgevoord |first=Jan |date=March 2005 |title=Time in quantum mechanics: a story of confusion |url=https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S1355219804000760 |journal=Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics |language=en |volume=36 |issue=1 |pages=29–60 |doi=10.1016/j.shpsb.2004.10.002 |bibcode=2005SHPMP..36...29H |access-date=2024-01-28 |archive-date=2022-10-23 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221023233903/https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S1355219804000760 |url-status=live }}</ref>{{rp|31}} |
|||
:<math> \Delta P \Delta X \gtrapprox h </math> |
|||
Observable time, measuring time between two events, remains a challenge for quantum theories; some progress has been made using [[POVM| positive operator-valued measure]] concepts.<ref name="Busch2002"/> |
|||
The uncertainty Principle can be seen as a theorem in [[Fourier analysis]]: the standard deviation of the squared absolute value of a function, times the standard deviation of the squared absolute value of its Fourier transform, is at least 1/(16π²) (Folland and Sitaram, Theorem 1.1). |
|||
===Mandelstam–Tamm=== |
|||
An instructive example is the (unnormalized) gaussian wave-function |
|||
In 1945, [[Leonid Mandelstam]] and [[Igor Tamm]] derived a non-relativistic ''time–energy uncertainty relation'' as follows.<ref>L. I. Mandelstam, I. E. Tamm, [http://daarb.narod.ru/mandtamm/index-eng.html ''The uncertainty relation between energy and time in nonrelativistic quantum mechanics''] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190607131054/http://daarb.narod.ru/mandtamm/index-eng.html |date=2019-06-07 }}, 1945.</ref><ref name="Busch2002"/> From Heisenberg mechanics, the generalized [[Ehrenfest theorem]] for an observable ''B'' without explicit time dependence, represented by a self-adjoint operator <math>\hat B</math> relates time dependence of the average value of <math>\hat B</math> to the average of its commutator with the Hamiltonian: |
|||
<math display=block> \frac{d\langle \hat{B} \rangle}{dt} = \frac{i}{\hbar}\langle [\hat{H},\hat{B}]\rangle. </math> |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\langle x | \psi \rangle = \psi(x) = e^{- {Ax^2 \over 2}}. |
|||
</math> |
|||
The value of <math>\langle [\hat{H},\hat{B}]\rangle</math> is then substituted in the [[#Robertson–Schrödinger_uncertainty_relations|Robertson uncertainty relation]] for the energy operator <math>\hat H</math> and <math>\hat B</math>: |
|||
The expectation value of X is zero by symmetry, and so the variance is found by averaging <math>X^2</math> over all positions with the weight <math>\psi(x)^2</math>, careful to divide by the normalization factor. |
|||
<math display=block> \sigma_H\sigma_B \geq \left|\frac{1}{2i} \langle[ \hat{H}, \hat{B}] \rangle\right|, </math> |
|||
giving |
|||
<math display="block"> \sigma_H \frac{\sigma_B}{\left| \frac{d\langle \hat B \rangle}{dt}\right |} \ge \frac{\hbar}{2}</math> |
|||
(whenever the denominator is nonzero). |
|||
While this is a universal result, it depends upon the observable chosen and that the deviations <math>\sigma_H</math> and <math>\sigma_B</math> are computed for a particular state. |
|||
Identifying <math>\Delta E \equiv \sigma_E </math> and the characteristic time |
|||
<math display="block">\tau_B \equiv \frac{\sigma_B}{\left| \frac{d\langle \hat B \rangle}{dt}\right |}</math> |
|||
gives an energy–time relationship <math>\Delta E \tau_B \ge \frac{\hbar}{2}.</math> |
|||
Although <math>\tau_B</math> has the dimension of time, it is different from the time parameter ''t'' that enters the [[Schrödinger equation]]. This <math>\tau_B</math> can be interpreted as time for which the expectation value of the observable, <math>\langle \hat B \rangle,</math> changes by an amount equal to one standard deviation.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Naber |first=Gregory L. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kARGEAAAQBAJ |title=Quantum Mechanics: An Introduction to the Physical Background and Mathematical Structure |year=2021 |publisher=Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG |isbn=978-3-11-075194-9 |pages=230 |language=en |access-date=2024-01-20 |archive-date=2024-02-23 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240223155539/https://books.google.com/books?id=kARGEAAAQBAJ |url-status=live }}</ref> |
|||
Examples: |
|||
* The time a free quantum particle passes a point in space is more uncertain as the energy of the state is more precisely controlled: <math>\Delta T = \hbar/2\Delta E.</math> Since the time spread is related to the particle position spread and the energy spread is related to the momentum spread, this relation is directly related to position–momentum uncertainty.<ref name="GriffithsSchroeter2018" />{{rp|144}} |
|||
* A [[Delta particle]], a quasistable composite of quarks related to protons and neutrons, has a lifetime of 10<sup>−23</sup> s, so its measured [[Mass–energy equivalence| mass equivalent to energy]], 1232 MeV/''c''<sup>2</sup>, varies by ±120 MeV/''c''<sup>2</sup>; this variation is intrinsic and not caused by measurement errors.<ref name="GriffithsSchroeter2018" />{{rp|144}} |
|||
* Two energy states <math>\psi_{1,2}</math> with energies <math>E_{1,2},</math> superimposed to create a composite state |
|||
:<math display="block">\Psi(x,t) = a\psi_1(x) e^{-iE_1t/h} + b\psi_2(x) e^{-iE_2t/h}.</math> |
|||
:The probability amplitude of this state has a time-dependent interference term: |
|||
:<math display="block">|\Psi(x,t)|^2 = a^2|\psi_1(x)|^2 + b^2|\psi_2(x)|^2 + 2ab\cos(\frac{E_2 - E_1}{\hbar}t).</math> |
|||
:The oscillation period varies inversely with the energy difference: <math>\tau = 2\pi\hbar/(E_2 - E_1)</math>.<ref name="GriffithsSchroeter2018" />{{rp|144}} |
|||
Each example has a different meaning for the time uncertainty, according to the observable and state used. |
|||
===Quantum field theory=== |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\langle X^2 \rangle = {\int_{-\infty}^\infty e^ {- A x^2} x^2 dx \over \int_{-\infty}^\infty e^{- Ax^2} dx } = - {d\over dA} \log ( \int_{-\infty}^\infty e^{- A x^2} dx ) = - {d\over dA} \log(\sqrt{\pi\over A} ) = {1 \over 2A} |
|||
</math> |
|||
Some formulations of [[quantum field theory]] uses temporary electron–positron pairs in its calculations called [[virtual particles]]. The mass-energy and lifetime of these particles are related by the energy–time uncertainty relation. The energy of a quantum systems is not known with enough precision to limit their behavior to a single, simple history. Thus the influence of ''all histories'' must be incorporated into quantum calculations, including those with much greater or much less energy than the mean of the measured/calculated energy distribution. |
|||
The fourier transform of the gaussian is the wavefunction in k-space, where k is the wavenumber and is related to the momentum by DeBroglie's relation <math>\scriptstyle p=\hbar k</math>: |
|||
The energy–time uncertainty principle does not temporarily violate [[conservation of energy]]; it does not imply that energy can be "borrowed" from the universe as long as it is "returned" within a short amount of time.<ref name="GriffithsSchroeter2018" />{{rp|145}} The energy of the universe is not an exactly known parameter at all times.<ref name=Sen2014/> When events transpire at very short time intervals, there is uncertainty in the energy of these events. |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\langle k | \psi \rangle = \psi(k) = \int_{-\infty}^{\infty} e^{- {Ax^2\over 2} + i p x} = \int_{-\infty}^{\infty} e^{ - {A\over 2}(x - ip/A)^2 - {p^2\over 2A} } = e^{-{p^2\over 2A}} \int_{-\infty}^{\infty} e^{- {A\over 2}(x- ip/A)^2} |
|||
</math> |
|||
==Harmonic analysis== |
|||
The last integral does not depend on p, because there is a continuous change of variables <math>x\rightarrow x-ip/A </math> which removes the dependence, and this deformation of the integration path in the complex plane does not pass any singularities. So up to normalization, the answer is again a Gaussian. |
|||
{{Main article|Fourier transform#Uncertainty principle}} |
|||
In the context of [[harmonic analysis]] the uncertainty principle implies that one cannot at the same time localize the value of a function and its Fourier transform. To wit, the following inequality holds, |
|||
<math display="block">\left(\int_{-\infty}^\infty x^2 |f(x)|^2\,dx\right)\left(\int_{-\infty}^\infty \xi^2 |\hat{f}(\xi)|^2\,d\xi\right)\ge \frac{\|f\|_2^4}{16\pi^2}.</math> |
|||
Further mathematical uncertainty inequalities, including the above [[entropic uncertainty]], hold between a function {{mvar|f}} and its Fourier transform {{math| ƒ̂}}:<ref>{{Citation|first1=V.|last1=Havin|first2= B.|last2=Jöricke|title=The Uncertainty Principle in Harmonic Analysis|publisher=Springer-Verlag|year=1994}}</ref><ref>{{Citation | last1 = Folland | first1 = Gerald | last2 = Sitaram |first2 = Alladi | title = The Uncertainty Principle: A Mathematical Survey | journal = Journal of Fourier Analysis and Applications | date = May 1997 | volume = 3 | issue = 3 | pages = 207–238 | doi = 10.1007/BF02649110 | bibcode = 1997JFAA....3..207F | mr=1448337 | s2cid = 121355943 }}</ref><ref>{{springer|title=Uncertainty principle, mathematical|id=U/u130020|first=A|last=Sitaram|year=2001}}</ref> |
|||
:<math> |
|||
<math display="block">H_x+H_\xi \ge \log(e/2)</math> |
|||
\langle k | \psi \rangle = e^{- p^2 \over 2A} |
|||
:</math> |
|||
===Signal processing {{anchor|Gabor limit}}=== |
|||
The width of the distribution in k is found in the same way as before, and the answer just flips A to 1/A. |
|||
In the context of [[time–frequency analysis]] uncertainty principles are referred to as the '''Gabor limit''', after [[Dennis Gabor]], or sometimes the ''Heisenberg–Gabor limit''. The basic result, which follows from "Benedicks's theorem", below, is that a function cannot be both [[time limited]] and [[band limited]] (a function and its Fourier transform cannot both have bounded domain)—see [[Bandlimiting#Bandlimited versus timelimited|bandlimited versus timelimited]]. More accurately, the ''time-bandwidth'' or ''duration-bandwidth'' product satisfies |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_{t} \sigma_{f} \ge \frac{1}{4\pi} \approx 0.08 \text{ cycles},</math> |
|||
where <math>\sigma_{t}</math> and <math>\sigma_{f}</math> are the standard deviations of the time and frequency energy concentrations respectively.<ref>{{cite book | last=Mallat | first=S. G. | title=A wavelet tour of signal processing: the sparse way | publisher=Elsevier/Academic Press | publication-place=Amsterdam ; Boston | date=2009 | isbn=978-0-12-374370-1|doi=10.1016/B978-0-12-374370-1.X0001-8|page=44}}</ref> The minimum is attained for a [[Gaussian function|Gaussian]]-shaped pulse ([[Gabor wavelet]]) [For the un-squared Gaussian (i.e. signal amplitude) and its un-squared Fourier transform magnitude <math>\sigma_t\sigma_f=1/2\pi</math>; squaring reduces each <math>\sigma</math> by a factor <math>\sqrt 2</math>.] Another common measure is the product of the time and frequency [[full width at half maximum]] (of the power/energy), which for the Gaussian equals <math>2 \ln 2 / \pi \approx 0.44</math> (see [[bandwidth-limited pulse]]). |
|||
Stated differently, one cannot simultaneously sharply localize a signal {{mvar|f}} in both the [[time domain]] and [[frequency domain]]. |
|||
:<math> |
|||
\Delta k^2 = {\Delta P^2 \over \hbar^2} = {A \over 2} |
|||
</math> |
|||
When applied to [[Filter (signal processing)|filters]], the result implies that one cannot simultaneously achieve a high temporal resolution and high frequency resolution at the same time; a concrete example are the [[Short-time Fourier transform#Resolution issues|resolution issues of the short-time Fourier transform]]—if one uses a wide window, one achieves good frequency resolution at the cost of temporal resolution, while a narrow window has the opposite trade-off. |
|||
so that for this example |
|||
Alternate theorems give more precise quantitative results, and, in time–frequency analysis, rather than interpreting the (1-dimensional) time and frequency domains separately, one instead interprets the limit as a lower limit on the support of a function in the (2-dimensional) time–frequency plane. In practice, the Gabor limit limits the ''simultaneous'' time–frequency resolution one can achieve without interference; it is possible to achieve higher resolution, but at the cost of different components of the signal interfering with each other. |
|||
:<math> \Delta X \Delta P = \sqrt{1\over 2A}\sqrt{\hbar^2 A\over 2} = {\hbar \over 2} </math> |
|||
As a result, in order to analyze signals where the [[Transient (acoustics)|transients]] are important, the [[Wavelet Transform|wavelet transform]] is often used instead of the Fourier. |
|||
which shows that the uncertainty relation inequality is tight. There are wavefunctions which saturate the bound. |
|||
===Discrete Fourier transform=== |
|||
== Robertson-Schrödinger relation == |
|||
Let <math>\left \{ \mathbf{ x_n } \right \} := x_0, x_1, \ldots, x_{N-1}</math> be a sequence of ''N'' complex numbers and <math>\left \{ \mathbf{X_k} \right \} := X_0, X_1, \ldots, X_{N-1},</math> be its [[Discrete Fourier transform#Uncertainty principles | discrete Fourier transform]]. |
|||
Denote by <math>\|x\|_0</math> the number of non-zero elements in the time sequence <math>x_0,x_1,\ldots,x_{N-1}</math> and by <math>\|X\|_0</math> the number of non-zero elements in the frequency sequence <math>X_0,X_1,\ldots,X_{N-1}</math>. Then, |
|||
Given any two [[Self-adjoint operator|Hermitian operators]] ''A'' and ''B'', and a system in the state ψ, there are probability distributions for the value of a [[measurement in quantum mechanics|measurement]] of ''A'' and ''B'', with standard deviations Δ<sub>ψ</sub>''A'' and Δ<sub>ψ</sub>''B''. Then |
|||
<math display="block">\|x\|_0 \cdot \|X\|_0 \ge N.</math> |
|||
:<math>\Delta_\psi A \, \Delta_\psi B \geq \sqrt{ \frac{1}{4}\left|\left\langle\left[{A},{B}\right]\right\rangle_\psi\right|^2 |
|||
+{1\over 4} \left|\left\langle\left\{ A-\langle A\rangle_\psi,B-\langle B\rangle_\psi \right\} \right\rangle_\psi \right|^2}</math> |
|||
where [''A'',''B''] = ''AB'' - ''BA'' is the [[Commutator#Ring theory|commutator]] of ''A'' and ''B'', <math>\{A,B\}</math>= ''AB''+''BA'' is the anticommutator, and <math>\langle X \rangle_\psi</math> is the expectation value. This inequality is called the [[Robertson-Schrödinger relation]], and includes the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle as a special case. The inequality with the commutator term only was developed in [[1930]] by [[Howard Percy Robertson]], and [[Erwin Schrödinger]] added the anticommutator term a little later. |
|||
This inequality is [[inequality (mathematics)#Sharp inequalities|sharp]], with equality achieved when ''x'' or ''X'' is a Dirac mass, or more generally when ''x'' is a nonzero multiple of a Dirac comb supported on a subgroup of the integers modulo ''N'' (in which case ''X'' is also a Dirac comb supported on a complementary subgroup, and vice versa). |
|||
===Other uncertainty principles=== |
|||
More generally, if ''T'' and ''W'' are subsets of the integers modulo ''N'', let <math>L_T,R_W : \ell^2(\mathbb Z/N\mathbb Z)\to\ell^2(\mathbb Z/N\mathbb Z)</math> denote the time-limiting operator and [[bandlimiting|band-limiting operator]]s, respectively. Then |
|||
The Robertson Schrödinger relation gives the uncertainty relation for any two observables that do not commute: |
|||
<math display="block">\|L_TR_W\|^2 \le \frac{|T||W|}{|G|} </math> |
|||
where the norm is the [[operator norm]] of operators on the Hilbert space <math>\ell^2(\mathbb Z/N\mathbb Z)</math> of functions on the integers modulo ''N''. This inequality has implications for [[signal reconstruction]].<ref name="Donoho">{{cite journal |last1=Donoho |first1=D.L. |last2=Stark |first2=P.B |year=1989 |title=Uncertainty principles and signal recovery |journal=SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics |volume=49 |issue=3 |pages=906–931 |doi=10.1137/0149053}}</ref> |
|||
When ''N'' is a [[prime number]], a stronger inequality holds: |
|||
*There is an uncertainty relation between the position and momentum of an object: |
|||
<math display="block">\|x\|_0 + \|X\|_0 \ge N + 1.</math> |
|||
Discovered by [[Terence Tao]], this inequality is also sharp.<ref>{{citation| |
|||
journal=Mathematical Research Letters |
|||
|volume=12 |
|||
|year=2005 |
|||
|issue=1 |
|||
|title=An uncertainty principle for cyclic groups of prime order |
|||
|pages=121–127 |
|||
|author=[[Terence Tao]] |
|||
|doi=10.4310/MRL.2005.v12.n1.a11 |
|||
|arxiv=math/0308286 |
|||
|s2cid=8548232 |
|||
}}</ref> |
|||
=== Benedicks's theorem === |
|||
*between the energy and position of a particle in a one-dimensional potential V(x): |
|||
Amrein–Berthier<ref> |
|||
{{citation |
|||
| last1 = Amrein | first1 = W.O. |
|||
| last2 = Berthier | first2 = A.M. |
|||
| year = 1977 |
|||
| title = On support properties of ''L''<sup>''p''</sup>-functions and their Fourier transforms |
|||
| journal = Journal of Functional Analysis |
|||
| volume = 24 | issue = 3 | pages = 258–267 |
|||
| doi = 10.1016/0022-1236(77)90056-8 |
|||
| postscript = . |
|||
| doi-access = free |
|||
}}</ref> and Benedicks's theorem<ref>{{citation |first=M. |last=Benedicks |author-link=Michael Benedicks |title=On Fourier transforms of functions supported on sets of finite Lebesgue measure |journal=J. Math. Anal. Appl. |volume=106 |year=1985 |issue=1 |pages=180–183 |doi=10.1016/0022-247X(85)90140-4 |doi-access=free }}</ref> intuitively says that the set of points where {{mvar|f}} is non-zero and the set of points where {{math|ƒ̂}} is non-zero cannot both be small. |
|||
Specifically, it is impossible for a function {{mvar|f}} in {{math|''L''<sup>2</sup>('''R''')}} and its Fourier transform {{math|ƒ̂}} to both be [[support of a function|supported]] on sets of finite [[Lebesgue measure]]. A more quantitative version is<ref>{{Citation|first=F.|last=Nazarov|author-link=Fedor Nazarov|title=Local estimates for exponential polynomials and their applications to inequalities of the uncertainty principle type|journal=St. Petersburg Math. J.|volume=5|year=1994|pages=663–717}}</ref><ref>{{Citation|first=Ph.|last=Jaming|title=Nazarov's uncertainty principles in higher dimension|journal= J. Approx. Theory|volume=149|year=2007|issue=1|pages=30–41|doi=10.1016/j.jat.2007.04.005|arxiv=math/0612367|s2cid=9794547}}</ref> |
|||
::<math>\Delta E \Delta x \geq {\hbar\over 2m} \left|\left\langle p_{x}\right\rangle\right| </math> |
|||
<math display="block">\|f\|_{L^2(\mathbf{R}^d)}\leq Ce^{C|S||\Sigma|} \bigl(\|f\|_{L^2(S^c)} + \| \hat{f} \|_{L^2(\Sigma^c)} \bigr) ~.</math> |
|||
One expects that the factor {{math|''Ce''<sup>''C''{{abs|''S''}}{{abs|''Σ''}}</sup>}} may be replaced by {{math|''Ce''<sup>''C''({{abs|''S''}}{{abs|''Σ''}})<sup>1/''d''</sup></sup>}}, which is only known if either {{mvar|S}} or {{mvar|Σ}} is convex. |
|||
*between angular position and angular momentum of an object with small angular uncertainty:<ref>{{cite journal |journal=New Journal of Physics|title=Uncertainty principle for angular position and angular momentum |year=2004 |volume=6 |page=103 |doi=10.1088/1367-2630/6/1/103 |url=http://www.iop.org/EJ/article/1367-2630/6/1/103/njp4_1_103.html}}</ref> |
|||
=== Hardy's uncertainty principle === |
|||
::<math>\Delta \Theta_i \Delta J_i \gtrapprox \frac{\hbar}{2} </math> |
|||
The mathematician [[G. H. Hardy]] formulated the following uncertainty principle:<ref>{{Citation|first=G.H.|last=Hardy|author-link=G. H. Hardy|title=A theorem concerning Fourier transforms|journal=Journal of the London Mathematical Society|volume=8|year=1933|issue=3|pages=227–231|doi=10.1112/jlms/s1-8.3.227}}</ref> it is not possible for {{mvar|f}} and {{math| ƒ̂}} to both be "very rapidly decreasing". Specifically, if {{mvar|f}} in <math>L^2(\mathbb{R})</math> is such that |
|||
<math display="block">|f(x)|\leq C(1+|x|)^Ne^{-a\pi x^2}</math> |
|||
and |
|||
<math display="block">|\hat{f}(\xi)|\leq C(1+|\xi|)^Ne^{-b\pi \xi^2}</math> (<math>C>0,N</math> an integer), |
|||
then, if {{math|1=''ab'' > 1, ''f'' = 0}}, while if {{math|1=''ab'' = 1}}, then there is a polynomial {{mvar|P}} of degree {{math|≤ ''N''}} such that |
|||
<math display="block">f(x)=P(x)e^{-a\pi x^2}. </math> |
|||
This was later improved as follows: if <math>f \in L^2(\mathbb{R}^d)</math> is such that |
|||
*between two orthogonal components of the [[angular momentum|total angular momentum]] operator of an object: |
|||
<math display="block">\int_{\mathbb{R}^d}\int_{\mathbb{R}^d}|f(x)||\hat{f}(\xi)|\frac{e^{\pi|\langle x,\xi\rangle|}}{(1+|x|+|\xi|)^N} \, dx \, d\xi < +\infty ~,</math> |
|||
then |
|||
<math display="block">f(x)=P(x)e^{-\pi\langle Ax,x\rangle} ~,</math> |
|||
where {{mvar|P}} is a polynomial of degree {{math|(''N'' − ''d'')/2}} and {{mvar|A}} is a real {{math|''d'' × ''d''}} positive definite matrix. |
|||
This result was stated in Beurling's complete works without proof and proved in Hörmander<ref>{{Citation | first=L. | last=Hörmander | author-link=Lars Hörmander|title=A uniqueness theorem of Beurling for Fourier transform pairs|journal= Ark. Mat. | volume=29|issue=1–2|year=1991|pages=231–240|bibcode=1991ArM....29..237H|doi=10.1007/BF02384339|s2cid=121375111 | doi-access=free}}</ref> (the case <math>d=1,N=0</math>) and Bonami, Demange, and Jaming<ref>{{Citation | first1=A. | last1=Bonami | author1-link= Aline Bonami |first2=B.|last2=Demange|first3=Ph.|last3=Jaming|title=Hermite functions and uncertainty principles for the Fourier and the windowed Fourier transforms |journal= Rev. Mat. Iberoamericana | volume=19 | year=2003 | pages=23–55 | bibcode=2001math......2111B|arxiv=math/0102111| doi=10.4171/RMI/337|s2cid=1211391}}</ref> for the general case. Note that Hörmander–Beurling's version implies the case {{math|''ab'' > 1}} in Hardy's Theorem while the version by Bonami–Demange–Jaming covers the full strength of Hardy's Theorem. A different proof of Beurling's theorem based on Liouville's theorem appeared in ref.<ref>{{Citation|first=Haakan|last=Hedenmalm|title=Heisenberg's uncertainty principle in the sense of Beurling|journal=[[Journal d'Analyse Mathématique]] | volume=118 | issue=2 | year=2012 | pages=691–702 | doi=10.1007/s11854-012-0048-9 | doi-access=free | arxiv=1203.5222 | bibcode=2012arXiv1203.5222H | s2cid=54533890}}</ref> |
|||
:: <math> \Delta J_i \Delta J_j \geq \frac{\hbar}{2} \left|\left\langle J_k\right\rangle\right|</math> |
|||
:where ''i'', ''j'', ''k'' are distinct and ''J''<sub>''i''</sub> denotes angular momentum along the ''x''<sub>''i''</sub> axis. |
|||
A full description of the case {{math|''ab'' < 1}} as well as the following extension to Schwartz class distributions appears in ref.<ref>{{Citation|first=Bruno|last=Demange|title=Uncertainty Principles Associated to Non-degenerate Quadratic Forms|year=2009|publisher= Société Mathématique de France|isbn=978-2-85629-297-6}}</ref> |
|||
*between the number of electrons in a [[superconductor]] and the [[Phase factor|phase]] of its [[Ginzburg-Landau theory|Ginzburg-Landau order parameter]]<ref>{{cite journal|last=Likharev|first=K.K.|coauthors=A.B. Zorin|title=Theory of Bloch-Wave Oscillations in Small Josephson Junctions|journal=J. Low Temp. Phys.|volume=59|issue=3/4|pages=347-382|date=1985}}</ref><ref>{{Citation|first=P.W.|last=Anderson|editor-last=Caianiello|editor-first=E.R.|contribution=Special Effects in Superconductivity|title=Lectures on the Many-Body Problem, Vol. 2|year=1964|place=New York|publisher=Academic Press}}</ref> |
|||
{{math theorem| If a tempered distribution <math>f\in\mathcal{S}'(\R^d)</math> is such that |
|||
:: <math> \Delta N \Delta \phi \geq 1</math> |
|||
<math display="block">e^{\pi|x|^2}f\in\mathcal{S} '(\R^d)</math> |
|||
and |
|||
<math display="block">e^{\pi|\xi|^2}\hat f\in\mathcal{S}'(\R^d) ~,</math> |
|||
then |
|||
<math display="block">f(x)=P(x)e^{-\pi\langle Ax,x\rangle} ~,</math> |
|||
for some convenient polynomial {{mvar|P}} and real positive definite matrix {{mvar|A}} of type {{math|''d'' × ''d''}}.}} |
|||
== |
==Additional uncertainty relations== |
||
===Heisenberg limit=== |
|||
One well-known uncertainty relation is not an obvious consequence of the Robertson-Schrödinger relation: the energy-time uncertainty principle. |
|||
In [[quantum metrology]], and especially [[interferometry]], the '''Heisenberg limit''' is the optimal rate at which the accuracy of a measurement can scale with the energy used in the measurement. Typically, this is the measurement of a phase (applied to one arm of a [[beam-splitter]]) and the energy is given by the number of photons used in an [[interferometer]]. Although some claim to have broken the Heisenberg limit, this reflects disagreement on the definition of the scaling resource.<ref>{{Cite journal | last1 = Giovannetti | first1 = V. | last2 = Lloyd | first2 = S. | last3 = Maccone | first3 = L. | doi = 10.1038/nphoton.2011.35 | title = Advances in quantum metrology | journal = Nature Photonics | volume = 5 | issue = 4 | pages = 222 | year = 2011 | arxiv = 1102.2318 | bibcode = 2011NaPho...5..222G | s2cid = 12591819 }}; [https://arxiv.org/abs/1102.2318 arXiv] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200806200530/https://arxiv.org/abs/1102.2318 |date=2020-08-06 }}</ref> Suitably defined, the Heisenberg limit is a consequence of the basic principles of quantum mechanics and cannot be beaten, although the weak Heisenberg limit can be beaten.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Luis|first=Alfredo|date=2017-03-13|title=Breaking the weak Heisenberg limit | journal=Physical Review A | language=en|volume=95|issue=3 | pages=032113 | doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.95.032113 | arxiv=1607.07668 | bibcode=2017PhRvA..95c2113L | s2cid=55838380|issn=2469-9926}}</ref> |
|||
===Systematic and statistical errors=== |
|||
Since energy bears the same relation to time as momentum does to space in [[special relativity]], it was clear to many early founders, [[Niels Bohr]] among them, that the following relation holds: |
|||
The inequalities above focus on the ''statistical imprecision'' of observables as quantified by the standard deviation <math>\sigma</math>. Heisenberg's original version, however, was dealing with the ''systematic error'', a disturbance of the quantum system produced by the measuring apparatus, i.e., an observer effect. |
|||
:<math> \Delta E \Delta t \gtrapprox \hbar </math>, |
|||
If we let <math>\varepsilon_A</math> represent the error (i.e., [[accuracy|inaccuracy]]) of a measurement of an observable ''A'' and <math>\eta_B</math> the disturbance produced on a subsequent measurement of the conjugate variable ''B'' by the former measurement of ''A'', then the inequality proposed by Masanao Ozawa − encompassing both systematic and statistical errors - holds:<ref name="Ozawa2003"/> |
|||
but it was not obvious what Δt is, because the time at which the particle has a given state is not an operator belonging to the particle, it is a parameter describing the evolution of the system. As Lev Landau once joked "To violate the time-energy uncertainty relation all I have to do is measure the energy very precisely and then look at my watch!" |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation = <math> \varepsilon_A\, \eta_B + \varepsilon_A \, \sigma_B + \sigma_A \, \eta_B \,\ge\, \frac{1}{2} \, \left| \Bigl\langle \bigl[\hat{A},\hat{B}\bigr] \Bigr\rangle \right|</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, as originally described in the 1927 formulation, mentions only the first term of Ozawa inequality, regarding the ''systematic error''. Using the notation above to describe the ''error/disturbance'' effect of ''sequential measurements'' (first ''A'', then ''B''), it could be written as |
|||
Nevertheless, Einstein and Bohr understood the heuristic meaning of the principle. A state which only exists for a short time cannot have a definite energy. In order to have a definite energy, the frequency of the state needs to be accurately defined, and this requires the state to hang around for many cycles, the reciprocal of the required accuracy. |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation = <math> \varepsilon_{A} \, \eta_{B} \, \ge \, \frac{1}{2} \, \left| \Bigl\langle \bigl[\hat{A},\hat{B}\bigr] \Bigr\rangle \right|</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
The formal derivation of the Heisenberg relation is possible but far from intuitive. It was ''not'' proposed by Heisenberg, but formulated in a mathematically consistent way only in recent years.<ref>{{Cite journal | doi = 10.1103/PhysRevLett.111.160405| title = Proof of Heisenberg's Error-Disturbance Relation| journal = Physical Review Letters| volume = 111| issue = 16| year = 2013| last1 = Busch | first1 = P. | last2 = Lahti | first2 = P. | last3 = Werner | first3 = R. F. |arxiv = 1306.1565 |bibcode = 2013PhRvL.111p0405B | pmid=24182239 | page=160405| s2cid = 24507489}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal | doi = 10.1103/PhysRevA.89.012129| title = Heisenberg uncertainty for qubit measurements| journal = Physical Review A| volume = 89| issue = 1| pages = 012129| year = 2014| last1 = Busch | first1 = P. | last2 = Lahti | first2 = P. | last3 = Werner | first3 = R. F. |arxiv = 1311.0837 |bibcode = 2014PhRvA..89a2129B | s2cid = 118383022}}</ref> |
|||
Also, it must be stressed that the Heisenberg formulation is not taking into account the intrinsic statistical errors <math>\sigma_A</math> and <math>\sigma_B</math>. There is increasing experimental evidence<ref name="Rozema"/><ref>{{Cite journal| last1 = Erhart | first1 = J.| last2 = Sponar | first2 =S.| last3 = Sulyok | first3 = G. | last4 = Badurek | first4 = G. | last5 = Ozawa | first5 = M. | last6 = Hasegawa | first6 = Y.| title = Experimental demonstration of a universally valid error-disturbance uncertainty relation in spin measurements | journal = Nature Physics | volume=8 | pages=185–189 | year=2012 | doi=10.1038/nphys2194 | arxiv = 1201.1833 | bibcode = 2012NatPh...8..185E | issue=3 | s2cid = 117270618}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal| last1 = Baek | first1 = S.-Y. | last2 = Kaneda | first2 = F. | last3 = Ozawa | first3 = M. | last4 = Edamatsu | first4 = K. | title = Experimental violation and reformulation of the Heisenberg's error-disturbance uncertainty relation |journal = Scientific Reports |volume= 3 |pages= 2221 |year= 2013 |doi= 10.1038/srep02221 |bibcode = 2013NatSR...3.2221B | pmid=23860715 | pmc=3713528}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal| last1 = Ringbauer | first1 = M. | last2 = Biggerstaff | first2 = D.N. | last3 = Broome | first3 = M.A. | last4 = Fedrizzi | first4 = A. | last5 = Branciard | first5 = C. | last6 = White | first6 = A.G. | title = Experimental Joint Quantum Measurements with Minimum Uncertainty |journal = Physical Review Letters |volume= 112 | issue = 2 |pages= 020401 |year= 2014 |doi= 10.1103/PhysRevLett.112.020401 |arxiv = 1308.5688 |bibcode = 2014PhRvL.112b0401R | pmid=24483993| s2cid = 18730255 }}</ref> that the total quantum uncertainty cannot be described by the Heisenberg term alone, but requires the presence of all the three terms of the Ozawa inequality. |
|||
Using the same formalism,<ref name="Sen2014"/> it is also possible to introduce the other kind of physical situation, often confused with the previous one, namely the case of ''simultaneous measurements'' (''A'' and ''B'' at the same time): |
|||
For example, in [[Electromagnetic spectroscopy|spectroscopy]], excited states have a finite lifetime. By the time-energy uncertainty principle, they do not have a definite energy, and each time they decay the energy they release is slightly different. The average energy of the outgoing photon has a peak at the theoretical energy of the state, but the distribution has a finite width called the [[Spectral linewidth|''natural linewidth'']]. Fast-decaying states have a broad linewidth, while slow decaying states have a narrow linewidth. |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation = <math> \varepsilon_A \, \varepsilon_B \, \ge \, \frac{1}{2} \, \left| \Bigl\langle \bigl[\hat{A},\hat{B}\bigr] \Bigr\rangle \right|</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
The two simultaneous measurements on ''A'' and ''B'' are necessarily<ref>{{Cite journal | last1 = Björk | first1 = G. | last2 = Söderholm | first2 = J. | last3 = Trifonov | first3 = A. | last4 = Tsegaye | first4 = T. | last5 = Karlsson | first5 = A. | |
|||
title = Complementarity and the uncertainty relations | doi = 10.1103/PhysRevA.60.1874 | journal = Physical Review | volume = A60 | issue = 3 | year = 1999| page = 1878 |arxiv = quant-ph/9904069 |bibcode = 1999PhRvA..60.1874B | s2cid = 27371899 }}</ref> ''unsharp'' or [[weak measurement|''weak'']]. |
|||
It is also possible to derive an uncertainty relation that, as the Ozawa's one, combines both the statistical and systematic error components, but keeps a form very close to the Heisenberg original inequality. By adding Robertson<ref name="Sen2014"/> |
|||
The broad linewidth of fast decaying states makes it difficult to accurately measure the energy of the state, and researchers have even used microwave cavities to slow down the decay-rate, to get sharper peaks <ref>{{cite journal|last=Gabrielse|first =Gerald|coauthors=H. Dehmelt|title=Observation of Inhibited Spontaneous Emission|journal=Physical Review Letters|volume=55|pages=67-70|date=1985}}</ref>. The same linewidth effect also makes it difficult to measure the [[rest mass]] of fast decaying particles in [[particle physics]]. The faster the particle decays, the less certain is its mass. |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation = <math> \sigma_{A} \, \sigma_{B} \, \ge \, \frac{1}{2} \, \left| \Bigl\langle \bigl[\hat{A},\hat{B} \bigr] \Bigr\rangle \right|</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
and Ozawa relations we obtain |
|||
<math display="block">\varepsilon_A \eta_B + \varepsilon_A \, \sigma_B + \sigma_A \, \eta_B + \sigma_A \sigma_B \geq \left|\Bigl\langle \bigl[\hat{A},\hat{B}\bigr] \Bigr\rangle \right| .</math> |
|||
The four terms can be written as: |
|||
<math display="block">(\varepsilon_A + \sigma_A) \, (\eta_B + \sigma_B) \, \geq \, \left|\Bigl\langle\bigl[\hat{A},\hat{B} \bigr] \Bigr\rangle \right| .</math> |
|||
Defining: |
|||
<math display="block">\bar \varepsilon_A \, \equiv \, (\varepsilon_A + \sigma_A)</math> |
|||
as the ''inaccuracy'' in the measured values of the variable ''A'' and |
|||
<math display="block">\bar \eta_B \, \equiv \, (\eta_B + \sigma_B)</math> |
|||
as the ''resulting fluctuation'' in the conjugate variable ''B'', Kazuo Fujikawa<ref>{{Cite journal|last = Fujikawa|first = Kazuo|title = Universally valid Heisenberg uncertainty relation|journal = Physical Review A|volume=85|year=2012|doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.85.062117|arxiv = 1205.1360 |bibcode = 2012PhRvA..85f2117F|issue=6 |pages = 062117|s2cid = 119640759}}</ref> established an uncertainty relation similar to the Heisenberg original one, but valid both for ''systematic and statistical errors'': |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation = <math> \bar \varepsilon_A \, \bar \eta_B \, \ge \, \left| \Bigl\langle \bigl[\hat{A},\hat{B}\bigr] \Bigr\rangle \right|</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
===Quantum entropic uncertainty principle=== |
|||
One ''false'' formulation of the energy-time uncertainty principle says that measuring the energy of a quantum system to an accuracy <math>\Delta E</math> requires a time interval <math>\Delta t > h/\Delta E</math>. This formulation is similar to the one alluded to in Landau's joke, and was explicitly invalidated by [[Yakir Aharonov|Y. Aharonov]] and [[David Bohm|D. Bohm]] in 1961. The time <math>\Delta t</math> in the uncertainty relation is the time during which the system exists unperturbed, not the time during which the experimental equipment is turned on. |
|||
For many distributions, the standard deviation is not a particularly natural way of quantifying the structure. For example, uncertainty relations in which one of the observables is an angle has little physical meaning for fluctuations larger than one period.<ref name="CarruthersNieto" /><ref>{{Citation |first=D. |last=Judge |title=On the uncertainty relation for angle variables | journal=Il Nuovo Cimento |year=1964|volume=31|issue=2|pages=332–340|doi=10.1007/BF02733639 | bibcode=1964NCim...31..332J | s2cid=120553526 }}</ref><ref>{{Citation |first1= M. |last1= Bouten |first2= N. |last2= Maene | first3= P. | last3= Van Leuven | title=On an uncertainty relation for angle variables | journal=Il Nuovo Cimento | year=1965 | volume=37 | issue=3 | pages=1119–1125 | doi=10.1007/BF02773197 | bibcode=1965NCim...37.1119B | s2cid= 122838645 }}</ref><ref>{{Citation |first=W. H. | last=Louisell | title=Amplitude and phase uncertainty relations|journal=Physics Letters | year=1963 | volume=7 | issue=1 | pages=60–61 | doi=10.1016/0031-9163(63)90442-6 | bibcode = 1963PhL.....7...60L }}</ref> Other examples include highly [[bimodal distribution]]s, or [[unimodal distribution]]s with divergent variance. |
|||
A solution that overcomes these issues is an uncertainty based on [[entropic uncertainty]] instead of the product of variances. While formulating the [[many-worlds interpretation]] of quantum mechanics in 1957, [[Hugh Everett III]] conjectured a stronger extension of the uncertainty principle based on entropic certainty.<ref>{{Citation |last1=DeWitt |first1=B. S. |last2=Graham |first2=N. |year=1973 |title=The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics |location=Princeton |publisher=[[Princeton University Press]] |pages=52–53 |isbn=0-691-08126-3 }}</ref> This conjecture, also studied by I. I. Hirschman<ref>{{Citation | first=I. I. Jr. |last=Hirschman |title=A note on entropy |journal=[[American Journal of Mathematics]] |year=1957 |volume=79 |issue=1 |pages=152–156 |doi=10.2307/2372390 |postscript=. |jstor=2372390 }}</ref> and proven in 1975 by W. Beckner<ref name="Beckner">{{Citation |first=W. |last=Beckner |title=Inequalities in Fourier analysis |journal=[[Annals of Mathematics]] |volume=102 |issue=6 |year=1975 |pages=159–182 |doi=10.2307/1970980 |postscript=. |jstor=1970980 |pmid=16592223 |pmc=432369 }}</ref> and by Iwo Bialynicki-Birula and Jerzy Mycielski<ref name="BBM">{{Citation |first1=I. |last1=Bialynicki-Birula |last2=Mycielski |first2=J. |title=Uncertainty Relations for Information Entropy in Wave Mechanics |journal=[[Communications in Mathematical Physics]] |volume=44 |year=1975 |pages=129–132 |doi=10.1007/BF01608825 |issue=2 |bibcode=1975CMaPh..44..129B |s2cid=122277352 |url=http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.cmp/1103899297 |access-date=2021-08-17 |archive-date=2021-02-08 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210208011223/https://projecteuclid.org/euclid.cmp/1103899297 |url-status=live }}</ref> is that, for two normalized, dimensionless Fourier transform pairs {{math|''f''(''a'')}} and {{math|''g''(''b'')}} where |
|||
In 1936, Dirac offered a precise definition and derivation of the time-energy uncertainty relation, in a relativistic quantum theory of "events". In this formulation, particles followed a trajectory in space time, and each particles trajectory was parametrized independently by a different proper time. The [[many-times formulation]] of quantum mechanics is mathematically equivalent to the standard formualations, but it was in a form more suited for relativistic generalization. It was the inspiration for [[Shin-Ichiro Tomonaga]]'s to covariant perturbation theory for [[quantum electrodynamics]]. |
|||
:<math>f(a) = \int_{-\infty}^\infty g(b)\ e^{2\pi i a b}\,db</math>{{spaces|3}} and {{spaces|3}} <math> \,\,\,g(b) = \int_{-\infty}^\infty f(a)\ e^{- 2\pi i a b}\,da</math> |
|||
the Shannon [[Information entropy|information entropies]] |
|||
<math display="block">H_a = -\int_{-\infty}^\infty |f(a)|^2 \log |f(a)|^2\,da,</math> |
|||
and |
|||
<math display="block">H_b = -\int_{-\infty}^\infty |g(b)|^2 \log |g(b)|^2\,db</math> |
|||
are subject to the following constraint, |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation =<math>H_a + H_b \ge \log (e/2)</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
where the logarithms may be in any base. |
|||
The probability distribution functions associated with the position wave function {{math|''ψ''(''x'')}} and the momentum wave function {{math|''φ''(''x'')}} have dimensions of inverse length and momentum respectively, but the entropies may be rendered dimensionless by |
|||
But a better-known, more widely-used formulation of the time-energy uncertainty principle [http://daarb.narod.ru/mandtamm-eng.html was given] only in 1945 by [[Leonid Mandelshtam|L. I. Mandelshtam]] and [[Igor Tamm|I. E. Tamm]], as follows. For a quantum system in a non-stationary state <math>|\psi\rangle</math> and an observable <math>B</math> represented by a self-adjoint operator <math>\hat B</math>, the following formula holds: |
|||
<math display="block">H_x = - \int |\psi(x)|^2 \ln \left(x_0 \, |\psi(x)|^2 \right) dx =-\left\langle \ln \left(x_0 \, \left|\psi(x)\right|^2 \right) \right\rangle</math> |
|||
<math display="block">H_p = - \int |\varphi(p)|^2 \ln (p_0\,|\varphi(p)|^2) \,dp =-\left\langle \ln (p_0\left|\varphi(p)\right|^2 ) \right\rangle</math> |
|||
where {{math|''x''<sub>0</sub>}} and {{math|''p''<sub>0</sub>}} are some arbitrarily chosen length and momentum respectively, which render the arguments of the logarithms dimensionless. Note that the entropies will be functions of these chosen parameters. Due to the [[Wavefunction#Relation between wave functions|Fourier transform relation]] between the position wave function {{math|''ψ''(''x'')}} and the momentum wavefunction {{math|''φ''(''p'')}}, the above constraint can be written for the corresponding entropies as |
|||
{{Equation box 1 |
|||
|indent =: |
|||
|equation = <math>H_x + H_p \ge \log \left(\frac{e\,h}{2\,x_0\,p_0}\right)</math> |
|||
|cellpadding= 6 |
|||
|border |
|||
|border colour = #0073CF |
|||
|background colour=#F5FFFA}} |
|||
where {{mvar|h}} is the [[Planck constant]]. |
|||
Depending on one's choice of the {{math|''x<sub>0</sub> p<sub>0</sub>''}} product, the expression may be written in many ways. If {{math|''x''<sub>0</sub> ''p''<sub>0</sub>}} is chosen to be {{mvar|h}}, then |
|||
:<math> \Delta_{\psi} E \frac{\Delta_{\psi} B}{\left | \frac{\mathrm{d}\langle \hat B \rangle}{\mathrm{d}t}\right |} \ge \frac{\hbar}{2} </math>, |
|||
<math display="block">H_x + H_p \ge \log \left(\frac{e}{2}\right)</math> |
|||
If, instead, {{math|''x''<sub>0</sub> ''p''<sub>0</sub>}} is chosen to be {{mvar|ħ}}, then |
|||
where <math>\Delta_{\psi} E</math> is the standard deviation of the energy operator in the state <math>|\psi\rangle </math>, <math>\Delta_{\psi} B</math> stands for the standard deviation of the operator <math>\hat B</math> and <math> \langle \hat B \rangle </math> is the expectation value of <math>\hat B</math> in that state. Although, the second factor in the left-hand side has dimension of time, it is different from the time parameter that enters [[Schrödinger equation]]. It is a lifetime of the state <math>|\psi\rangle</math> with respect to the observable <math>B</math>. In other words, this is the time after which the expectation value <math>\langle\hat B\rangle</math> changes appreciably. |
|||
<math display="block">H_x + H_p \ge \log (e\,\pi)</math> |
|||
If {{math|''x''<sub>0</sub>}} and {{math|''p''<sub>0</sub>}} are chosen to be unity in whatever system of units are being used, then |
|||
<math display="block">H_x + H_p \ge \log \left(\frac{e\,h }{2}\right)</math> |
|||
where {{mvar|h}} is interpreted as a dimensionless number equal to the value of the Planck constant in the chosen system of units. Note that these inequalities can be extended to multimode quantum states, or wavefunctions in more than one spatial dimension.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Huang |first1=Yichen |title=Entropic uncertainty relations in multidimensional position and momentum spaces | journal=Physical Review A |date=24 May 2011 |volume=83 |issue=5 |page=052124 | doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.83.052124 | bibcode=2011PhRvA..83e2124H | arxiv=1101.2944 | s2cid=119243096 }}</ref> |
|||
The quantum entropic uncertainty principle is more restrictive than the Heisenberg uncertainty principle. From the inverse [[logarithmic Sobolev inequalities]]<ref>{{citation |first=D. |last=Chafaï |chapter=Gaussian maximum of entropy and reversed log-Sobolev inequality|arxiv=math/0102227 |doi=10.1007/978-3-540-36107-7_5 |year=2003 |isbn=978-3-540-00072-3 |pages=194–200|title=Séminaire de Probabilités XXXVI |volume=1801 |series=Lecture Notes in Mathematics |s2cid=17795603 }}</ref> |
|||
<math display="block">H_x \le \frac{1}{2} \log ( 2e\pi \sigma_x^2 / x_0^2 )~,</math> |
|||
<math display="block">H_p \le \frac{1}{2} \log ( 2e\pi \sigma_p^2 /p_0^2 )~,</math> |
|||
(equivalently, from the fact that normal distributions maximize the entropy of all such with a given variance), it readily follows that this entropic uncertainty principle is ''stronger than the one based on standard deviations'', because |
|||
<math display="block">\sigma_x \sigma_p \ge \frac{\hbar}{2} \exp\left(H_x + H_p - \log \left(\frac{e\,h}{2\,x_0\,p_0}\right)\right) \ge \frac{\hbar}{2}~.</math> |
|||
In other words, the Heisenberg uncertainty principle, is a consequence of the quantum entropic uncertainty principle, but not vice versa. A few remarks on these inequalities. First, the choice of [[base e]] is a matter of popular convention in physics. The logarithm can alternatively be in any base, provided that it be consistent on both sides of the inequality. Second, recall the [[Shannon entropy]] has been used, ''not'' the quantum [[von Neumann entropy]]. Finally, the normal distribution saturates the inequality, and it is the only distribution with this property, because it is the [[maximum entropy probability distribution]] among those with fixed variance (cf. [[differential entropy#Maximization in the normal distribution|here]] for proof). |
|||
{| class="toccolours collapsible collapsed" width="70%" style="text-align:left" |
|||
!Entropic uncertainty of the normal distribution |
|||
|- |
|||
|We demonstrate this method on the ground state of the QHO, which as discussed above saturates the usual uncertainty based on standard deviations. The length scale can be set to whatever is convenient, so we assign |
|||
<math display="block">x_0 = \sqrt{\frac{\hbar}{2m\omega}}</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
\psi(x) &= \left(\frac{m \omega}{\pi \hbar}\right)^{1/4} \exp{\left( -\frac{m \omega x^2}{2\hbar}\right)} \\ |
|||
&= \left(\frac{1}{2\pi x_0^2}\right)^{1/4} \exp{\left( -\frac{x^2}{4x_0^2}\right)} |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
The probability distribution is the normal distribution |
|||
<math display="block">|\psi(x)|^2 = \frac{1}{x_0 \sqrt{2\pi}} \exp{\left( -\frac{x^2}{2x_0^2}\right)}</math> |
|||
with Shannon entropy |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
H_x &= - \int |\psi(x)|^2 \ln (|\psi(x)|^2 \cdot x_0 ) \,dx \\ |
|||
&= -\frac{1}{x_0 \sqrt{2\pi}} \int_{-\infty}^\infty \exp{\left( -\frac{x^2}{2x_0^2}\right)} \ln \left[\frac{1}{\sqrt{2\pi}} \exp{\left( -\frac{x^2}{2x_0^2}\right)}\right] \, dx \\ |
|||
&= \frac{1}{\sqrt{2\pi}} \int_{-\infty}^\infty \exp{\left( -\frac{u^2}{2}\right)} \left[\ln(\sqrt{2\pi}) + \frac{u^2}{2}\right] \, du\\ |
|||
&= \ln(\sqrt{2\pi}) + \frac{1}{2}. |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
A completely analogous calculation proceeds for the momentum distribution. Choosing a standard momentum of <math>p_0=\hbar/x_0</math>: |
|||
<math display="block">\varphi(p) = \left(\frac{2 x_0^2}{\pi \hbar^2}\right)^{1/4} \exp{\left( -\frac{x_0^2 p^2}{\hbar^2}\right)}</math> |
|||
<math display="block">|\varphi(p)|^2 = \sqrt{\frac{2 x_0^2}{\pi \hbar^2}} \exp{\left( -\frac{2x_0^2 p^2}{\hbar^2}\right)}</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
H_p &= - \int |\varphi(p)|^2 \ln (|\varphi(p)|^2 \cdot \hbar / x_0 ) \,dp \\ |
|||
&= -\sqrt{\frac{2 x_0^2}{\pi \hbar^2}} \int_{-\infty}^\infty \exp{\left( -\frac{2x_0^2 p^2}{\hbar^2}\right)} \ln \left[\sqrt{\frac{2}{\pi}} \exp{\left( -\frac{2x_0^2 p^2}{\hbar^2}\right)}\right] \, dp \\ |
|||
&= \sqrt{\frac{2}{\pi}} \int_{-\infty}^\infty \exp{\left( -2v^2\right)} \left[\ln\left(\sqrt{\frac{\pi}{2}}\right) + 2v^2 \right] \, dv \\ |
|||
&= \ln\left(\sqrt{\frac{\pi}{2}}\right) + \frac{1}{2}. |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
The entropic uncertainty is therefore the limiting value |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
H_x+H_p &= \ln(\sqrt{2\pi}) + \frac{1}{2} + \ln\left(\sqrt{\frac{\pi}{2}}\right) + \frac{1}{2}\\ |
|||
&= 1 + \ln \pi = \ln(e\pi). |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
|} |
|||
A measurement apparatus will have a finite resolution set by the discretization of its possible outputs into bins, with the probability of lying within one of the bins given by the Born rule. We will consider the most common experimental situation, in which the bins are of uniform size. Let ''δx'' be a measure of the spatial resolution. We take the zeroth bin to be centered near the origin, with possibly some small constant offset ''c''. The probability of lying within the jth interval of width ''δx'' is |
|||
<math display="block">\operatorname P[x_j]= \int_{(j-1/2)\delta x-c}^{(j+1/2)\delta x-c}| \psi(x)|^2 \, dx</math> |
|||
To account for this discretization, we can define the Shannon entropy of the wave function for a given measurement apparatus as |
|||
<math display="block">H_x=-\sum_{j=-\infty}^\infty \operatorname P[x_j] \ln \operatorname P[x_j].</math> |
|||
Under the above definition, the entropic uncertainty relation is |
|||
<math display="block">H_x + H_p > \ln\left(\frac{e}{2}\right)-\ln\left(\frac{\delta x \delta p}{h} \right).</math> |
|||
Here we note that {{math|''δx'' ''δp''/''h''}} is a typical infinitesimal phase space volume used in the calculation of a [[partition function (statistical mechanics)|partition function]]. The inequality is also strict and not saturated. Efforts to improve this bound are an active area of research. |
|||
{| class="toccolours collapsible collapsed" width="70%" style="text-align:left" |
|||
!Normal distribution example |
|||
|- |
|||
|We demonstrate this method first on the ground state of the QHO, which as discussed above saturates the usual uncertainty based on standard deviations. |
|||
<math display="block">\psi(x)=\left(\frac{m \omega}{\pi \hbar}\right)^{1/4} \exp{\left( -\frac{m \omega x^2}{2\hbar}\right)}</math> |
|||
The probability of lying within one of these bins can be expressed in terms of the [[error function]]. |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
\operatorname P[x_j] &= \sqrt{\frac{m \omega}{\pi \hbar}} \int_{(j-1/2)\delta x}^{(j+1/2)\delta x} \exp\left( -\frac{m \omega x^2}{\hbar}\right) \, dx \\ |
|||
&= \sqrt{\frac{1}{\pi}} \int_{(j-1/2)\delta x\sqrt{m \omega / \hbar}}^{(j+1/2)\delta x\sqrt{m \omega / \hbar}} e^{u^2} \, du \\ |
|||
&= \frac{1}{2} \left[ \operatorname{erf} \left( \left(j+\frac{1}{2}\right)\delta x \cdot \sqrt{\frac{m \omega}{\hbar}}\right)- \operatorname {erf} \left( \left(j-\frac{1}{2}\right)\delta x \cdot \sqrt{\frac{m \omega}{\hbar}}\right) \right] |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
The momentum probabilities are completely analogous. |
|||
<math display="block">\operatorname P[p_j] = \frac{1}{2} \left[ \operatorname{erf} \left( \left(j+\frac{1}{2}\right)\delta p \cdot \frac{1}{\sqrt{\hbar m \omega}}\right)- \operatorname{erf} \left( \left(j-\frac{1}{2}\right)\delta x \cdot \frac{1}{\sqrt{\hbar m \omega}}\right) \right]</math> |
|||
For simplicity, we will set the resolutions to |
|||
<math display="block">\delta x = \sqrt{\frac{h}{m \omega}}</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\delta p = \sqrt{h m \omega}</math> |
|||
so that the probabilities reduce to |
|||
<math display="block">\operatorname P[x_j] = \operatorname P[p_j] = \frac{1}{2} \left[ \operatorname {erf} \left( \left(j+\frac{1}{2}\right) \sqrt{2\pi} \right)- \operatorname {erf} \left( \left(j-\frac{1}{2}\right) \sqrt{2\pi} \right) \right]</math> |
|||
The Shannon entropy can be evaluated numerically. |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
H_x = H_p &= -\sum_{j=-\infty}^\infty \operatorname P[x_j] \ln \operatorname P[x_j] \\ |
|||
&= -\sum_{j=-\infty}^\infty \frac{1}{2} \left[ \operatorname {erf} \left( \left(j+\frac{1}{2}\right) \sqrt{2\pi} \right)- \operatorname {erf} \left( \left(j-\frac{1}{2}\right) \sqrt{2\pi} \right) \right] \ln \frac{1}{2} \left[ \operatorname {erf} \left( \left(j+\frac{1}{2}\right) \sqrt{2\pi} \right)- \operatorname {erf} \left( \left(j-\frac{1}{2}\right) \sqrt{2\pi} \right) \right] \\ |
|||
&\approx 0.3226 |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
The entropic uncertainty is indeed larger than the limiting value. |
|||
<math display="block">H_x + H_p \approx 0.3226 + 0.3226 = 0.6452 >\ln\left(\frac{e}{2}\right)-\ln 1 \approx 0.3069</math> |
|||
Note that despite being in the optimal case, the inequality is not saturated. |
|||
|} |
|||
{| class="toccolours collapsible collapsed" width="70%" style="text-align:left" |
|||
!Sinc function example |
|||
|- |
|||
|An example of a unimodal distribution with infinite variance is the [[sinc function]]. If the wave function is the correctly normalized uniform distribution, |
|||
<math display="block">\psi(x) = \begin{cases} |
|||
{1}/{\sqrt{2a}} & \text{for } |x| \le a, \\[8pt] |
|||
0 & \text{for } |x|>a |
|||
\end{cases}</math> |
|||
then its Fourier transform is the sinc function, |
|||
<math display="block">\varphi(p)=\sqrt{\frac{a}{\pi \hbar}} \cdot \operatorname{sinc}\left(\frac{a p}{\hbar}\right)</math> |
|||
which yields infinite momentum variance despite having a centralized shape. The entropic uncertainty, on the other hand, is finite. Suppose for simplicity that the spatial resolution is just a two-bin measurement, ''δx'' = ''a'', and that the momentum resolution is ''δp'' = ''h''/''a''. |
|||
Partitioning the uniform spatial distribution into two equal bins is straightforward. We set the offset ''c'' = 1/2 so that the two bins span the distribution. |
|||
<math display="block">\operatorname P[x_0] = \int_{-a}^0 \frac{1}{2a} \, dx = \frac{1}{2}</math> |
|||
<math display="block">\operatorname P[x_1] = \int_0^a \frac{1}{2a} \, dx = \frac{1}{2}</math> |
|||
<math display="block">H_x = -\sum_{j=0}^{1} \operatorname P[x_j] \ln \operatorname P[x_j] = -\frac{1}{2} \ln \frac{1}{2} - \frac{1}{2} \ln \frac{1}{2} = \ln 2</math> |
|||
The bins for momentum must cover the entire real line. As done with the spatial distribution, we could apply an offset. It turns out, however, that the Shannon entropy is minimized when the zeroth bin for momentum is centered at the origin. (The reader is encouraged to try adding an offset.) The probability of lying within an arbitrary momentum bin can be expressed in terms of the [[sine integral]]. |
|||
<math display="block">\begin{align} |
|||
\operatorname P[p_j] &= \frac{a}{\pi \hbar} \int_{(j-1/2)\delta p}^{(j+1/2)\delta p} \operatorname{sinc}^2\left(\frac{a p}{\hbar}\right) \, dp \\ |
|||
&= \frac{1}{\pi} \int_{2\pi (j-1/2)}^{2\pi (j+1/2)} \operatorname{sinc}^2(u) \, du \\ |
|||
&= \frac{1}{\pi} \left[ \operatorname {Si} ((4j+2)\pi)- \operatorname {Si} ((4j-2)\pi) \right] |
|||
\end{align}</math> |
|||
The Shannon entropy can be evaluated numerically. |
|||
<math display="block">H_p = -\sum_{j=-\infty}^\infty \operatorname P[p_j] \ln \operatorname P[p_j] = -\operatorname P[p_0] \ln \operatorname P[p_0]-2 \cdot \sum_{j=1}^{\infty} \operatorname P[p_j] \ln \operatorname P[p_j] \approx 0.53</math> |
|||
The entropic uncertainty is indeed larger than the limiting value. |
|||
<math display="block">H_x+H_p \approx 0.69 + 0.53 = 1.22 >\ln\left(\frac{e}{2}\right)-\ln 1 \approx 0.31</math> |
|||
|} |
|||
===Uncertainty relation with three angular momentum components=== |
|||
For a particle of [[total angular momentum]] <math>j</math> the following uncertainty relation holds |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\sigma_{J_x}^2+\sigma_{J_y}^2+\sigma_{J_z}^2\ge j, |
|||
</math> |
|||
where <math>J_l</math> are angular momentum components. The relation can be derived from |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\langle J_x^2+J_y^2+J_z^2\rangle = j(j+1), |
|||
</math> |
|||
and |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\langle J_x\rangle^2+\langle J_y\rangle^2+\langle J_z\rangle^2\le j. |
|||
</math> |
|||
The relation can be strengthened as<ref name="PhysRevResearch21" /><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Chiew |first1=Shao-Hen |last2=Gessner |first2=Manuel |title=Improving sum uncertainty relations with the quantum Fisher information |journal=Physical Review Research |date=31 January 2022 |volume=4 |issue=1 |pages=013076 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevResearch.4.013076|arxiv=2109.06900 |bibcode=2022PhRvR...4a3076C |s2cid=237513883 }}</ref> |
|||
<math display="block"> |
|||
\sigma_{J_x}^2+\sigma_{J_y}^2+F_Q[\varrho,J_z]/4\ge j, |
|||
</math> |
|||
where <math>F_Q[\varrho,J_z]</math> is the quantum Fisher information. |
|||
== History == |
|||
{{See also|History of quantum mechanics}} |
|||
In 1925 Heisenberg published the [[Umdeutung paper|''Umdeutung'' (reinterpretation) paper]] where he showed that central aspect of quantum theory was the non-[[commutativity]]: the theory implied that the relative order of position and momentum measurement was significant. Working with [[Max Born]] and [[Pascual Jordan]], he continued to develop [[matrix mechanics]], that would become the first modern quantum mechanics formulation.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Whittaker |first=Edmund T. |title=A history of the theories of aether & electricity|volume= II: The modern theories, 1900–1926 |date=1989 |publisher=Dover Publ |isbn=978-0-486-26126-3 |edition=Repr |location=New York|page=267}}</ref> |
|||
[[File:Heisenbergbohr.jpg|thumb|Werner Heisenberg and Niels Bohr]] |
|||
In March 1926, working in Bohr's institute, Heisenberg realized that the non-[[commutativity]] implies the uncertainty principle. Writing to [[Wolfgang Pauli]] in February 1927, he worked out the basic concepts.<ref>{{Cite web |title=This Month in Physics History |url=http://www.aps.org/publications/apsnews/200802/physicshistory.cfm |access-date=2023-11-04 |website=www.aps.org |language=en |archive-date=2011-01-30 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110130195156/http://aps.org/publications/apsnews/200802/physicshistory.cfm |url-status=live }}</ref> |
|||
In his celebrated 1927 paper "{{lang|de|Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik}}" ("On the Perceptual Content of Quantum Theoretical Kinematics and Mechanics"), Heisenberg established this expression as the minimum amount of unavoidable momentum disturbance caused by any position measurement,<ref name=":0" /> but he did not give a precise definition for the uncertainties Δx and Δ''p''. Instead, he gave some plausible estimates in each case separately. His paper gave an analysis in terms of a microscope that Bohr showed was incorrect; Heisenberg included an addendum to the publication. |
|||
In his 1930 Chicago lecture<ref name="Heisenberg_1930">{{Citation |first=W. |last=Heisenberg |year=1930 |title=Physikalische Prinzipien der Quantentheorie |language=de|location=Leipzig |publisher=Hirzel }} English translation ''The Physical Principles of Quantum Theory''. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1930.</ref> he refined his principle: |
|||
{{NumBlk|:|<math>\Delta x \, \Delta p\gtrsim h</math>|{{EquationRef|A1}}}} |
|||
Later work broadened the concept. Any two variables that do not commute cannot be measured simultaneously—the more precisely one is known, the less precisely the other can be known. Heisenberg wrote:<blockquote>It can be expressed in its simplest form as follows: One can never know with perfect accuracy both of those two important factors which determine the movement of one of the smallest particles—its position and its velocity. It is impossible to determine accurately ''both'' the position and the direction and speed of a particle ''at the same instant''.<ref>Heisenberg, W., ''Die Physik der Atomkerne'', Taylor & Francis, 1952, p. 30.</ref></blockquote> |
|||
[[Earle Hesse Kennard|Kennard]]<ref name="Kennard" /><ref name=Sen2014 />{{rp|204}} in 1927 first proved the modern inequality: |
|||
{{NumBlk|:|<math>\sigma_x\sigma_p\ge\frac{\hbar}{2}</math>|{{EquationRef|A2}}}} |
|||
where {{math|1=''ħ'' = {{sfrac|''h''|2''π''}}}}, and {{math|''σ<sub>x</sub>''}}, {{math|''σ<sub>p</sub>''}} are the standard deviations of position and momentum. (Heisenberg only proved relation ({{EquationNote|A2}}) for the special case of Gaussian states.<ref name="Heisenberg_1930"/>) In 1929 Robertson generalized the inequality to all observables and in 1930 Schrödinger extended the form to allow non-zero covariance of the operators; this result is referred to as Robertson-Schrödinger inequality.<ref name=Sen2014 />{{rp|204}} |
|||
=== Terminology and translation === |
|||
Throughout the main body of his original 1927 paper, written in German, Heisenberg used the word "Ungenauigkeit",<ref name=":0" /> |
|||
to describe the basic theoretical principle. Only in the endnote did he switch to the word "Unsicherheit". Later on, he always used "Unbestimmtheit". When the English-language version of Heisenberg's textbook, ''The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory'', was published in 1930, however, only the English word "uncertainty" was used, and it became the term in the English language.<ref>{{Citation |first1=David |last1=Cassidy |year=2009 |title=Beyond Uncertainty: Heisenberg, Quantum Physics, and the Bomb |location= New York |publisher=Bellevue Literary Press |page=185 |bibcode=2010PhT....63a..49C |bibcode-access=free |last2=Saperstein |first2=Alvin M. |volume=63 |issue=1 |journal=Physics Today |doi=10.1063/1.3293416 |doi-access=free |url=https://pubs.aip.org/physicstoday/article/63/1/49/413272/Beyond-Uncertainty-Heisenberg-Quantum-Physics-and |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240104193333/https://pubs.aip.org/physicstoday/article/63/1/49/413272/Beyond-Uncertainty-Heisenberg-Quantum-Physics-and |archive-date= Jan 4, 2024 }}</ref> |
|||
=== Heisenberg's microscope === |
|||
[[File:Heisenberg gamma ray microscope.svg|thumb|200px|right|Heisenberg's gamma-ray microscope for locating an electron (shown in blue). The incoming gamma ray (shown in green) is scattered by the electron up into the microscope's aperture angle ''θ''. The scattered gamma-ray is shown in red. Classical [[optics]] shows that the electron position can be resolved only up to an uncertainty Δ''x'' that depends on ''θ'' and the wavelength ''λ'' of the incoming light.]] |
|||
{{Main article|Heisenberg's microscope}} |
|||
The principle is quite counter-intuitive, so the early students of quantum theory had to be reassured that naive measurements to violate it were bound always to be unworkable. One way in which Heisenberg originally illustrated the intrinsic impossibility of violating the uncertainty principle is by using the [[observer effect (physics)|observer effect]] of an imaginary microscope as a measuring device.<ref name="Heisenberg_1930"/> |
|||
He imagines an experimenter trying to measure the position and momentum of an [[electron]] by shooting a [[photon]] at it.<ref name=GreensteinZajonc2006>{{cite book|first1=George |last1=Greenstein|first2=Arthur |last2=Zajonc|authorlink2=Arthur Zajonc|title=The Quantum Challenge: Modern Research on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics|year=2006|publisher=Jones & Bartlett Learning|isbn=978-0-7637-2470-2}}</ref>{{rp|49–50}} |
|||
* Problem 1 – If the photon has a short [[wavelength]], and therefore, a large momentum, the position can be measured accurately. But the photon scatters in a random direction, transferring a large and uncertain amount of momentum to the electron. If the photon has a long [[wavelength]] and low momentum, the collision does not disturb the electron's momentum very much, but the scattering will reveal its position only vaguely. |
|||
* Problem 2 – If a large [[aperture]] is used for the microscope, the electron's location can be well resolved (see [[Angular resolution#The_Rayleigh_criterion|Rayleigh criterion]]); but by the principle of [[conservation of momentum]], the transverse momentum of the incoming photon affects the electron's beamline momentum and hence, the new momentum of the electron resolves poorly. If a small aperture is used, the accuracy of both resolutions is the other way around. |
|||
The combination of these trade-offs implies that no matter what photon wavelength and aperture size are used, the product of the uncertainty in measured position and measured momentum is greater than or equal to a lower limit, which is (up to a small numerical factor) equal to the [[Planck constant]].<ref>{{Citation |last1=Tipler |first1=Paul A. |first2=Ralph A. |last2=Llewellyn |title=Modern Physics |volume=3 |publisher=W.H. Freeman & Co. |year=1999 |isbn=978-1572591646|lccn= 98046099 |
|||
|url-access=|url=https://archive.org/details/modernphysics0003tipl |page=3 }}</ref> Heisenberg did not care to formulate the uncertainty principle as an exact limit, and preferred to use it instead, as a heuristic quantitative statement, correct up to small numerical factors, which makes the radically new noncommutativity of quantum mechanics inevitable. |
|||
===Intrinsic quantum uncertainty=== |
|||
Historically, the uncertainty principle has been confused<ref>{{Citation|last=Furuta|first=Aya|title=One Thing Is Certain: Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle Is Not Dead|journal=Scientific American|year=2012|url=https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/heisenbergs-uncertainty-principle-is-not-dead/|access-date=2018-10-20|archive-date=2022-04-01|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220401183444/https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/heisenbergs-uncertainty-principle-is-not-dead/|url-status=live}}</ref><ref name="Ozawa2003">{{Citation | last=Ozawa | first=Masanao | title=Universally valid reformulation of the Heisenberg uncertainty principle on noise and disturbance in measurement | journal=Physical Review A | volume=67 | year=2003 | doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.67.042105|arxiv = quant-ph/0207121 |bibcode = 2003PhRvA..67d2105O | issue=4 | pages=42105 | s2cid=42012188}}</ref> with a related effect in [[physics]], called the [[observer effect (physics)|observer effect]], which notes that measurements of certain systems cannot be made without affecting the system,<ref>{{Citation |last=Wheeler |first=John Archibald |title=The 'Past' and the 'Delayed-Choice' Double-Slit Experiment |date=1978-01-01 |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/B9780124732506500066 |work=Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Theory |pages=9–48 |editor-last=Marlow |editor-first=A. R. |access-date=2023-07-19 |publisher=Academic Press |language=en |doi=10.1016/b978-0-12-473250-6.50006-6 |isbn=978-0-12-473250-6 |archive-date=2022-12-10 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221210014455/https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/B9780124732506500066 |url-status=live }}</ref><ref>{{Citation |last=Wheeler |first=John Archibald |title=Include the Observer in the Wave Function? |date=1977 |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1196-9_1 |work=Quantum Mechanics, A Half Century Later: Papers of a Colloquium on Fifty Years of Quantum Mechanics, Held at the University Louis Pasteur, Strasbourg, May 2–4, 1974 |pages=1–18 |editor-last=Lopes |editor-first=José Leite |access-date=2023-07-19 |series=Episteme |place=Dordrecht |publisher=Springer Netherlands |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-94-010-1196-9_1 |isbn=978-94-010-1196-9 |editor2-last=Paty |editor2-first=Michel |archive-date=2024-02-23 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240223170245/https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-010-1196-9_1 |url-status=live }}</ref> that is, without changing something in a system. Heisenberg used such an observer effect at the quantum level (see below) as a physical "explanation" of quantum uncertainty.<ref>Werner Heisenberg, ''The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory'', p. 20</ref> It has since become clearer, however, that the uncertainty principle is inherent in the properties of all [[wave|wave-like systems]],<ref name="Rozema">{{Cite journal | last1 = Rozema | first1 = L. A. | last2 = Darabi | first2 = A. | last3 = Mahler | first3 = D. H. | last4 = Hayat | first4 = A. | last5 = Soudagar | first5 = Y. | last6 = Steinberg | first6 = A. M. | doi = 10.1103/PhysRevLett.109.100404 |arxiv = 1208.0034v2| title = Violation of Heisenberg's Measurement–Disturbance Relationship by Weak Measurements | journal = Physical Review Letters | volume = 109 | issue = 10 | year = 2012 | pmid = 23005268|bibcode = 2012PhRvL.109j0404R | page=100404| s2cid = 37576344 }}</ref> and that it arises in quantum mechanics simply due to the [[matter wave]] nature of all quantum objects.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=De Broglie |first=Louis |date=October 1923 |title=Waves and Quanta |journal=Nature |language=en |volume=112 |issue=2815 |pages=540 |doi=10.1038/112540a0 |bibcode=1923Natur.112..540D |s2cid=186242764 |issn=1476-4687|doi-access=free }}</ref> Thus, the uncertainty principle actually states a fundamental property of quantum systems and is not a statement about the observational success of current technology.<ref name=nptel>{{YouTube|TcmGYe39XG0|Indian Institute of Technology Madras, Professor V. Balakrishnan, Lecture 1 – Introduction to Quantum Physics; Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, National Programme of Technology Enhanced Learning}}</ref> |
|||
== Critical reactions == |
== Critical reactions == |
||
{{Main article|Bohr–Einstein debates}} |
|||
[[Albert Einstein]] was not happy with the uncertainty principle, and he challenged [[Niels Bohr]] and Werner Heisenberg with many [[thought experiment]]s designed to test it. The most famous went as follows (see also [[Bohr-Einstein debates]]): |
|||
The Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics and Heisenberg's uncertainty principle were, in fact, initially seen as twin targets by detractors. According to the [[Copenhagen interpretation]] of quantum mechanics, there is no fundamental reality that the [[quantum state]] describes, just a prescription for calculating experimental results. There is no way to say what the state of a system fundamentally is, only what the result of observations might be. |
|||
Consider a box filled with light. The box has a shutter, which opens and quickly closes by a clock at a precise time, and some of the light escapes. We can set the clock so that the time that the energy escapes is known. To measure the amount of energy that leaves, Einstein proposed weighing the box just after the emission. The missing energy will [[Mass-energy equivalence|lessen the weight]] of the box. If the box is mounted on a scale, it is naively possible to adjust the parameters so that the uncertainty principle is violated. |
|||
[[Albert Einstein]] believed that randomness is a reflection of our ignorance of some fundamental property of reality, while [[Niels Bohr]] believed that the probability distributions are fundamental and irreducible, and depend on which measurements we choose to perform. [[Bohr–Einstein debates|Einstein and Bohr debated]] the uncertainty principle for many years. |
|||
Bohr spent a day considering this setup, but eventually realized that if the scale and the box are placed in a gravitational field, then the uncertainty of the position of the clock in the gravitational field will [[gravitational redshift|alter the rate]], and this introduces the right amount of uncertainty. |
|||
=== Ideal detached observer === |
|||
The Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics and Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle were seen as twin targets by detractors who believed in an underlying [[determinism]] and [[realism]]. Within the [[Copenhagen interpretation]] of quantum mechanics, there is no fundamental reality which the quantum state is describing, just a prescription for calculating experimental results. There is no way to say what the state of a system fundamentally is, only what the result of observations might be. |
|||
Wolfgang Pauli called Einstein's fundamental objection to the uncertainty principle "the ideal of the detached observer" (phrase translated from the German): |
|||
{{Blockquote|"Like the moon has a definite position," Einstein said to me last winter, "whether or not we look at the moon, the same must also hold for the atomic objects, as there is no sharp distinction possible between these and macroscopic objects. Observation cannot ''create'' an element of reality like a position, there must be something contained in the complete description of physical reality which corresponds to the ''possibility'' of observing a position, already before the observation has been actually made." I hope, that I quoted Einstein correctly; it is always difficult to quote somebody out of memory with whom one does not agree. It is precisely this kind of postulate which I call the ideal of the detached observer.|Letter from Pauli to Niels Bohr, February 15, 1955<ref>{{cite book |last1=Enz |first1=Charles Paul |last2=von Meyenn |first2=Karl |title=Writings on Physics and Philosophy by Wolfgang Pauli |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ueTd4g7pc5MC&pg=PA43 |publisher=Springer-Verlag |year=1994 |page=43 |translator=Robert Schlapp |isbn=3-540-56859-X |access-date=2018-02-10 |archive-date=2020-08-19 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200819235529/https://books.google.com/books?id=ueTd4g7pc5MC&pg=PA43 |url-status=live }}</ref>}} |
|||
While Einstein believed that randomness is a reflection of our ignorance of some fundamental property of reality, Bohr believed that the probability distributions are fundamental and irreducible, and depend on which measurements we choose to perform. There is no objective reality underneath determining the outcome. Not only is there a veil hiding the clockwork, but the clockwork is different depending on how you lift the veil. |
|||
=== Einstein's slit === |
|||
But Bohr was compelled to modify his understanding of the uncertainty principle after another thought experiment by Einstein. In 1935, Einstein, Podolski and Rosen published an analysis of widely separated [[entanglement|entangled]] particles. Measuring one particle, Einstein realized, would alter the probability distribution of the other, yet here the other particle could not possibly be disturbed. This example led Bohr to revise his understanding of the principle, concluding that the uncertainty was not caused by a direct interaction.<ref> Walter Isaacson, "Einstein", p 452.</ref>. |
|||
The first of Einstein's [[thought experiment]]s challenging the uncertainty principle went as follows: |
|||
{{quote|Consider a particle passing through a slit of width {{mvar|d}}. The slit introduces an uncertainty in momentum of approximately {{mvar|{{sfrac|h|d}}}} because the particle passes through the wall. But let us determine the momentum of the particle by measuring the recoil of the wall. In doing so, we find the momentum of the particle to arbitrary accuracy by conservation of momentum.}} |
|||
But Einstein came to much more far reaching conclusions from the same thought experiment. He felt that a complete description of reality would have to predict the results of experiments from locally changing deterministic quantities, and therefore would have to include more information than the maximum possible allowed by the uncertainty principle. |
|||
Bohr's response was that the wall is quantum mechanical as well, and that to measure the recoil to accuracy {{math|Δ''p''}}, the momentum of the wall must be known to this accuracy before the particle passes through. This introduces an uncertainty in the position of the wall and therefore the position of the slit equal to {{math|{{sfrac|''h''|Δ''p''}}}}, and if the wall's momentum is known precisely enough to measure the recoil, the slit's position is uncertain enough to disallow a position measurement. |
|||
In [[1964]] [[John Stewart Bell|John Bell]] showed that this assumption can be tested, since it implies a certain [[Bell inequality|inequality]] between the probability of different experiments. Experimental results confirm the predictions of quantum mechanics, ruling out local hidden variables. |
|||
A similar analysis with particles diffracting through multiple slits is given by [[Richard Feynman]].<ref>Feynman lectures on Physics, vol 3, 2–2</ref> |
|||
While it is possible to assume that quantum mechanical predictions are due to ''nonlocal'' hidden variables, in fact [[David Bohm]] invented such a formulation, this is not a satisfactory resolution for the vast majority of physicists. The question of whether a random outcome is predetermined by a nonlocal theory can be philosophical, and potentially intractable. If the hidden variables are not constrained, they could just be a list of random digits that are used to produce the measurement outcomes. To make it sensible, the assumption of nonlocal hidden variables is sometimes augmented by a second assumption--- that the size of the observable universe puts a limit on the computations that these variables can do. A nonlocal theory of this sort predicts that a [[quantum computer]] will encounter fundamental obstacles when it tries to factor numbers of approximately 10000 digits or more, an [[Shor's algorithm|achievable task]] in quantum mechanics <ref>[[Gerardus t'Hooft]] has at times advocated this point of view.</ref>. |
|||
=== Einstein's box === |
|||
==Popular culture== |
|||
Bohr was present when Einstein proposed the thought experiment which has become known as [[Einstein's box]]. Einstein argued that "Heisenberg's uncertainty equation implied that the uncertainty in time was related to the uncertainty in energy, the product of the two being related to the Planck constant."<ref name="Gamow">Gamow, G., ''The great physicists from Galileo to Einstein'', Courier Dover, 1988, p.260.</ref> Consider, he said, an ideal box, lined with mirrors so that it can contain light indefinitely. The box could be weighed before a clockwork mechanism opened an ideal shutter at a chosen instant to allow one single photon to escape. "We now know, explained Einstein, precisely the time at which the photon left the box."<ref>Kumar, M., ''Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the Great Debate About the Nature of Reality'', Icon, 2009, p. 282.</ref> "Now, weigh the box again. The change of mass tells the energy of the emitted light. In this manner, said Einstein, one could measure the energy emitted and the time it was released with any desired precision, in contradiction to the uncertainty principle."<ref name="Gamow" /> |
|||
Bohr spent a sleepless night considering this argument, and eventually realized that it was flawed. He pointed out that if the box were to be weighed, say by a spring and a pointer on a scale, "since the box must move vertically with a change in its weight, there will be uncertainty in its vertical velocity and therefore an uncertainty in its height above the table. ... Furthermore, the uncertainty about the elevation above the Earth's surface will result in an uncertainty in the rate of the clock",<ref>Gamow, G., ''The great physicists from Galileo to Einstein'', Courier Dover, 1988, pp. 260–261. {{ISBN?}}</ref> because of Einstein's own theory of [[Gravitational time dilation|gravity's effect on time]]. "Through this chain of uncertainties, Bohr showed that Einstein's light box experiment could not simultaneously measure exactly both the energy of the photon and the time of its escape."<ref>{{cite book |last=Kumar |first=M. |title=Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the Great Debate About the Nature of Reality |publisher=Icon |year=2009 |page=287}}</ref> |
|||
The uncertainty principle appears in popular culture in many places, although it is sometimes stated imprecisely, or as a stand-in for the [[observer effect]]: |
|||
=== EPR paradox for entangled particles === |
|||
*In the [[Coen Brothers]] film ''[[The Man Who Wasn't There]]'', lawyer Freddy Riedenschneider ([[Tony Shalhoub]]) uses the Uncertainty Principle as a defense for his client. Riedenschneider can't remember Heisenberg's name, calling him "Fritz something-or-other. Or is it. Maybe it's Werner." |
|||
{{Main|Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox}} |
|||
*In the ''[[The Luck of the Fryrish]]'' episode of the animated sci-fi sitcom ''[[Futurama]]'' the Professor loses at the horse track when his horse is narrowly beat out in a "quantum finish". He complains, "No fair! You changed the outcome by measuring it!" (this may refer instead to wavefunction collapse). |
|||
In 1935, Einstein, [[Boris Podolsky]] and [[Nathan Rosen]] published an analysis of spatially separated [[Quantum entanglement|entangled]] particles (EPR paradox).<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Einstein |first1=A. |last2=Podolsky |first2=B. |last3=Rosen |first3=N. |date=1935-05-15 |title=Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete? |journal=Physical Review |volume=47 |issue=10 |pages=777–780 |doi=10.1103/PhysRev.47.777|bibcode=1935PhRv...47..777E |doi-access=free }}</ref> According to EPR, one could measure the position of one of the entangled particles and the momentum of the second particle, and from those measurements deduce the position and momentum of both particles to any precision, violating the uncertainty principle. In order to avoid such possibility, the measurement of one particle must modify the probability distribution of the other particle instantaneously, possibly violating the [[principle of locality]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Kumar |first=Manjit |title=Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the great debate about the nature of reality |date=2011 |publisher=Norton |isbn=978-0-393-33988-8 |edition=1st paperback |location=New York}}</ref> |
|||
*In the science fiction television series ''[[Star Trek: The Next Generation]]'', the fictional transporters used to "beam" characters to different locations overcame the sampling limitations due to the Uncertainty Principle with the use of "[[Heisenberg compensator]]s." When asked, "How do the Heisenberg compensators work?" by [[Time magazine]] on 28 November 1994, [[Michael Okuda]], technical advisor on Star Trek, famously responded, "They work just fine, thank you."<ref>{{cite news|url=http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,981892,00.html|title=Reconfigure the Modulators!|date=November 28, 1994|publisher=Time Magazine}}</ref> |
|||
*In the well known joke: "Heisenberg is pulled over by a policeman whilst driving down a motorway, the policeman gets out of his car, walks towards Heisenberg's window and motions with his hand for Heisenberg to wind the window down, which he does. The policeman then says ‘Do you know what speed you were driving at sir?’, to which the genius responds ‘No, but I knew exactly where I was.’" |
|||
*In the 1997 film ''[[The Lost World: Jurassic Park]]'', chaostician Ian Malcolm claims that the effort "to observe and document, not interact" with the dinosaurs is a scientific impossibility because of "the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle, whatever you study, you also change." This conflates the uncertainty principle with the observer effect. |
|||
*The [[Michael Frayn]] play ''[[Copenhagen (play)|Copenhagen]]'' (1998) highlights some of the processes that went into the formation of the Uncertainty Principle. The play dramatizes the meetings between Werner Heisenberg and Niels Bohr. It highlights, as well, the discussion of the work that both did on nuclear bombs - Heisenberg for Germany and Bohr for the United States and allied forces. |
|||
*In an episode of the television show ''[[Aqua Teen Hunger Force]]'', [[Meatwad]] (who was temporarily made into a genius) tries to incorrectly explain Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle to [[Frylock]] to explain his new found intelligence. "Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle tells us that at a specific curvature of space, knowledge can be transferred into energy, or — and this is key now — matter." |
|||
*In an episode of ''[[Stargate SG-1]]'', Samantha Carter explains, using the Uncertainty Principle, that the future is not [[Determinism|predetermined]], that one can only calculate possibilities. |
|||
*Horror novelist [[Dennis Etchison]] makes mention of the Heisenberg principle in a handful of his stories and books. |
|||
*On the television show "[[CSI: Crime Scene Investigation]]" in the episode [[Living Doll (CSI episode)|Living Doll]], [[Gil Grissom]] says that he lives "by the uncertainty principle. The mere act of observing a phenomenon changes its nature." again conflating it with the observer effect. |
|||
*In Episode 16 (No Need for Hiding) of the English-dubbed version of the Japanese anime ''[[Tenchi Universe]]'', [[Washu]] gives a rapid explanation of the Uncertainty Principle while singing [[karaoke]]. |
|||
* In ''A Sound of Thunder'' (2005) A space travel technician says that the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle states that nothing is ever 100% certain. |
|||
*The French electronic music group [[Télépopmusik]] recorded a song called "dp.dq>=h/4pi" for their album [[Genetic World]] (2001). |
|||
*In the webcomic [[Questionable Content]], Pintsize tries to explain his lateness using relativity and the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle. |
|||
*In an episode of the West wing, season 5 episode 18 "Access" aired 3-31-2004, a documentary reporter asks the character CJ Craig if she is, "..familiar with the Heisenberg principle?" |
|||
*In the television show "[[Numb3rs]]" in the episode Uncertainty Principle, Charlie uses Uncertainy Principle to help predict a team of bank robbers actions. |
|||
In 1964, [[John Stewart Bell]] showed that this assumption can be falsified, since it would imply a certain [[Bell's theorem|inequality]] between the probabilities of different experiments. [[Bell test|Experimental results]] confirm the predictions of quantum mechanics, ruling out EPR's basic assumption of [[Local hidden-variable theory|local hidden variables]]. |
|||
==See also== |
|||
*[[Quantum indeterminacy]] |
|||
*[[Introduction to quantum mechanics]] |
|||
*[[Correspondence principle]] |
|||
=== Popper's criticism === |
|||
==Notes== |
|||
{{Main article|Popper's experiment}} |
|||
{{reflist}} |
|||
Science philosopher [[Karl Popper]] approached the problem of indeterminacy as a logician and [[Philosophical realism|metaphysical realist]].<ref name="Popper1959">{{cite book | last1 = Popper | first1 = Karl | author-link1 = Karl Popper | title = The Logic of Scientific Discovery | publisher = Hutchinson & Co. | year = 1959| title-link = The Logic of Scientific Discovery }}</ref> He disagreed with the application of the uncertainty relations to individual particles rather than to [[Quantum ensemble|ensembles]] of identically prepared particles, referring to them as "statistical scatter relations".<ref name="Popper1959" /><ref name="Jarvie2006">{{cite book | last1 = Jarvie | first1 = Ian Charles | last2 = Milford | first2 = Karl | last3 = Miller | first3 = David W. | title = Karl Popper: a centenary assessment | volume = 3 | publisher = Ashgate | year = 2006 | isbn = 978-0-7546-5712-5}}</ref> In this statistical interpretation, a ''particular'' measurement may be made to arbitrary precision without invalidating the quantum theory. |
|||
In 1934, Popper published {{lang|de|italic=no|Zur Kritik der Ungenauigkeitsrelationen}} ("Critique of the Uncertainty Relations") in {{lang|de|[[Naturwissenschaften]]}},<ref name="Popper1934">{{cite journal | title = Zur Kritik der Ungenauigkeitsrelationen |language=de |trans-title=Critique of the Uncertainty Relations | journal = Naturwissenschaften | year = 1934 | first = Karl | last = Popper | author2 = Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker | volume = 22 | issue = 48 | pages = 807–808 | doi=10.1007/BF01496543|bibcode = 1934NW.....22..807P | s2cid = 40843068}}</ref> and in the same year {{lang|de|[[The Logic of Scientific Discovery|Logik der Forschung]]}} (translated and updated by the author as ''The Logic of Scientific Discovery'' in 1959<ref name="Popper1959" />), outlining his arguments for the statistical interpretation. In 1982, he further developed his theory in ''Quantum theory and the schism in Physics'', writing: |
|||
==References== |
|||
*W. Heisenberg, "Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik", ''Zeitschrift für Physik'', '''43''' 1927, pp. 172-198. English translation: J. A. Wheeler and H. Zurek, ''Quantum Theory and Measurement'' Princeton Univ. Press, 1983, pp. 62-84. |
|||
*[[Leonid Mandelshtam|L. I. Mandelshtam]], [[Igor Tamm|I. E. Tamm]] "[http://daarb.narod.ru/mandtamm-eng.html The uncertainty relation between energy and time in nonrelativistic quantum mechanics]", Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR (ser. fiz.) '''9''', 122-128 (1945). English translation: J. Phys. (USSR) '''9''', 249-254 (1945). |
|||
*G. Folland, A. Sitaram, "The Uncertainty Principle: A Mathematical Survey", ''Journal of Fourier Analysis and Applications'', 1997 pp 207-238. |
|||
{{quote|[Heisenberg's] formulae are, beyond all doubt, derivable ''statistical formulae'' of the quantum theory. But they have been ''habitually misinterpreted'' by those quantum theorists who said that these formulae can be interpreted as determining some upper limit to the ''precision of our measurements''. [original emphasis]<ref>{{cite book |last=Popper |first=K. |title=Quantum theory and the schism in Physics |publisher=Unwin Hyman |year=1982 |pages=53–54}}</ref>}} |
|||
==External links== |
|||
*[http://www.lightandmatter.com/html_books/6mr/ch04/ch04.html Matter as a Wave] - a chapter from an online textbook |
|||
*[http://physnet.org/home/modules/pdf_modules/m241.pdf '' The Uncertainty Relations: Description, Applications''] on [http://www.physnet.org Project PHYSNET] |
|||
*[http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0609163 Quantum mechanics: Myths and facts] |
|||
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qt-uncertainty/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry] |
|||
*[http://www.aip.org/history/heisenberg/p08.htm aip.org: Quantum mechanics 1925-1927 - The uncertainty principle] |
|||
*[http://scienceworld.wolfram.com/physics/UncertaintyPrinciple.html Eric Weisstein's World of Physics - Uncertainty principle] |
|||
*[http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0102069 Schrödinger equation from an exact uncertainty principle] |
|||
*[http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/uncertainty.html John Baez on the time-energy uncertainty relation] |
|||
*[http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/quant-ph/0512223 The time-energy certainty relation] |
|||
*[http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00003139/01/text.pdf PhilSci Archive] - a mathematical note on the single particle interpretation of the uncertainty principle |
|||
Popper proposed an experiment to [[Falsifiability|falsify]] the uncertainty relations, although he later withdrew his initial version after discussions with [[Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker]], Heisenberg, and Einstein; Popper sent his paper to Einstein and it may have influenced the formulation of the EPR paradox.<ref name="Mehra2001">{{cite book | last1 = Mehra | first1 = Jagdish | last2 = Rechenberg | first2 = Helmut | author-link1 = Jagdish Mehra | author-link2 = Helmut Rechenberg | title = The Historical Development of Quantum Theory | publisher = Springer | year = 2001 | isbn = 978-0-387-95086-0 | url-access = registration | url = https://archive.org/details/completionofquan0000mehr }}</ref>{{rp|720}} |
|||
[[Category:Fundamental physics concepts]] |
|||
[[Category:Quantum mechanics]] |
|||
[[Category:Determinism]] |
|||
=== Free will === |
|||
[[ar:مبدأ عدم التأكد]] |
|||
Some scientists, including [[Arthur Compton]]<ref>{{Cite journal | doi = 10.1126/science.74.1911.172| title = The Uncertainty Principle and Free Will| journal = Science| volume = 74| issue = 1911| pages = 172| year = 1931| last1 = Compton | first1 = A. H. | pmid=17808216|bibcode = 1931Sci....74..172C | s2cid = 29126625}}</ref> and [[Martin Heisenberg]],<ref>{{Cite journal | doi = 10.1038/459164a| pmid = 19444190| title = Is free will an illusion?| journal = Nature| volume = 459| issue = 7244| pages = 164–165| year = 2009| last1 = Heisenberg | first1 = M. |bibcode = 2009Natur.459..164H | s2cid = 4420023| doi-access = free}}</ref> have suggested that the uncertainty principle, or at least the general probabilistic nature of quantum mechanics, could be evidence for the two-stage model of free will. One critique, however, is that apart from the basic role of quantum mechanics as a foundation for chemistry, [[Quantum biology|nontrivial biological mechanisms requiring quantum mechanics]] are unlikely, due to the rapid [[Quantum decoherence|decoherence]] time of quantum systems at room temperature.<ref name="ReferenceA">{{Cite journal | doi = 10.1016/j.biosystems.2004.07.001| pmid = 15555759| title = Does quantum mechanics play a non-trivial role in life?| journal = Biosystems| volume = 78| issue = 1–3| pages = 69–79| year = 2004| last1 = Davies | first1 = P. C. W. | bibcode = 2004BiSys..78...69D}}</ref> Proponents of this theory commonly say that this decoherence is overcome by both screening and decoherence-free subspaces found in biological cells.<ref name="ReferenceA"/> |
|||
[[bn:অনিশ্চয়তা নীতি]] |
|||
[[bg:Съотношение на неопределеност на Хайзенберг]] |
|||
=== Thermodynamics === |
|||
[[ca:Principi d'incertesa d'Heisenberg]] |
|||
There is reason to believe that violating the uncertainty principle also strongly implies the violation of the [[second law of thermodynamics]].<ref>{{Cite journal |arxiv = 1205.6894|doi = 10.1038/ncomms2665|title = A violation of the uncertainty principle implies a violation of the second law of thermodynamics|year = 2013|last1 = Hänggi|first1 = Esther|last2 = Wehner|first2 = Stephanie|journal = Nature Communications|volume = 4|pages = 1670|pmid = 23575674|bibcode = 2013NatCo...4.1670H|s2cid = 205316392}}</ref> See [[Gibbs paradox]]. |
|||
[[cs:Princip neurčitosti]] |
|||
[[da:Heisenbergs ubestemthedsrelationer]] |
|||
=== Rejection of the principle === |
|||
[[de:Heisenbergsche Unschärferelation]] |
|||
Uncertainty principles relate quantum particles – electrons for example – to classical concepts – position and momentum. This presumes quantum particles have position and momentum. [[Edwin C. Kemble]] pointed out<ref>{{cite book |last=Kemble |first=E. C. |year=1937 |title=The Fundamental Principles of Quantum Mechanics |location=New York |publisher=McGraw-Hill, reprinted by Dover |page=244}}</ref>{{clarify inline|reason=What printing/edition does this page number refer to? Use year for that, and orig-year for original publication date|date=December 2024}} in 1937 that such properties cannot be experimentally verified and assuming they exist gives rise to many contradictions; similarly [[Rudolf Haag]] notes that position in quantum mechanics is an attribute of an interaction, say between an electron and a detector, not an intrinsic property.<ref>{{cite book |last=Haag |first=R. |year=1996 |title=Local Quantum Physics: Fields, Particles, Algebras |location=Berlin |publisher=Springer}}{{page?|date=February 2024}}{{ISBN?}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Peres |first1=Asher |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/RevModPhys.76.93 |title=Quantum information and relativity theory |last2=Terno |first2=Daniel R. |journal=Reviews of Modern Physics |date=2004-01-06 |volume=76 |issue=1 |pages=93–123 [111] |language=en |doi=10.1103/RevModPhys.76.93 |arxiv=quant-ph/0212023 |bibcode=2004RvMP...76...93P |s2cid=7481797 |issn=0034-6861 |access-date=2024-01-25 |archive-date=2024-02-23 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240223160147/https://journals.aps.org/rmp/abstract/10.1103/RevModPhys.76.93 |url-status=live }}</ref> From this point of view the uncertainty principle is not a fundamental quantum property but a concept "carried over from the language of our ancestors", as Kemble says. |
|||
[[el:Αρχή της απροσδιοριστίας]] |
|||
[[es:Relación de indeterminación de Heisenberg]] |
|||
==Applications== |
|||
[[eu:Heisenbergen ziurgabetasunaren printzipioa]] |
|||
Since the uncertainty principle is such a basic result in quantum mechanics, typical experiments in quantum mechanics routinely observe aspects of it. All forms of [[spectroscopy]], including [[particle physics]] use the relationship to relate measured energy line-width to the lifetime of quantum states. Certain experiments, however, may deliberately test a particular form of the uncertainty principle as part of their main research program. These include, for example, tests of number–phase uncertainty relations in [[superconductivity|superconducting]]<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Elion|first1=W. J. | last2=Matters | first2=M. | last3=Geigenmüller | first3=U. | last4=Mooij | first4=J. E. | title=Direct demonstration of Heisenberg's uncertainty principle in a superconductor | journal=Nature | volume=371 | pages=594–595 | year=1994 | doi= 10.1038/371594a0 | bibcode = 1994Natur.371..594E | issue=6498 | s2cid=4240085}}</ref> or [[quantum optics]]<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Smithey |first1=D. T. |first2=M. |last2=Beck |first3=J. |last3=Cooper |first4=M. G. |last4=Raymer | title=Measurement of number–phase uncertainty relations of optical fields | journal=Physical Review A |volume=48 | pages=3159–3167 | year=1993|doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.48.3159|bibcode = 1993PhRvA..48.3159S|issue=4|pmid=9909968}}</ref> systems. Applications dependent on the uncertainty principle for their operation include extremely low-noise technology such as that required in [[gravitational-wave interferometer|gravitational wave interferometer]]s.<ref>{{cite journal|last=Caves|first=Carlton|title=Quantum-mechanical noise in an interferometer|journal=Physical Review D | volume=23 | pages=1693–1708 | year=1981|doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.23.1693|bibcode = 1981PhRvD..23.1693C|issue=8 }}</ref> |
|||
[[fa:اصل عدم قطعیت]] |
|||
[[fr:Principe d'incertitude]] |
|||
== See also == |
|||
[[gl:Principio de Indeterminación de Heisenberg]] |
|||
{{div col|colwidth=20em}} |
|||
[[ko:불확정성 원리]] |
|||
* {{annotated link|Correspondence principle}} |
|||
[[id:Prinsip Ketidakpastian Heisenberg]] |
|||
* {{annotated link|Goodhart's law}} — when an attempt is made to use a statistical measure for purposes of control (directing), its statistical validity breaks down |
|||
[[it:Principio di indeterminazione di Heisenberg]] |
|||
* {{annotated link|Introduction to quantum mechanics}} |
|||
[[he:עקרון אי הוודאות]] |
|||
* {{annotated link|Küpfmüller's uncertainty principle}} |
|||
[[sw:Kanuni ya Heisenberg ya Utovu wa Hakika]] |
|||
* {{annotated link|Quantum indeterminacy}} |
|||
[[lv:Heizenberga nenoteiktības princips]] |
|||
* {{annotated link|Quantum superposition}} |
|||
[[lt:Heizenbergo neapibrėžtumo principas]] |
|||
* {{annotated link|Quantum tunnelling}} |
|||
[[hu:Határozatlansági reláció]] |
|||
* ''{{annotated link|Physics and Beyond}}'' (Heisenberg's recollections) |
|||
[[ml:അനിശ്ചിതത്വതത്വം]] |
|||
* {{annotated link|Stronger uncertainty relations}} |
|||
[[nl:Onzekerheidsrelatie van Heisenberg]] |
|||
{{div col end}} |
|||
[[ja:不確定性原理]] |
|||
<!-- |
|||
[[no:Heisenbergs uskarphetsrelasjon]] |
|||
== Notes == |
|||
[[pl:Zasada nieoznaczoności]] |
|||
{{reflist|group=note}}--> |
|||
[[pt:Princípio da incerteza de Heisenberg]] |
|||
[[ro:Principiul incertitudinii]] |
|||
== References == |
|||
[[ru:Принцип неопределённости Гейзенберга]] |
|||
{{reflist|30em}} |
|||
[[simple:Uncertainty principle]] |
|||
[[sk:Princíp neurčitosti]] |
|||
== External links == |
|||
[[sl:Načelo nedoločenosti]] |
|||
{{wikiquote}} |
|||
[[fi:Heisenbergin epätarkkuusperiaate]] |
|||
{{Commons category}} |
|||
[[sv:Osäkerhetsprincipen]] |
|||
* {{springer|title=Uncertainty principle|id=p/u095100}} |
|||
[[vi:Nguyên lý bất định]] |
|||
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qt-uncertainty/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry] |
|||
[[tr:Belirsizlik ilkesi]] |
|||
[[uk:Принцип невизначеності]] |
|||
{{Quantum mechanics topics}} |
|||
[[yi:דער אימזיכערקייט פרינציפ]] |
|||
{{Authority control}} |
|||
[[zh:不确定性原理]] |
|||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Uncertainty Principle}} |
|||
[[Category:Quantum mechanics]] |
|||
[[Category:Principles]] |
|||
[[Category:Mathematical physics]] |
|||
[[Category:Inequalities]] |
|||
[[Category:Werner Heisenberg]] |
|||
[[Category:Scientific laws]] |
|||
[[Category:1927 in science]] |
|||
[[Category:1927 in Germany]] |
Latest revision as of 13:44, 2 January 2025
Part of a series of articles about |
Quantum mechanics |
---|
The uncertainty principle, also known as Heisenberg's indeterminacy principle, is a fundamental concept in quantum mechanics. It states that there is a limit to the precision with which certain pairs of physical properties, such as position and momentum, can be simultaneously known. In other words, the more accurately one property is measured, the less accurately the other property can be known.
More formally, the uncertainty principle is any of a variety of mathematical inequalities asserting a fundamental limit to the product of the accuracy of certain related pairs of measurements on a quantum system, such as position, x, and momentum, p.[1] Such paired-variables are known as complementary variables or canonically conjugate variables.
First introduced in 1927 by German physicist Werner Heisenberg,[2][3][4][5] the formal inequality relating the standard deviation of position σx and the standard deviation of momentum σp was derived by Earle Hesse Kennard[6] later that year and by Hermann Weyl[7] in 1928:
where is the reduced Planck constant.
The quintessentially quantum mechanical uncertainty principle comes in many forms other than position–momentum. The energy–time relationship is widely used to relate quantum state lifetime to measured energy widths but its formal derivation is fraught with confusing issues about the nature of time. The basic principle has been extended in numerous directions; it must be considered in many kinds of fundamental physical measurements.
Position–momentum
[edit]It is vital to illustrate how the principle applies to relatively intelligible physical situations since it is indiscernible on the macroscopic[8] scales that humans experience. Two alternative frameworks for quantum physics offer different explanations for the uncertainty principle. The wave mechanics picture of the uncertainty principle is more visually intuitive, but the more abstract matrix mechanics picture formulates it in a way that generalizes more easily.
Mathematically, in wave mechanics, the uncertainty relation between position and momentum arises because the expressions of the wavefunction in the two corresponding orthonormal bases in Hilbert space are Fourier transforms of one another (i.e., position and momentum are conjugate variables). A nonzero function and its Fourier transform cannot both be sharply localized at the same time.[9] A similar tradeoff between the variances of Fourier conjugates arises in all systems underlain by Fourier analysis, for example in sound waves: A pure tone is a sharp spike at a single frequency, while its Fourier transform gives the shape of the sound wave in the time domain, which is a completely delocalized sine wave. In quantum mechanics, the two key points are that the position of the particle takes the form of a matter wave, and momentum is its Fourier conjugate, assured by the de Broglie relation p = ħk, where k is the wavenumber.
In matrix mechanics, the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics, any pair of non-commuting self-adjoint operators representing observables are subject to similar uncertainty limits. An eigenstate of an observable represents the state of the wavefunction for a certain measurement value (the eigenvalue). For example, if a measurement of an observable A is performed, then the system is in a particular eigenstate Ψ of that observable. However, the particular eigenstate of the observable A need not be an eigenstate of another observable B: If so, then it does not have a unique associated measurement for it, as the system is not in an eigenstate of that observable.[10]
Visualization
[edit]The uncertainty principle can be visualized using the position- and momentum-space wavefunctions for one spinless particle with mass in one dimension.
The more localized the position-space wavefunction, the more likely the particle is to be found with the position coordinates in that region, and correspondingly the momentum-space wavefunction is less localized so the possible momentum components the particle could have are more widespread. Conversely, the more localized the momentum-space wavefunction, the more likely the particle is to be found with those values of momentum components in that region, and correspondingly the less localized the position-space wavefunction, so the position coordinates the particle could occupy are more widespread. These wavefunctions are Fourier transforms of each other: mathematically, the uncertainty principle expresses the relationship between conjugate variables in the transform.
Wave mechanics interpretation
[edit]According to the de Broglie hypothesis, every object in the universe is associated with a wave. Thus every object, from an elementary particle to atoms, molecules and on up to planets and beyond are subject to the uncertainty principle.
The time-independent wave function of a single-moded plane wave of wavenumber k0 or momentum p0 is[11]
The Born rule states that this should be interpreted as a probability density amplitude function in the sense that the probability of finding the particle between a and b is
In the case of the single-mode plane wave, is 1 if and 0 otherwise. In other words, the particle position is extremely uncertain in the sense that it could be essentially anywhere along the wave packet.
On the other hand, consider a wave function that is a sum of many waves, which we may write as where An represents the relative contribution of the mode pn to the overall total. The figures to the right show how with the addition of many plane waves, the wave packet can become more localized. We may take this a step further to the continuum limit, where the wave function is an integral over all possible modes with representing the amplitude of these modes and is called the wave function in momentum space. In mathematical terms, we say that is the Fourier transform of and that x and p are conjugate variables. Adding together all of these plane waves comes at a cost, namely the momentum has become less precise, having become a mixture of waves of many different momenta.[12]
One way to quantify the precision of the position and momentum is the standard deviation σ. Since is a probability density function for position, we calculate its standard deviation.
The precision of the position is improved, i.e. reduced σx, by using many plane waves, thereby weakening the precision of the momentum, i.e. increased σp. Another way of stating this is that σx and σp have an inverse relationship or are at least bounded from below. This is the uncertainty principle, the exact limit of which is the Kennard bound.
Proof of the Kennard inequality using wave mechanics
[edit]We are interested in the variances of position and momentum, defined as
Without loss of generality, we will assume that the means vanish, which just amounts to a shift of the origin of our coordinates. (A more general proof that does not make this assumption is given below.) This gives us the simpler form
The function can be interpreted as a vector in a function space. We can define an inner product for a pair of functions u(x) and v(x) in this vector space: where the asterisk denotes the complex conjugate.
With this inner product defined, we note that the variance for position can be written as
We can repeat this for momentum by interpreting the function as a vector, but we can also take advantage of the fact that and are Fourier transforms of each other. We evaluate the inverse Fourier transform through integration by parts: where in the integration by parts, the cancelled term vanishes because the wave function vanishes at infinity, and then use the Dirac delta function which is valid because does not depend on p .
The term is called the momentum operator in position space. Applying Plancherel's theorem, we see that the variance for momentum can be written as
The Cauchy–Schwarz inequality asserts that
The modulus squared of any complex number z can be expressed as we let and and substitute these into the equation above to get
All that remains is to evaluate these inner products.
Plugging this into the above inequalities, we get and taking the square root
with equality if and only if p and x are linearly dependent. Note that the only physics involved in this proof was that and are wave functions for position and momentum, which are Fourier transforms of each other. A similar result would hold for any pair of conjugate variables.
Matrix mechanics interpretation
[edit]In matrix mechanics, observables such as position and momentum are represented by self-adjoint operators.[12] When considering pairs of observables, an important quantity is the commutator. For a pair of operators  and , one defines their commutator as In the case of position and momentum, the commutator is the canonical commutation relation
The physical meaning of the non-commutativity can be understood by considering the effect of the commutator on position and momentum eigenstates. Let be a right eigenstate of position with a constant eigenvalue x0. By definition, this means that Applying the commutator to yields where Î is the identity operator.
Suppose, for the sake of proof by contradiction, that is also a right eigenstate of momentum, with constant eigenvalue p0. If this were true, then one could write On the other hand, the above canonical commutation relation requires that This implies that no quantum state can simultaneously be both a position and a momentum eigenstate.
When a state is measured, it is projected onto an eigenstate in the basis of the relevant observable. For example, if a particle's position is measured, then the state amounts to a position eigenstate. This means that the state is not a momentum eigenstate, however, but rather it can be represented as a sum of multiple momentum basis eigenstates. In other words, the momentum must be less precise. This precision may be quantified by the standard deviations,
As in the wave mechanics interpretation above, one sees a tradeoff between the respective precisions of the two, quantified by the uncertainty principle.
Quantum harmonic oscillator stationary states
[edit]Consider a one-dimensional quantum harmonic oscillator. It is possible to express the position and momentum operators in terms of the creation and annihilation operators:
Using the standard rules for creation and annihilation operators on the energy eigenstates, the variances may be computed directly, The product of these standard deviations is then
In particular, the above Kennard bound[6] is saturated for the ground state n=0, for which the probability density is just the normal distribution.
Quantum harmonic oscillators with Gaussian initial condition
[edit]In a quantum harmonic oscillator of characteristic angular frequency ω, place a state that is offset from the bottom of the potential by some displacement x0 as where Ω describes the width of the initial state but need not be the same as ω. Through integration over the propagator, we can solve for the full time-dependent solution. After many cancelations, the probability densities reduce to where we have used the notation to denote a normal distribution of mean μ and variance σ2. Copying the variances above and applying trigonometric identities, we can write the product of the standard deviations as
From the relations we can conclude the following (the right most equality holds only when Ω = ω):
Coherent states
[edit]A coherent state is a right eigenstate of the annihilation operator, which may be represented in terms of Fock states as
In the picture where the coherent state is a massive particle in a quantum harmonic oscillator, the position and momentum operators may be expressed in terms of the annihilation operators in the same formulas above and used to calculate the variances, Therefore, every coherent state saturates the Kennard bound with position and momentum each contributing an amount in a "balanced" way. Moreover, every squeezed coherent state also saturates the Kennard bound although the individual contributions of position and momentum need not be balanced in general.
Particle in a box
[edit]Consider a particle in a one-dimensional box of length . The eigenfunctions in position and momentum space are and where and we have used the de Broglie relation . The variances of and can be calculated explicitly:
The product of the standard deviations is therefore For all , the quantity is greater than 1, so the uncertainty principle is never violated. For numerical concreteness, the smallest value occurs when , in which case
Constant momentum
[edit]Assume a particle initially has a momentum space wave function described by a normal distribution around some constant momentum p0 according to where we have introduced a reference scale , with describing the width of the distribution—cf. nondimensionalization. If the state is allowed to evolve in free space, then the time-dependent momentum and position space wave functions are
Since and , this can be interpreted as a particle moving along with constant momentum at arbitrarily high precision. On the other hand, the standard deviation of the position is such that the uncertainty product can only increase with time as
Mathematical formalism
[edit]Starting with Kennard's derivation of position-momentum uncertainty, Howard Percy Robertson developed[13][1] a formulation for arbitrary Hermitian operator operators expressed in terms of their standard deviation where the brackets indicate an expectation value of the observable represented by operator . For a pair of operators and , define their commutator as
and the Robertson uncertainty relation is given by[14]
Erwin Schrödinger[15] showed how to allow for correlation between the operators, giving a stronger inequality, known as the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation,[16][1]
where the anticommutator, is used.
The derivation shown here incorporates and builds off of those shown in Robertson,[13] Schrödinger[16] and standard textbooks such as Griffiths.[17]: 138 For any Hermitian operator , based upon the definition of variance, we have we let and thus
Similarly, for any other Hermitian operator in the same state for
The product of the two deviations can thus be expressed as
1 |
In order to relate the two vectors and , we use the Cauchy–Schwarz inequality[18] which is defined as and thus Equation (1) can be written as
2 |
Since is in general a complex number, we use the fact that the modulus squared of any complex number is defined as , where is the complex conjugate of . The modulus squared can also be expressed as
3 |
we let and and substitute these into the equation above to get
4 |
The inner product is written out explicitly as and using the fact that and are Hermitian operators, we find
Similarly it can be shown that
Thus, we have and
We now substitute the above two equations above back into Eq. (4) and get
Substituting the above into Equation (2) we get the Schrödinger uncertainty relation
This proof has an issue[19] related to the domains of the operators involved. For the proof to make sense, the vector has to be in the domain of the unbounded operator , which is not always the case. In fact, the Robertson uncertainty relation is false if is an angle variable and is the derivative with respect to this variable. In this example, the commutator is a nonzero constant—just as in the Heisenberg uncertainty relation—and yet there are states where the product of the uncertainties is zero.[20] (See the counterexample section below.) This issue can be overcome by using a variational method for the proof,[21][22] or by working with an exponentiated version of the canonical commutation relations.[20]
Note that in the general form of the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation, there is no need to assume that the operators and are self-adjoint operators. It suffices to assume that they are merely symmetric operators. (The distinction between these two notions is generally glossed over in the physics literature, where the term Hermitian is used for either or both classes of operators. See Chapter 9 of Hall's book[23] for a detailed discussion of this important but technical distinction.)
Phase space
[edit]In the phase space formulation of quantum mechanics, the Robertson–Schrödinger relation follows from a positivity condition on a real star-square function. Given a Wigner function with star product ★ and a function f, the following is generally true:[24]
Choosing , we arrive at
Since this positivity condition is true for all a, b, and c, it follows that all the eigenvalues of the matrix are non-negative.
The non-negative eigenvalues then imply a corresponding non-negativity condition on the determinant, or, explicitly, after algebraic manipulation,
Examples
[edit]Since the Robertson and Schrödinger relations are for general operators, the relations can be applied to any two observables to obtain specific uncertainty relations. A few of the most common relations found in the literature are given below.
- Position–linear momentum uncertainty relation: for the position and linear momentum operators, the canonical commutation relation implies the Kennard inequality from above:
- Angular momentum uncertainty relation: For two orthogonal components of the total angular momentum operator of an object: where i, j, k are distinct, and Ji denotes angular momentum along the xi axis. This relation implies that unless all three components vanish together, only a single component of a system's angular momentum can be defined with arbitrary precision, normally the component parallel to an external (magnetic or electric) field. Moreover, for , a choice , , in angular momentum multiplets, ψ = |j, m⟩, bounds the Casimir invariant (angular momentum squared, ) from below and thus yields useful constraints such as j(j + 1) ≥ m(m + 1), and hence j ≥ m, among others.
- For the number of electrons in a superconductor and the phase of its Ginzburg–Landau order parameter[25][26]
Limitations
[edit]The derivation of the Robertson inequality for operators and requires and to be defined. There are quantum systems where these conditions are not valid.[27] One example is a quantum particle on a ring, where the wave function depends on an angular variable in the interval . Define "position" and "momentum" operators and by and with periodic boundary conditions on . The definition of depends the range from 0 to . These operators satisfy the usual commutation relations for position and momentum operators, . More precisely, whenever both and are defined, and the space of such is a dense subspace of the quantum Hilbert space.[28]
Now let be any of the eigenstates of , which are given by . These states are normalizable, unlike the eigenstates of the momentum operator on the line. Also the operator is bounded, since ranges over a bounded interval. Thus, in the state , the uncertainty of is zero and the uncertainty of is finite, so that The Robertson uncertainty principle does not apply in this case: is not in the domain of the operator , since multiplication by disrupts the periodic boundary conditions imposed on .[20]
For the usual position and momentum operators and on the real line, no such counterexamples can occur. As long as and are defined in the state , the Heisenberg uncertainty principle holds, even if fails to be in the domain of or of .[29]
Mixed states
[edit]The Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty can be improved noting that it must hold for all components in any decomposition of the density matrix given as Here, for the probabilities and hold. Then, using the relation for , it follows that[30] where the function in the bound is defined The above relation very often has a bound larger than that of the original Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation. Thus, we need to calculate the bound of the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty for the mixed components of the quantum state rather than for the quantum state, and compute an average of their square roots. The following expression is stronger than the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation where on the right-hand side there is a concave roof over the decompositions of the density matrix. The improved relation above is saturated by all single-qubit quantum states.[30]
With similar arguments, one can derive a relation with a convex roof on the right-hand side[30] where denotes the quantum Fisher information and the density matrix is decomposed to pure states as The derivation takes advantage of the fact that the quantum Fisher information is the convex roof of the variance times four.[31][32]
A simpler inequality follows without a convex roof[33] which is stronger than the Heisenberg uncertainty relation, since for the quantum Fisher information we have while for pure states the equality holds.
The Maccone–Pati uncertainty relations
[edit]The Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation can be trivial if the state of the system is chosen to be eigenstate of one of the observable. The stronger uncertainty relations proved by Lorenzo Maccone and Arun K. Pati give non-trivial bounds on the sum of the variances for two incompatible observables.[34] (Earlier works on uncertainty relations formulated as the sum of variances include, e.g., Ref.[35] due to Yichen Huang.) For two non-commuting observables and the first stronger uncertainty relation is given by where , , is a normalized vector that is orthogonal to the state of the system and one should choose the sign of to make this real quantity a positive number.
The second stronger uncertainty relation is given by where is a state orthogonal to . The form of implies that the right-hand side of the new uncertainty relation is nonzero unless is an eigenstate of . One may note that can be an eigenstate of without being an eigenstate of either or . However, when is an eigenstate of one of the two observables the Heisenberg–Schrödinger uncertainty relation becomes trivial. But the lower bound in the new relation is nonzero unless is an eigenstate of both.
Energy–time
[edit]An energy–time uncertainty relation like has a long, controversial history; the meaning of and varies and different formulations have different arenas of validity.[36] However, one well-known application is both well established[37][38] and experimentally verified:[39][40] the connection between the life-time of a resonance state, and its energy width : In particle-physics, widths from experimental fits to the Breit–Wigner energy distribution are used to characterize the lifetime of quasi-stable or decaying states.[41]
An informal, heuristic meaning of the principle is the following:[42] A state that only exists for a short time cannot have a definite energy. To have a definite energy, the frequency of the state must be defined accurately, and this requires the state to hang around for many cycles, the reciprocal of the required accuracy. For example, in spectroscopy, excited states have a finite lifetime. By the time–energy uncertainty principle, they do not have a definite energy, and, each time they decay, the energy they release is slightly different. The average energy of the outgoing photon has a peak at the theoretical energy of the state, but the distribution has a finite width called the natural linewidth. Fast-decaying states have a broad linewidth, while slow-decaying states have a narrow linewidth.[43] The same linewidth effect also makes it difficult to specify the rest mass of unstable, fast-decaying particles in particle physics. The faster the particle decays (the shorter its lifetime), the less certain is its mass (the larger the particle's width).
Time in quantum mechanics
[edit]The concept of "time" in quantum mechanics offers many challenges.[44] There is no quantum theory of time measurement; relativity is both fundamental to time and difficult to include in quantum mechanics.[36] While position and momentum are associated with a single particle, time is a system property: it has no operator needed for the Robertson–Schrödinger relation.[1] The mathematical treatment of stable and unstable quantum systems differ.[45] These factors combine to make energy–time uncertainty principles controversial.
Three notions of "time" can be distinguished:[36] external, intrinsic, and observable. External or laboratory time is seen by the experimenter; intrinsic time is inferred by changes in dynamic variables, like the hands of a clock or the motion of a free particle; observable time concerns time as an observable, the measurement of time-separated events.
An external-time energy–time uncertainty principle might say that measuring the energy of a quantum system to an accuracy requires a time interval .[38] However, Yakir Aharonov and David Bohm[46][36] have shown that, in some quantum systems, energy can be measured accurately within an arbitrarily short time: external-time uncertainty principles are not universal.
Intrinsic time is the basis for several formulations of energy–time uncertainty relations, including the Mandelstam–Tamm relation discussed in the next section. A physical system with an intrinsic time closely matching the external laboratory time is called a "clock".[44]: 31
Observable time, measuring time between two events, remains a challenge for quantum theories; some progress has been made using positive operator-valued measure concepts.[36]
Mandelstam–Tamm
[edit]In 1945, Leonid Mandelstam and Igor Tamm derived a non-relativistic time–energy uncertainty relation as follows.[47][36] From Heisenberg mechanics, the generalized Ehrenfest theorem for an observable B without explicit time dependence, represented by a self-adjoint operator relates time dependence of the average value of to the average of its commutator with the Hamiltonian:
The value of is then substituted in the Robertson uncertainty relation for the energy operator and : giving (whenever the denominator is nonzero). While this is a universal result, it depends upon the observable chosen and that the deviations and are computed for a particular state. Identifying and the characteristic time gives an energy–time relationship Although has the dimension of time, it is different from the time parameter t that enters the Schrödinger equation. This can be interpreted as time for which the expectation value of the observable, changes by an amount equal to one standard deviation.[48] Examples:
- The time a free quantum particle passes a point in space is more uncertain as the energy of the state is more precisely controlled: Since the time spread is related to the particle position spread and the energy spread is related to the momentum spread, this relation is directly related to position–momentum uncertainty.[17]: 144
- A Delta particle, a quasistable composite of quarks related to protons and neutrons, has a lifetime of 10−23 s, so its measured mass equivalent to energy, 1232 MeV/c2, varies by ±120 MeV/c2; this variation is intrinsic and not caused by measurement errors.[17]: 144
- Two energy states with energies superimposed to create a composite state
- The probability amplitude of this state has a time-dependent interference term:
- The oscillation period varies inversely with the energy difference: .[17]: 144
Each example has a different meaning for the time uncertainty, according to the observable and state used.
Quantum field theory
[edit]Some formulations of quantum field theory uses temporary electron–positron pairs in its calculations called virtual particles. The mass-energy and lifetime of these particles are related by the energy–time uncertainty relation. The energy of a quantum systems is not known with enough precision to limit their behavior to a single, simple history. Thus the influence of all histories must be incorporated into quantum calculations, including those with much greater or much less energy than the mean of the measured/calculated energy distribution.
The energy–time uncertainty principle does not temporarily violate conservation of energy; it does not imply that energy can be "borrowed" from the universe as long as it is "returned" within a short amount of time.[17]: 145 The energy of the universe is not an exactly known parameter at all times.[1] When events transpire at very short time intervals, there is uncertainty in the energy of these events.
Harmonic analysis
[edit]In the context of harmonic analysis the uncertainty principle implies that one cannot at the same time localize the value of a function and its Fourier transform. To wit, the following inequality holds,
Further mathematical uncertainty inequalities, including the above entropic uncertainty, hold between a function f and its Fourier transform ƒ̂:[49][50][51]
Signal processing
[edit]In the context of time–frequency analysis uncertainty principles are referred to as the Gabor limit, after Dennis Gabor, or sometimes the Heisenberg–Gabor limit. The basic result, which follows from "Benedicks's theorem", below, is that a function cannot be both time limited and band limited (a function and its Fourier transform cannot both have bounded domain)—see bandlimited versus timelimited. More accurately, the time-bandwidth or duration-bandwidth product satisfies where and are the standard deviations of the time and frequency energy concentrations respectively.[52] The minimum is attained for a Gaussian-shaped pulse (Gabor wavelet) [For the un-squared Gaussian (i.e. signal amplitude) and its un-squared Fourier transform magnitude ; squaring reduces each by a factor .] Another common measure is the product of the time and frequency full width at half maximum (of the power/energy), which for the Gaussian equals (see bandwidth-limited pulse).
Stated differently, one cannot simultaneously sharply localize a signal f in both the time domain and frequency domain.
When applied to filters, the result implies that one cannot simultaneously achieve a high temporal resolution and high frequency resolution at the same time; a concrete example are the resolution issues of the short-time Fourier transform—if one uses a wide window, one achieves good frequency resolution at the cost of temporal resolution, while a narrow window has the opposite trade-off.
Alternate theorems give more precise quantitative results, and, in time–frequency analysis, rather than interpreting the (1-dimensional) time and frequency domains separately, one instead interprets the limit as a lower limit on the support of a function in the (2-dimensional) time–frequency plane. In practice, the Gabor limit limits the simultaneous time–frequency resolution one can achieve without interference; it is possible to achieve higher resolution, but at the cost of different components of the signal interfering with each other.
As a result, in order to analyze signals where the transients are important, the wavelet transform is often used instead of the Fourier.
Discrete Fourier transform
[edit]Let be a sequence of N complex numbers and be its discrete Fourier transform.
Denote by the number of non-zero elements in the time sequence and by the number of non-zero elements in the frequency sequence . Then,
This inequality is sharp, with equality achieved when x or X is a Dirac mass, or more generally when x is a nonzero multiple of a Dirac comb supported on a subgroup of the integers modulo N (in which case X is also a Dirac comb supported on a complementary subgroup, and vice versa).
More generally, if T and W are subsets of the integers modulo N, let denote the time-limiting operator and band-limiting operators, respectively. Then where the norm is the operator norm of operators on the Hilbert space of functions on the integers modulo N. This inequality has implications for signal reconstruction.[53]
When N is a prime number, a stronger inequality holds: Discovered by Terence Tao, this inequality is also sharp.[54]
Benedicks's theorem
[edit]Amrein–Berthier[55] and Benedicks's theorem[56] intuitively says that the set of points where f is non-zero and the set of points where ƒ̂ is non-zero cannot both be small.
Specifically, it is impossible for a function f in L2(R) and its Fourier transform ƒ̂ to both be supported on sets of finite Lebesgue measure. A more quantitative version is[57][58]
One expects that the factor CeC|S||Σ| may be replaced by CeC(|S||Σ|)1/d, which is only known if either S or Σ is convex.
Hardy's uncertainty principle
[edit]The mathematician G. H. Hardy formulated the following uncertainty principle:[59] it is not possible for f and ƒ̂ to both be "very rapidly decreasing". Specifically, if f in is such that and ( an integer), then, if ab > 1, f = 0, while if ab = 1, then there is a polynomial P of degree ≤ N such that
This was later improved as follows: if is such that then where P is a polynomial of degree (N − d)/2 and A is a real d × d positive definite matrix.
This result was stated in Beurling's complete works without proof and proved in Hörmander[60] (the case ) and Bonami, Demange, and Jaming[61] for the general case. Note that Hörmander–Beurling's version implies the case ab > 1 in Hardy's Theorem while the version by Bonami–Demange–Jaming covers the full strength of Hardy's Theorem. A different proof of Beurling's theorem based on Liouville's theorem appeared in ref.[62]
A full description of the case ab < 1 as well as the following extension to Schwartz class distributions appears in ref.[63]
Theorem — If a tempered distribution is such that and then for some convenient polynomial P and real positive definite matrix A of type d × d.
Additional uncertainty relations
[edit]Heisenberg limit
[edit]In quantum metrology, and especially interferometry, the Heisenberg limit is the optimal rate at which the accuracy of a measurement can scale with the energy used in the measurement. Typically, this is the measurement of a phase (applied to one arm of a beam-splitter) and the energy is given by the number of photons used in an interferometer. Although some claim to have broken the Heisenberg limit, this reflects disagreement on the definition of the scaling resource.[64] Suitably defined, the Heisenberg limit is a consequence of the basic principles of quantum mechanics and cannot be beaten, although the weak Heisenberg limit can be beaten.[65]
Systematic and statistical errors
[edit]The inequalities above focus on the statistical imprecision of observables as quantified by the standard deviation . Heisenberg's original version, however, was dealing with the systematic error, a disturbance of the quantum system produced by the measuring apparatus, i.e., an observer effect.
If we let represent the error (i.e., inaccuracy) of a measurement of an observable A and the disturbance produced on a subsequent measurement of the conjugate variable B by the former measurement of A, then the inequality proposed by Masanao Ozawa − encompassing both systematic and statistical errors - holds:[66]
Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, as originally described in the 1927 formulation, mentions only the first term of Ozawa inequality, regarding the systematic error. Using the notation above to describe the error/disturbance effect of sequential measurements (first A, then B), it could be written as
The formal derivation of the Heisenberg relation is possible but far from intuitive. It was not proposed by Heisenberg, but formulated in a mathematically consistent way only in recent years.[67][68] Also, it must be stressed that the Heisenberg formulation is not taking into account the intrinsic statistical errors and . There is increasing experimental evidence[69][70][71][72] that the total quantum uncertainty cannot be described by the Heisenberg term alone, but requires the presence of all the three terms of the Ozawa inequality.
Using the same formalism,[1] it is also possible to introduce the other kind of physical situation, often confused with the previous one, namely the case of simultaneous measurements (A and B at the same time):
The two simultaneous measurements on A and B are necessarily[73] unsharp or weak.
It is also possible to derive an uncertainty relation that, as the Ozawa's one, combines both the statistical and systematic error components, but keeps a form very close to the Heisenberg original inequality. By adding Robertson[1]
and Ozawa relations we obtain The four terms can be written as: Defining: as the inaccuracy in the measured values of the variable A and as the resulting fluctuation in the conjugate variable B, Kazuo Fujikawa[74] established an uncertainty relation similar to the Heisenberg original one, but valid both for systematic and statistical errors:
Quantum entropic uncertainty principle
[edit]For many distributions, the standard deviation is not a particularly natural way of quantifying the structure. For example, uncertainty relations in which one of the observables is an angle has little physical meaning for fluctuations larger than one period.[22][75][76][77] Other examples include highly bimodal distributions, or unimodal distributions with divergent variance.
A solution that overcomes these issues is an uncertainty based on entropic uncertainty instead of the product of variances. While formulating the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics in 1957, Hugh Everett III conjectured a stronger extension of the uncertainty principle based on entropic certainty.[78] This conjecture, also studied by I. I. Hirschman[79] and proven in 1975 by W. Beckner[80] and by Iwo Bialynicki-Birula and Jerzy Mycielski[81] is that, for two normalized, dimensionless Fourier transform pairs f(a) and g(b) where
- and
the Shannon information entropies and are subject to the following constraint,
where the logarithms may be in any base.
The probability distribution functions associated with the position wave function ψ(x) and the momentum wave function φ(x) have dimensions of inverse length and momentum respectively, but the entropies may be rendered dimensionless by where x0 and p0 are some arbitrarily chosen length and momentum respectively, which render the arguments of the logarithms dimensionless. Note that the entropies will be functions of these chosen parameters. Due to the Fourier transform relation between the position wave function ψ(x) and the momentum wavefunction φ(p), the above constraint can be written for the corresponding entropies as
where h is the Planck constant.
Depending on one's choice of the x0 p0 product, the expression may be written in many ways. If x0 p0 is chosen to be h, then
If, instead, x0 p0 is chosen to be ħ, then
If x0 and p0 are chosen to be unity in whatever system of units are being used, then where h is interpreted as a dimensionless number equal to the value of the Planck constant in the chosen system of units. Note that these inequalities can be extended to multimode quantum states, or wavefunctions in more than one spatial dimension.[82]
The quantum entropic uncertainty principle is more restrictive than the Heisenberg uncertainty principle. From the inverse logarithmic Sobolev inequalities[83] (equivalently, from the fact that normal distributions maximize the entropy of all such with a given variance), it readily follows that this entropic uncertainty principle is stronger than the one based on standard deviations, because
In other words, the Heisenberg uncertainty principle, is a consequence of the quantum entropic uncertainty principle, but not vice versa. A few remarks on these inequalities. First, the choice of base e is a matter of popular convention in physics. The logarithm can alternatively be in any base, provided that it be consistent on both sides of the inequality. Second, recall the Shannon entropy has been used, not the quantum von Neumann entropy. Finally, the normal distribution saturates the inequality, and it is the only distribution with this property, because it is the maximum entropy probability distribution among those with fixed variance (cf. here for proof).
Entropic uncertainty of the normal distribution |
---|
We demonstrate this method on the ground state of the QHO, which as discussed above saturates the usual uncertainty based on standard deviations. The length scale can be set to whatever is convenient, so we assign
The probability distribution is the normal distribution with Shannon entropy A completely analogous calculation proceeds for the momentum distribution. Choosing a standard momentum of : The entropic uncertainty is therefore the limiting value |
A measurement apparatus will have a finite resolution set by the discretization of its possible outputs into bins, with the probability of lying within one of the bins given by the Born rule. We will consider the most common experimental situation, in which the bins are of uniform size. Let δx be a measure of the spatial resolution. We take the zeroth bin to be centered near the origin, with possibly some small constant offset c. The probability of lying within the jth interval of width δx is
To account for this discretization, we can define the Shannon entropy of the wave function for a given measurement apparatus as
Under the above definition, the entropic uncertainty relation is
Here we note that δx δp/h is a typical infinitesimal phase space volume used in the calculation of a partition function. The inequality is also strict and not saturated. Efforts to improve this bound are an active area of research.
Normal distribution example |
---|
We demonstrate this method first on the ground state of the QHO, which as discussed above saturates the usual uncertainty based on standard deviations.
The probability of lying within one of these bins can be expressed in terms of the error function.
The momentum probabilities are completely analogous.
For simplicity, we will set the resolutions to so that the probabilities reduce to The Shannon entropy can be evaluated numerically. The entropic uncertainty is indeed larger than the limiting value. Note that despite being in the optimal case, the inequality is not saturated. |
Sinc function example |
---|
An example of a unimodal distribution with infinite variance is the sinc function. If the wave function is the correctly normalized uniform distribution,
then its Fourier transform is the sinc function, which yields infinite momentum variance despite having a centralized shape. The entropic uncertainty, on the other hand, is finite. Suppose for simplicity that the spatial resolution is just a two-bin measurement, δx = a, and that the momentum resolution is δp = h/a. Partitioning the uniform spatial distribution into two equal bins is straightforward. We set the offset c = 1/2 so that the two bins span the distribution. The bins for momentum must cover the entire real line. As done with the spatial distribution, we could apply an offset. It turns out, however, that the Shannon entropy is minimized when the zeroth bin for momentum is centered at the origin. (The reader is encouraged to try adding an offset.) The probability of lying within an arbitrary momentum bin can be expressed in terms of the sine integral.
The Shannon entropy can be evaluated numerically. The entropic uncertainty is indeed larger than the limiting value. |
Uncertainty relation with three angular momentum components
[edit]For a particle of total angular momentum the following uncertainty relation holds where are angular momentum components. The relation can be derived from and The relation can be strengthened as[30][84] where is the quantum Fisher information.
History
[edit]In 1925 Heisenberg published the Umdeutung (reinterpretation) paper where he showed that central aspect of quantum theory was the non-commutativity: the theory implied that the relative order of position and momentum measurement was significant. Working with Max Born and Pascual Jordan, he continued to develop matrix mechanics, that would become the first modern quantum mechanics formulation.[85]
In March 1926, working in Bohr's institute, Heisenberg realized that the non-commutativity implies the uncertainty principle. Writing to Wolfgang Pauli in February 1927, he worked out the basic concepts.[86]
In his celebrated 1927 paper "Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik" ("On the Perceptual Content of Quantum Theoretical Kinematics and Mechanics"), Heisenberg established this expression as the minimum amount of unavoidable momentum disturbance caused by any position measurement,[2] but he did not give a precise definition for the uncertainties Δx and Δp. Instead, he gave some plausible estimates in each case separately. His paper gave an analysis in terms of a microscope that Bohr showed was incorrect; Heisenberg included an addendum to the publication.
In his 1930 Chicago lecture[87] he refined his principle:
A1 |
Later work broadened the concept. Any two variables that do not commute cannot be measured simultaneously—the more precisely one is known, the less precisely the other can be known. Heisenberg wrote:
It can be expressed in its simplest form as follows: One can never know with perfect accuracy both of those two important factors which determine the movement of one of the smallest particles—its position and its velocity. It is impossible to determine accurately both the position and the direction and speed of a particle at the same instant.[88]
Kennard[6][1]: 204 in 1927 first proved the modern inequality:
A2 |
where ħ = h/2π, and σx, σp are the standard deviations of position and momentum. (Heisenberg only proved relation (A2) for the special case of Gaussian states.[87]) In 1929 Robertson generalized the inequality to all observables and in 1930 Schrödinger extended the form to allow non-zero covariance of the operators; this result is referred to as Robertson-Schrödinger inequality.[1]: 204
Terminology and translation
[edit]Throughout the main body of his original 1927 paper, written in German, Heisenberg used the word "Ungenauigkeit",[2] to describe the basic theoretical principle. Only in the endnote did he switch to the word "Unsicherheit". Later on, he always used "Unbestimmtheit". When the English-language version of Heisenberg's textbook, The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory, was published in 1930, however, only the English word "uncertainty" was used, and it became the term in the English language.[89]
Heisenberg's microscope
[edit]The principle is quite counter-intuitive, so the early students of quantum theory had to be reassured that naive measurements to violate it were bound always to be unworkable. One way in which Heisenberg originally illustrated the intrinsic impossibility of violating the uncertainty principle is by using the observer effect of an imaginary microscope as a measuring device.[87]
He imagines an experimenter trying to measure the position and momentum of an electron by shooting a photon at it.[90]: 49–50
- Problem 1 – If the photon has a short wavelength, and therefore, a large momentum, the position can be measured accurately. But the photon scatters in a random direction, transferring a large and uncertain amount of momentum to the electron. If the photon has a long wavelength and low momentum, the collision does not disturb the electron's momentum very much, but the scattering will reveal its position only vaguely.
- Problem 2 – If a large aperture is used for the microscope, the electron's location can be well resolved (see Rayleigh criterion); but by the principle of conservation of momentum, the transverse momentum of the incoming photon affects the electron's beamline momentum and hence, the new momentum of the electron resolves poorly. If a small aperture is used, the accuracy of both resolutions is the other way around.
The combination of these trade-offs implies that no matter what photon wavelength and aperture size are used, the product of the uncertainty in measured position and measured momentum is greater than or equal to a lower limit, which is (up to a small numerical factor) equal to the Planck constant.[91] Heisenberg did not care to formulate the uncertainty principle as an exact limit, and preferred to use it instead, as a heuristic quantitative statement, correct up to small numerical factors, which makes the radically new noncommutativity of quantum mechanics inevitable.
Intrinsic quantum uncertainty
[edit]Historically, the uncertainty principle has been confused[92][66] with a related effect in physics, called the observer effect, which notes that measurements of certain systems cannot be made without affecting the system,[93][94] that is, without changing something in a system. Heisenberg used such an observer effect at the quantum level (see below) as a physical "explanation" of quantum uncertainty.[95] It has since become clearer, however, that the uncertainty principle is inherent in the properties of all wave-like systems,[69] and that it arises in quantum mechanics simply due to the matter wave nature of all quantum objects.[96] Thus, the uncertainty principle actually states a fundamental property of quantum systems and is not a statement about the observational success of current technology.[97]
Critical reactions
[edit]The Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics and Heisenberg's uncertainty principle were, in fact, initially seen as twin targets by detractors. According to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, there is no fundamental reality that the quantum state describes, just a prescription for calculating experimental results. There is no way to say what the state of a system fundamentally is, only what the result of observations might be.
Albert Einstein believed that randomness is a reflection of our ignorance of some fundamental property of reality, while Niels Bohr believed that the probability distributions are fundamental and irreducible, and depend on which measurements we choose to perform. Einstein and Bohr debated the uncertainty principle for many years.
Ideal detached observer
[edit]Wolfgang Pauli called Einstein's fundamental objection to the uncertainty principle "the ideal of the detached observer" (phrase translated from the German):
"Like the moon has a definite position," Einstein said to me last winter, "whether or not we look at the moon, the same must also hold for the atomic objects, as there is no sharp distinction possible between these and macroscopic objects. Observation cannot create an element of reality like a position, there must be something contained in the complete description of physical reality which corresponds to the possibility of observing a position, already before the observation has been actually made." I hope, that I quoted Einstein correctly; it is always difficult to quote somebody out of memory with whom one does not agree. It is precisely this kind of postulate which I call the ideal of the detached observer.
— Letter from Pauli to Niels Bohr, February 15, 1955[98]
Einstein's slit
[edit]The first of Einstein's thought experiments challenging the uncertainty principle went as follows:
Consider a particle passing through a slit of width d. The slit introduces an uncertainty in momentum of approximately h/d because the particle passes through the wall. But let us determine the momentum of the particle by measuring the recoil of the wall. In doing so, we find the momentum of the particle to arbitrary accuracy by conservation of momentum.
Bohr's response was that the wall is quantum mechanical as well, and that to measure the recoil to accuracy Δp, the momentum of the wall must be known to this accuracy before the particle passes through. This introduces an uncertainty in the position of the wall and therefore the position of the slit equal to h/Δp, and if the wall's momentum is known precisely enough to measure the recoil, the slit's position is uncertain enough to disallow a position measurement.
A similar analysis with particles diffracting through multiple slits is given by Richard Feynman.[99]
Einstein's box
[edit]Bohr was present when Einstein proposed the thought experiment which has become known as Einstein's box. Einstein argued that "Heisenberg's uncertainty equation implied that the uncertainty in time was related to the uncertainty in energy, the product of the two being related to the Planck constant."[100] Consider, he said, an ideal box, lined with mirrors so that it can contain light indefinitely. The box could be weighed before a clockwork mechanism opened an ideal shutter at a chosen instant to allow one single photon to escape. "We now know, explained Einstein, precisely the time at which the photon left the box."[101] "Now, weigh the box again. The change of mass tells the energy of the emitted light. In this manner, said Einstein, one could measure the energy emitted and the time it was released with any desired precision, in contradiction to the uncertainty principle."[100]
Bohr spent a sleepless night considering this argument, and eventually realized that it was flawed. He pointed out that if the box were to be weighed, say by a spring and a pointer on a scale, "since the box must move vertically with a change in its weight, there will be uncertainty in its vertical velocity and therefore an uncertainty in its height above the table. ... Furthermore, the uncertainty about the elevation above the Earth's surface will result in an uncertainty in the rate of the clock",[102] because of Einstein's own theory of gravity's effect on time. "Through this chain of uncertainties, Bohr showed that Einstein's light box experiment could not simultaneously measure exactly both the energy of the photon and the time of its escape."[103]
EPR paradox for entangled particles
[edit]In 1935, Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen published an analysis of spatially separated entangled particles (EPR paradox).[104] According to EPR, one could measure the position of one of the entangled particles and the momentum of the second particle, and from those measurements deduce the position and momentum of both particles to any precision, violating the uncertainty principle. In order to avoid such possibility, the measurement of one particle must modify the probability distribution of the other particle instantaneously, possibly violating the principle of locality.[105]
In 1964, John Stewart Bell showed that this assumption can be falsified, since it would imply a certain inequality between the probabilities of different experiments. Experimental results confirm the predictions of quantum mechanics, ruling out EPR's basic assumption of local hidden variables.
Popper's criticism
[edit]Science philosopher Karl Popper approached the problem of indeterminacy as a logician and metaphysical realist.[106] He disagreed with the application of the uncertainty relations to individual particles rather than to ensembles of identically prepared particles, referring to them as "statistical scatter relations".[106][107] In this statistical interpretation, a particular measurement may be made to arbitrary precision without invalidating the quantum theory.
In 1934, Popper published Zur Kritik der Ungenauigkeitsrelationen ("Critique of the Uncertainty Relations") in Naturwissenschaften,[108] and in the same year Logik der Forschung (translated and updated by the author as The Logic of Scientific Discovery in 1959[106]), outlining his arguments for the statistical interpretation. In 1982, he further developed his theory in Quantum theory and the schism in Physics, writing:
[Heisenberg's] formulae are, beyond all doubt, derivable statistical formulae of the quantum theory. But they have been habitually misinterpreted by those quantum theorists who said that these formulae can be interpreted as determining some upper limit to the precision of our measurements. [original emphasis][109]
Popper proposed an experiment to falsify the uncertainty relations, although he later withdrew his initial version after discussions with Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker, Heisenberg, and Einstein; Popper sent his paper to Einstein and it may have influenced the formulation of the EPR paradox.[110]: 720
Free will
[edit]Some scientists, including Arthur Compton[111] and Martin Heisenberg,[112] have suggested that the uncertainty principle, or at least the general probabilistic nature of quantum mechanics, could be evidence for the two-stage model of free will. One critique, however, is that apart from the basic role of quantum mechanics as a foundation for chemistry, nontrivial biological mechanisms requiring quantum mechanics are unlikely, due to the rapid decoherence time of quantum systems at room temperature.[113] Proponents of this theory commonly say that this decoherence is overcome by both screening and decoherence-free subspaces found in biological cells.[113]
Thermodynamics
[edit]There is reason to believe that violating the uncertainty principle also strongly implies the violation of the second law of thermodynamics.[114] See Gibbs paradox.
Rejection of the principle
[edit]Uncertainty principles relate quantum particles – electrons for example – to classical concepts – position and momentum. This presumes quantum particles have position and momentum. Edwin C. Kemble pointed out[115][clarification needed] in 1937 that such properties cannot be experimentally verified and assuming they exist gives rise to many contradictions; similarly Rudolf Haag notes that position in quantum mechanics is an attribute of an interaction, say between an electron and a detector, not an intrinsic property.[116][117] From this point of view the uncertainty principle is not a fundamental quantum property but a concept "carried over from the language of our ancestors", as Kemble says.
Applications
[edit]Since the uncertainty principle is such a basic result in quantum mechanics, typical experiments in quantum mechanics routinely observe aspects of it. All forms of spectroscopy, including particle physics use the relationship to relate measured energy line-width to the lifetime of quantum states. Certain experiments, however, may deliberately test a particular form of the uncertainty principle as part of their main research program. These include, for example, tests of number–phase uncertainty relations in superconducting[118] or quantum optics[119] systems. Applications dependent on the uncertainty principle for their operation include extremely low-noise technology such as that required in gravitational wave interferometers.[120]
See also
[edit]- Correspondence principle – Physics principle formulated by Niels Bohr
- Goodhart's law – Adage about statistical measures — when an attempt is made to use a statistical measure for purposes of control (directing), its statistical validity breaks down
- Introduction to quantum mechanics – Non-mathematical introduction
- Küpfmüller's uncertainty principle – concept in electronic engineering formulated by Karl Küpfmüller
- Quantum indeterminacy – Apparent lack of definite state before measurement of quantum systems
- Quantum superposition – Principle of quantum mechanics
- Quantum tunnelling – Quantum mechanical phenomenon
- Physics and Beyond – 1969 book by Werner Heisenberg (Heisenberg's recollections)
- Stronger uncertainty relations – Later developments of Heisenberg's principle
References
[edit]- ^ a b c d e f g h i Sen, D. (2014). "The Uncertainty relations in quantum mechanics" (PDF). Current Science. 107 (2): 203–218. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2019-09-24. Retrieved 2016-02-14.
- ^ a b c Heisenberg, W. (1927) [1927-03-01]. "Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik". Zeitschrift für Physik (in German). 43 (3): 172–198. Bibcode:1927ZPhy...43..172H. doi:10.1007/BF01397280. ISSN 0044-3328. S2CID 122763326.Heisenberg, W (1983) [1927]. "The actual content of quantum theoretical kinematics and mechanics". No. NAS 1.15: 77379. 1983. 43 (3–4): 172. Bibcode:1983ZhPhy..43..172H. Archived from the original on 2023-09-02. Retrieved 2023-08-28.
English translation of Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik
- ^ Werner Heisenberg (1989), Encounters with Einstein and Other Essays on People, Places and Particles, Princeton University Press, p. 53. [ISBN missing]
- ^ Dolling, Lisa M.; Gianelli, Arthur F.; Statile, Glenn N., eds. (2003). The Tests of Time. doi:10.1515/9781400889167. ISBN 978-1400889167.
- ^ Kumar, Manjit. Quantum: Einstein, Bohr, and the great debate about the nature of reality. 1st American ed., 2008. Chap. 10, Note 37. [ISBN missing]
- ^ a b c Kennard, E. H. (1927), "Zur Quantenmechanik einfacher Bewegungstypen", Zeitschrift für Physik (in German), 44 (4–5): 326–352, Bibcode:1927ZPhy...44..326K, doi:10.1007/BF01391200, S2CID 121626384.
- ^ Weyl, H. (1928). Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik (in German). Leipzig: Hirzel.[page needed]
- ^ Jaeger, Gregg (September 2014). "What in the (quantum) world is macroscopic?". American Journal of Physics. 82 (9): 896–905. Bibcode:2014AmJPh..82..896J. doi:10.1119/1.4878358.
- ^ See Appendix B in Bialynicki-Birula, Iwo; Bialynicka-Birula, Zofia (2009), "Why photons cannot be sharply localized", Physical Review A, 79 (3): 7–8, arXiv:0903.3712, Bibcode:2009PhRvA..79c2112B, doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.79.032112, S2CID 55632217
- ^ Claude Cohen-Tannoudji; Bernard Diu; Franck Laloë (1996), Quantum mechanics, Wiley-Interscience: Wiley, pp. 231–233, ISBN 978-0-471-56952-7
- ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, p. 60, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
- ^ a b Landau, Lev Davidovich; Lifshitz, Evgeny Mikhailovich (1977). Quantum Mechanics: Non-Relativistic Theory. Vol. 3 (3rd ed.). Pergamon Press. ISBN 978-0-08-020940-1.
- ^ a b Robertson, H. P. (1929), "The Uncertainty Principle", Phys. Rev., 34 (1): 163–164, Bibcode:1929PhRv...34..163R, doi:10.1103/PhysRev.34.163
- ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, pp. 242–243, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
- ^ Schrödinger, E., Zum Heisenbergschen Unschärfeprinzip, Berliner Berichte, 1930, pp. 296–303.
- ^ a b Schrödinger, E. (1930), "Zum Heisenbergschen Unschärfeprinzip", Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-mathematische Klasse, 14: 296–303
- ^ a b c d e Griffiths, David J.; Schroeter, Darrell F. (2018). Introduction to Quantum Mechanics (3rd ed.). Cambridge University Press. Bibcode:2018iqm..book.....G. doi:10.1017/9781316995433. ISBN 978-1-316-99543-3. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2024-01-27.
- ^ Riley, K. F.; M. P. Hobson and S. J. Bence (2006), Mathematical Methods for Physics and Engineering, Cambridge, p. 246[ISBN missing]
- ^ Davidson, E. R. (1965), "On Derivations of the Uncertainty Principle", J. Chem. Phys., 42 (4): 1461–1462, Bibcode:1965JChPh..42.1461D, doi:10.1063/1.1696139
- ^ a b c Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, p. 245, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
- ^ Jackiw, Roman (1968), "Minimum Uncertainty Product, Number-Phase Uncertainty Product, and Coherent States", J. Math. Phys., 9 (3): 339–346, Bibcode:1968JMP.....9..339J, doi:10.1063/1.1664585
- ^ a b Carruthers, P.; Nieto, M. M. (1968), "Phase and Angle Variables in Quantum Mechanics", Rev. Mod. Phys., 40 (2): 411–440, Bibcode:1968RvMP...40..411C, doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.40.411
- ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
- ^ Curtright, T.; Zachos, C. (2001). "Negative Probability and Uncertainty Relations". Modern Physics Letters A. 16 (37): 2381–2385. arXiv:hep-th/0105226. Bibcode:2001MPLA...16.2381C. doi:10.1142/S021773230100576X. S2CID 119669313.
- ^ Likharev, K. K.; A. B. Zorin (1985), "Theory of Bloch-Wave Oscillations in Small Josephson Junctions", J. Low Temp. Phys., 59 (3/4): 347–382, Bibcode:1985JLTP...59..347L, doi:10.1007/BF00683782, S2CID 120813342
- ^ Anderson, P. W. (1964), "Special Effects in Superconductivity", in Caianiello, E. R. (ed.), Lectures on the Many-Body Problem, Vol. 2, New York: Academic Press
- ^ Davidson, Ernest R. (1965-02-15). "On Derivations of the Uncertainty Principle". The Journal of Chemical Physics. 42 (4): 1461–1462. Bibcode:1965JChPh..42.1461D. doi:10.1063/1.1696139. ISSN 0021-9606. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2024-01-20.
- ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, p. 245, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
- ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, p. 246, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
- ^ a b c d Tóth, Géza; Fröwis, Florian (31 January 2022). "Uncertainty relations with the variance and the quantum Fisher information based on convex decompositions of density matrices". Physical Review Research. 4 (1): 013075. arXiv:2109.06893. Bibcode:2022PhRvR...4a3075T. doi:10.1103/PhysRevResearch.4.013075. S2CID 237513549.
- ^ Tóth, Géza; Petz, Dénes (20 March 2013). "Extremal properties of the variance and the quantum Fisher information". Physical Review A. 87 (3): 032324. arXiv:1109.2831. Bibcode:2013PhRvA..87c2324T. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.87.032324. S2CID 55088553.
- ^ Yu, Sixia (2013). "Quantum Fisher Information as the Convex Roof of Variance". arXiv:1302.5311 [quant-ph].
- ^ Fröwis, Florian; Schmied, Roman; Gisin, Nicolas (2 July 2015). "Tighter quantum uncertainty relations following from a general probabilistic bound". Physical Review A. 92 (1): 012102. arXiv:1409.4440. Bibcode:2015PhRvA..92a2102F. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.92.012102. S2CID 58912643.
- ^ Maccone, Lorenzo; Pati, Arun K. (31 December 2014). "Stronger Uncertainty Relations for All Incompatible Observables". Physical Review Letters. 113 (26): 260401. arXiv:1407.0338. Bibcode:2014PhRvL.113z0401M. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.113.260401. PMID 25615288. S2CID 21334130.
- ^ Huang, Yichen (10 August 2012). "Variance-based uncertainty relations". Physical Review A. 86 (2): 024101. arXiv:1012.3105. Bibcode:2012PhRvA..86b4101H. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.86.024101. S2CID 118507388.
- ^ a b c d e f Busch, Paul (2002). "The Time-Energy Uncertainty Relation". In Muga, J. G.; Mayato, R. Sala; Egusquiza, I. L. (eds.). Time in Quantum Mechanics. Lecture Notes in Physics. Vol. 72. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 69–98. doi:10.1007/3-540-45846-8_3. ISBN 978-3-540-43294-4.
- ^ Wigner, E. P. (1997). "On the Time–Energy Uncertainty Relation". In Wightman, Arthur S. (ed.). Part I: Particles and Fields. Part II: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 538–548. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-09203-3_58. ISBN 978-3-642-08179-8.
- ^ a b Hilgevoord, Jan (1996-12-01). "The uncertainty principle for energy and time". American Journal of Physics. 64 (12): 1451–1456. Bibcode:1996AmJPh..64.1451H. doi:10.1119/1.18410. ISSN 0002-9505. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2023-11-12.
- ^ Lynch, F. J.; Holland, R. E.; Hamermesh, M. (1960-10-15). "Time Dependence of Resonantly Filtered Gamma Rays from Fe 57". Physical Review. 120 (2): 513–520. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.120.513. ISSN 0031-899X.
- ^ Frauenfelder, H. (1962). The Mössbauer Effect. W. A. Benjamin. p. 66. LCCN 61018181.
- ^ Bohm, Arno R.; Sato, Yoshihiro (2005-04-28). "Relativistic resonances: Their masses, widths, lifetimes, superposition, and causal evolution". Physical Review D. 71 (8): 085018. arXiv:hep-ph/0412106. Bibcode:2005PhRvD..71h5018B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.71.085018. ISSN 1550-7998. S2CID 119417992.
- ^ Karplus, Martin, and Porter, Richard Needham (1970). Atoms and Molecules. California: Benjamin Cummings. p. 68 ISBN 978-0805352184. OCLC 984466711
- ^ The broad linewidth of fast-decaying states makes it difficult to accurately measure the energy of the state, and researchers have even used detuned microwave cavities to slow down the decay rate, to get sharper peaks. Gabrielse, Gerald; H. Dehmelt (1985). "Observation of Inhibited Spontaneous Emission". Physical Review Letters. 55 (1): 67–70. Bibcode:1985PhRvL..55...67G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.55.67. PMID 10031682.
- ^ a b Hilgevoord, Jan (March 2005). "Time in quantum mechanics: a story of confusion". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 36 (1): 29–60. Bibcode:2005SHPMP..36...29H. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2004.10.002. Archived from the original on 2022-10-23. Retrieved 2024-01-28.
- ^ Bohm, Arno (January 2011). "Resonances/decaying states and the mathematics of quantum physics". Reports on Mathematical Physics. 67 (3): 279–303. Bibcode:2011RpMP...67..279B. doi:10.1016/S0034-4877(11)60018-9. Archived from the original on 2023-12-04. Retrieved 2024-01-24.
- ^ Aharonov, Y.; Bohm, D. (June 1, 1961). "Time in the Quantum Theory and the Uncertainty Relation for Time and Energy" (PDF). Physical Review. 122 (5): 1649–1658. Bibcode:1961PhRv..122.1649A. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.122.1649. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-01-09. Retrieved 2012-01-21.
- ^ L. I. Mandelstam, I. E. Tamm, The uncertainty relation between energy and time in nonrelativistic quantum mechanics Archived 2019-06-07 at the Wayback Machine, 1945.
- ^ Naber, Gregory L. (2021). Quantum Mechanics: An Introduction to the Physical Background and Mathematical Structure. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. p. 230. ISBN 978-3-11-075194-9. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2024-01-20.
- ^ Havin, V.; Jöricke, B. (1994), The Uncertainty Principle in Harmonic Analysis, Springer-Verlag
- ^ Folland, Gerald; Sitaram, Alladi (May 1997), "The Uncertainty Principle: A Mathematical Survey", Journal of Fourier Analysis and Applications, 3 (3): 207–238, Bibcode:1997JFAA....3..207F, doi:10.1007/BF02649110, MR 1448337, S2CID 121355943
- ^ Sitaram, A (2001) [1994], "Uncertainty principle, mathematical", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press
- ^ Mallat, S. G. (2009). A wavelet tour of signal processing: the sparse way. Amsterdam ; Boston: Elsevier/Academic Press. p. 44. doi:10.1016/B978-0-12-374370-1.X0001-8. ISBN 978-0-12-374370-1.
- ^ Donoho, D.L.; Stark, P.B (1989). "Uncertainty principles and signal recovery". SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics. 49 (3): 906–931. doi:10.1137/0149053.
- ^ Terence Tao (2005), "An uncertainty principle for cyclic groups of prime order", Mathematical Research Letters, 12 (1): 121–127, arXiv:math/0308286, doi:10.4310/MRL.2005.v12.n1.a11, S2CID 8548232
- ^ Amrein, W.O.; Berthier, A.M. (1977), "On support properties of Lp-functions and their Fourier transforms", Journal of Functional Analysis, 24 (3): 258–267, doi:10.1016/0022-1236(77)90056-8.
- ^ Benedicks, M. (1985), "On Fourier transforms of functions supported on sets of finite Lebesgue measure", J. Math. Anal. Appl., 106 (1): 180–183, doi:10.1016/0022-247X(85)90140-4
- ^ Nazarov, F. (1994), "Local estimates for exponential polynomials and their applications to inequalities of the uncertainty principle type", St. Petersburg Math. J., 5: 663–717
- ^ Jaming, Ph. (2007), "Nazarov's uncertainty principles in higher dimension", J. Approx. Theory, 149 (1): 30–41, arXiv:math/0612367, doi:10.1016/j.jat.2007.04.005, S2CID 9794547
- ^ Hardy, G.H. (1933), "A theorem concerning Fourier transforms", Journal of the London Mathematical Society, 8 (3): 227–231, doi:10.1112/jlms/s1-8.3.227
- ^ Hörmander, L. (1991), "A uniqueness theorem of Beurling for Fourier transform pairs", Ark. Mat., 29 (1–2): 231–240, Bibcode:1991ArM....29..237H, doi:10.1007/BF02384339, S2CID 121375111
- ^ Bonami, A.; Demange, B.; Jaming, Ph. (2003), "Hermite functions and uncertainty principles for the Fourier and the windowed Fourier transforms", Rev. Mat. Iberoamericana, 19: 23–55, arXiv:math/0102111, Bibcode:2001math......2111B, doi:10.4171/RMI/337, S2CID 1211391
- ^ Hedenmalm, Haakan (2012), "Heisenberg's uncertainty principle in the sense of Beurling", Journal d'Analyse Mathématique, 118 (2): 691–702, arXiv:1203.5222, Bibcode:2012arXiv1203.5222H, doi:10.1007/s11854-012-0048-9, S2CID 54533890
- ^ Demange, Bruno (2009), Uncertainty Principles Associated to Non-degenerate Quadratic Forms, Société Mathématique de France, ISBN 978-2-85629-297-6
- ^ Giovannetti, V.; Lloyd, S.; Maccone, L. (2011). "Advances in quantum metrology". Nature Photonics. 5 (4): 222. arXiv:1102.2318. Bibcode:2011NaPho...5..222G. doi:10.1038/nphoton.2011.35. S2CID 12591819.; arXiv Archived 2020-08-06 at the Wayback Machine
- ^ Luis, Alfredo (2017-03-13). "Breaking the weak Heisenberg limit". Physical Review A. 95 (3): 032113. arXiv:1607.07668. Bibcode:2017PhRvA..95c2113L. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.95.032113. ISSN 2469-9926. S2CID 55838380.
- ^ a b Ozawa, Masanao (2003), "Universally valid reformulation of the Heisenberg uncertainty principle on noise and disturbance in measurement", Physical Review A, 67 (4): 42105, arXiv:quant-ph/0207121, Bibcode:2003PhRvA..67d2105O, doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.67.042105, S2CID 42012188
- ^ Busch, P.; Lahti, P.; Werner, R. F. (2013). "Proof of Heisenberg's Error-Disturbance Relation". Physical Review Letters. 111 (16): 160405. arXiv:1306.1565. Bibcode:2013PhRvL.111p0405B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.111.160405. PMID 24182239. S2CID 24507489.
- ^ Busch, P.; Lahti, P.; Werner, R. F. (2014). "Heisenberg uncertainty for qubit measurements". Physical Review A. 89 (1): 012129. arXiv:1311.0837. Bibcode:2014PhRvA..89a2129B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.89.012129. S2CID 118383022.
- ^ a b Rozema, L. A.; Darabi, A.; Mahler, D. H.; Hayat, A.; Soudagar, Y.; Steinberg, A. M. (2012). "Violation of Heisenberg's Measurement–Disturbance Relationship by Weak Measurements". Physical Review Letters. 109 (10): 100404. arXiv:1208.0034v2. Bibcode:2012PhRvL.109j0404R. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.109.100404. PMID 23005268. S2CID 37576344.
- ^ Erhart, J.; Sponar, S.; Sulyok, G.; Badurek, G.; Ozawa, M.; Hasegawa, Y. (2012). "Experimental demonstration of a universally valid error-disturbance uncertainty relation in spin measurements". Nature Physics. 8 (3): 185–189. arXiv:1201.1833. Bibcode:2012NatPh...8..185E. doi:10.1038/nphys2194. S2CID 117270618.
- ^ Baek, S.-Y.; Kaneda, F.; Ozawa, M.; Edamatsu, K. (2013). "Experimental violation and reformulation of the Heisenberg's error-disturbance uncertainty relation". Scientific Reports. 3: 2221. Bibcode:2013NatSR...3.2221B. doi:10.1038/srep02221. PMC 3713528. PMID 23860715.
- ^ Ringbauer, M.; Biggerstaff, D.N.; Broome, M.A.; Fedrizzi, A.; Branciard, C.; White, A.G. (2014). "Experimental Joint Quantum Measurements with Minimum Uncertainty". Physical Review Letters. 112 (2): 020401. arXiv:1308.5688. Bibcode:2014PhRvL.112b0401R. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.112.020401. PMID 24483993. S2CID 18730255.
- ^ Björk, G.; Söderholm, J.; Trifonov, A.; Tsegaye, T.; Karlsson, A. (1999). "Complementarity and the uncertainty relations". Physical Review. A60 (3): 1878. arXiv:quant-ph/9904069. Bibcode:1999PhRvA..60.1874B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.60.1874. S2CID 27371899.
- ^ Fujikawa, Kazuo (2012). "Universally valid Heisenberg uncertainty relation". Physical Review A. 85 (6): 062117. arXiv:1205.1360. Bibcode:2012PhRvA..85f2117F. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.85.062117. S2CID 119640759.
- ^ Judge, D. (1964), "On the uncertainty relation for angle variables", Il Nuovo Cimento, 31 (2): 332–340, Bibcode:1964NCim...31..332J, doi:10.1007/BF02733639, S2CID 120553526
- ^ Bouten, M.; Maene, N.; Van Leuven, P. (1965), "On an uncertainty relation for angle variables", Il Nuovo Cimento, 37 (3): 1119–1125, Bibcode:1965NCim...37.1119B, doi:10.1007/BF02773197, S2CID 122838645
- ^ Louisell, W. H. (1963), "Amplitude and phase uncertainty relations", Physics Letters, 7 (1): 60–61, Bibcode:1963PhL.....7...60L, doi:10.1016/0031-9163(63)90442-6
- ^ DeWitt, B. S.; Graham, N. (1973), The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 52–53, ISBN 0-691-08126-3
- ^ Hirschman, I. I. Jr. (1957), "A note on entropy", American Journal of Mathematics, 79 (1): 152–156, doi:10.2307/2372390, JSTOR 2372390.
- ^ Beckner, W. (1975), "Inequalities in Fourier analysis", Annals of Mathematics, 102 (6): 159–182, doi:10.2307/1970980, JSTOR 1970980, PMC 432369, PMID 16592223.
- ^ Bialynicki-Birula, I.; Mycielski, J. (1975), "Uncertainty Relations for Information Entropy in Wave Mechanics", Communications in Mathematical Physics, 44 (2): 129–132, Bibcode:1975CMaPh..44..129B, doi:10.1007/BF01608825, S2CID 122277352, archived from the original on 2021-02-08, retrieved 2021-08-17
- ^ Huang, Yichen (24 May 2011). "Entropic uncertainty relations in multidimensional position and momentum spaces". Physical Review A. 83 (5): 052124. arXiv:1101.2944. Bibcode:2011PhRvA..83e2124H. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.83.052124. S2CID 119243096.
- ^ Chafaï, D. (2003), "Gaussian maximum of entropy and reversed log-Sobolev inequality", Séminaire de Probabilités XXXVI, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1801, pp. 194–200, arXiv:math/0102227, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-36107-7_5, ISBN 978-3-540-00072-3, S2CID 17795603
- ^ Chiew, Shao-Hen; Gessner, Manuel (31 January 2022). "Improving sum uncertainty relations with the quantum Fisher information". Physical Review Research. 4 (1): 013076. arXiv:2109.06900. Bibcode:2022PhRvR...4a3076C. doi:10.1103/PhysRevResearch.4.013076. S2CID 237513883.
- ^ Whittaker, Edmund T. (1989). A history of the theories of aether & electricity. Vol. II: The modern theories, 1900–1926 (Repr ed.). New York: Dover Publ. p. 267. ISBN 978-0-486-26126-3.
- ^ "This Month in Physics History". www.aps.org. Archived from the original on 2011-01-30. Retrieved 2023-11-04.
- ^ a b c Heisenberg, W. (1930), Physikalische Prinzipien der Quantentheorie (in German), Leipzig: Hirzel English translation The Physical Principles of Quantum Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1930.
- ^ Heisenberg, W., Die Physik der Atomkerne, Taylor & Francis, 1952, p. 30.
- ^ Cassidy, David; Saperstein, Alvin M. (2009), "Beyond Uncertainty: Heisenberg, Quantum Physics, and the Bomb", Physics Today, 63 (1), New York: Bellevue Literary Press: 185, Bibcode:2010PhT....63a..49C, doi:10.1063/1.3293416, archived from the original on Jan 4, 2024
- ^ Greenstein, George; Zajonc, Arthur (2006). The Quantum Challenge: Modern Research on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Jones & Bartlett Learning. ISBN 978-0-7637-2470-2.
- ^ Tipler, Paul A.; Llewellyn, Ralph A. (1999), Modern Physics, vol. 3, W.H. Freeman & Co., p. 3, ISBN 978-1572591646, LCCN 98046099
- ^ Furuta, Aya (2012), "One Thing Is Certain: Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle Is Not Dead", Scientific American, archived from the original on 2022-04-01, retrieved 2018-10-20
- ^ Wheeler, John Archibald (1978-01-01), Marlow, A. R. (ed.), "The 'Past' and the 'Delayed-Choice' Double-Slit Experiment", Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Theory, Academic Press, pp. 9–48, doi:10.1016/b978-0-12-473250-6.50006-6, ISBN 978-0-12-473250-6, archived from the original on 2022-12-10, retrieved 2023-07-19
- ^ Wheeler, John Archibald (1977), Lopes, José Leite; Paty, Michel (eds.), "Include the Observer in the Wave Function?", Quantum Mechanics, A Half Century Later: Papers of a Colloquium on Fifty Years of Quantum Mechanics, Held at the University Louis Pasteur, Strasbourg, May 2–4, 1974, Episteme, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 1–18, doi:10.1007/978-94-010-1196-9_1, ISBN 978-94-010-1196-9, archived from the original on 2024-02-23, retrieved 2023-07-19
- ^ Werner Heisenberg, The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory, p. 20
- ^ De Broglie, Louis (October 1923). "Waves and Quanta". Nature. 112 (2815): 540. Bibcode:1923Natur.112..540D. doi:10.1038/112540a0. ISSN 1476-4687. S2CID 186242764.
- ^ Indian Institute of Technology Madras, Professor V. Balakrishnan, Lecture 1 – Introduction to Quantum Physics; Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, National Programme of Technology Enhanced Learning on YouTube
- ^ Enz, Charles Paul; von Meyenn, Karl (1994). Writings on Physics and Philosophy by Wolfgang Pauli. Translated by Robert Schlapp. Springer-Verlag. p. 43. ISBN 3-540-56859-X. Archived from the original on 2020-08-19. Retrieved 2018-02-10.
- ^ Feynman lectures on Physics, vol 3, 2–2
- ^ a b Gamow, G., The great physicists from Galileo to Einstein, Courier Dover, 1988, p.260.
- ^ Kumar, M., Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the Great Debate About the Nature of Reality, Icon, 2009, p. 282.
- ^ Gamow, G., The great physicists from Galileo to Einstein, Courier Dover, 1988, pp. 260–261. [ISBN missing]
- ^ Kumar, M. (2009). Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the Great Debate About the Nature of Reality. Icon. p. 287.
- ^ Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. (1935-05-15). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777.
- ^ Kumar, Manjit (2011). Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the great debate about the nature of reality (1st paperback ed.). New York: Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-33988-8.
- ^ a b c Popper, Karl (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Hutchinson & Co.
- ^ Jarvie, Ian Charles; Milford, Karl; Miller, David W. (2006). Karl Popper: a centenary assessment. Vol. 3. Ashgate. ISBN 978-0-7546-5712-5.
- ^ Popper, Karl; Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker (1934). "Zur Kritik der Ungenauigkeitsrelationen" [Critique of the Uncertainty Relations]. Naturwissenschaften (in German). 22 (48): 807–808. Bibcode:1934NW.....22..807P. doi:10.1007/BF01496543. S2CID 40843068.
- ^ Popper, K. (1982). Quantum theory and the schism in Physics. Unwin Hyman. pp. 53–54.
- ^ Mehra, Jagdish; Rechenberg, Helmut (2001). The Historical Development of Quantum Theory. Springer. ISBN 978-0-387-95086-0.
- ^ Compton, A. H. (1931). "The Uncertainty Principle and Free Will". Science. 74 (1911): 172. Bibcode:1931Sci....74..172C. doi:10.1126/science.74.1911.172. PMID 17808216. S2CID 29126625.
- ^ Heisenberg, M. (2009). "Is free will an illusion?". Nature. 459 (7244): 164–165. Bibcode:2009Natur.459..164H. doi:10.1038/459164a. PMID 19444190. S2CID 4420023.
- ^ a b Davies, P. C. W. (2004). "Does quantum mechanics play a non-trivial role in life?". Biosystems. 78 (1–3): 69–79. Bibcode:2004BiSys..78...69D. doi:10.1016/j.biosystems.2004.07.001. PMID 15555759.
- ^ Hänggi, Esther; Wehner, Stephanie (2013). "A violation of the uncertainty principle implies a violation of the second law of thermodynamics". Nature Communications. 4: 1670. arXiv:1205.6894. Bibcode:2013NatCo...4.1670H. doi:10.1038/ncomms2665. PMID 23575674. S2CID 205316392.
- ^ Kemble, E. C. (1937). The Fundamental Principles of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, reprinted by Dover. p. 244.
- ^ Haag, R. (1996). Local Quantum Physics: Fields, Particles, Algebras. Berlin: Springer.[page needed][ISBN missing]
- ^ Peres, Asher; Terno, Daniel R. (2004-01-06). "Quantum information and relativity theory". Reviews of Modern Physics. 76 (1): 93–123 [111]. arXiv:quant-ph/0212023. Bibcode:2004RvMP...76...93P. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.76.93. ISSN 0034-6861. S2CID 7481797. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2024-01-25.
- ^ Elion, W. J.; Matters, M.; Geigenmüller, U.; Mooij, J. E. (1994). "Direct demonstration of Heisenberg's uncertainty principle in a superconductor". Nature. 371 (6498): 594–595. Bibcode:1994Natur.371..594E. doi:10.1038/371594a0. S2CID 4240085.
- ^ Smithey, D. T.; Beck, M.; Cooper, J.; Raymer, M. G. (1993). "Measurement of number–phase uncertainty relations of optical fields". Physical Review A. 48 (4): 3159–3167. Bibcode:1993PhRvA..48.3159S. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.48.3159. PMID 9909968.
- ^ Caves, Carlton (1981). "Quantum-mechanical noise in an interferometer". Physical Review D. 23 (8): 1693–1708. Bibcode:1981PhRvD..23.1693C. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.23.1693.