Jump to content

Relativism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Responses: I deleted the final entry under 'Responses'; it was a criticism of relativism rather than a response against a criticism, and moreover was logically invalid regardless.
m Reverted 1 edit by MRFissi (talk) to last revision by Kowal2701
 
(862 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Philosophical view rejecting objectivity}}
:''Compare [[moral relativism]], [[aesthetic relativism]], [[social constructionism]], [[cultural relativism]], and [[cognitive relativism]].''
{{for|the physics theory with a similar name|Theory of Relativity}}
{{For|the physics theory|Theory of relativity}}
{{Citation style|date=September 2009}}
{{Epistemology sidebar}}


''' Relativism''' is a family of [[philosophical]] views which deny claims to [[Objectivity (philosophy)|objectivity]] within a particular domain and assert that valuations in that domain are relative to the perspective of an observer or the context in which they are assessed.<ref>Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relativism/] "The label “relativism” has been attached to a wide range of ideas and positions which may explain the lack of consensus on how the term should be defined."</ref> There are many different forms of relativism, with a great deal of variation in scope and differing degrees of controversy among them.<ref>[[Maria Baghramian]] identifies 16 (''Relativism'', 2004, Baghramian)</ref> ''[[Moral relativism]]'' encompasses the differences in moral judgments among people and cultures.<ref name=stanford>{{Cite web | last = Swoyer | first = Chris | date = February 22, 2003 | title = Relativism | url = http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relativism/#1.2 | access-date = May 10, 2010}}</ref> ''[[Epistemology#Epistemic relativism|Epistemic relativism]]'' holds that there are no absolute principles regarding normative [[belief]], [[Justification (epistemology)|justification]], or [[rationality]], and that there are only relative ones.<ref name="SEP Epistemic Relativism">{{cite web |title=Epistemic Relativism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relativism/#EpiRel |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=6 July 2020}}</ref> ''[[Factual relativism|Alethic relativism]]'' (also factual relativism) is the doctrine that there are no [[Universality (philosophy)|absolute truths]], i.e., that truth is always relative to some particular frame of reference, such as a language or a culture ([[cultural relativism]]), while [[Linguistic relativity|linguistic relativism]] asserts that a language's structures influence a speaker's perceptions.<ref name=":0">{{Cite book |last=Ahearn |first=Laura M. |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/729731177 |title=Living language : an introduction to linguistic anthropology |year=2012 |isbn=978-1-4443-4056-3 |location=Chichester, West Sussex, U.K. |pages=69 |oclc=729731177}}</ref><ref>Baghramian, Maria and Carter, Adam, "Relativism", "The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition)", Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/relativism/#RelAboTruAleRel/ "Relativism about truth, or alethic relativism, at its simplest, is the claim that what is true for one individual or social group may not be true for another"</ref> Some forms of relativism also bear a resemblance to [[philosophical skepticism]].<ref>{{Cite book|chapter-url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relativism/#BriHisOldIde|title = The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|chapter = Relativism|year = 2021|publisher = Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University}}</ref> ''Descriptive relativism'' seeks to describe the differences among cultures and people without evaluation, while normative relativism evaluates the word truthfulness of views within a given framework.
{{Cleanup|date=September 2006}}


==Forms of relativism==
'''Relativism''' is the idea that some element or aspect of [[experience]] or [[culture]] is relative to, i.e., dependent on, some other element or aspect. Some relativists claim that humans can understand and evaluate beliefs and behaviors only in terms of their [[history|historical]] or [[culture|cultural]] context. The term often refers to ''[[truth]] relativism'', which is the doctrine that there are no [[Universality (philosophy)|absolute truth]]s, i.e., that truth is always relative to some particular frame of reference, such as a language or a culture.

One argument for relativism suggests that our own [[cognitive bias]] prevents us from observing something objectively with our own senses, and [[notational bias]] will apply to whatever we can allegedly measure without using our senses. In addition, we have a [[culture bias]] — shared with other trusted observers — which we cannot eliminate. A counterargument to this states that [[subjective]] certainty and concrete objects and causes form part of our everyday life, and that there is no great value in discarding such useful ideas as [[Isomorphism (sociology)|isomorphism]], [[Objectivity (philosophy)|objectivity]] and a final [[truth]]. (For more information on the "usefulness" of ideas, see [[Pragmatism]].)

Relativism does not say that all points of view are equally valid, in contrast to an [[Moral absolutism|absolutism]] which argues there is but one true and correct view. In fact, relativism asserts that a particular instance Y exists only in relation to and as a manifestation of a particular [[framework]] or [[viewpoint]] X, and that no framework or standpoint is uniquely privileged over all others. That is, a non-universal trait Y (e.g., a particular [[practice]], [[behavior]], [[custom]], [[convention]], [[concept]], [[belief]], [[perception]], [[ethics]], [[truth]], or [[conceptual framework]]) is a [[dependent variable]] influenced by the [[independent variable]] X (e.g., a particular [[language]], [[culture]], [[historical epoch]], [[a priori]] [[cognitive architecture]], [[scientific frameworks]], [[gender]], [[ethnicity]], [[status]], [[individuality]]). Notably, this is not an argument that all instances of a certain kind of framework (say, all [[languages]]) do not share certain basic universal commonalities (say, [[grammatical structure]] and [[vocabulary]]) that essentially define that kind of framework and distinguish it from other frameworks (for example, linguists have criteria that define language and distinguish it from the mere [[communication]] of other animals). Moreover, relativism also presupposes philosophical [[realism]] in that there are actual objective things in the world that are relative to other real things. Moreover, relativism also assumes [[causality]], as well as a problematic web of relationships between various independent variables and the particular dependent variables that they influence.

==Forms of relativism and advocates of relativism==
===Anthropological versus philosophical relativism===
===Anthropological versus philosophical relativism===
[[Anthropological relativism]] refers to a [[methodology|methodological]] stance, in which the researcher suspends (or brackets) his or her own cultural biases while attempting to understand beliefs and behaviors in their local contexts. This has become known as [[methodological relativism]], and concerns itself specifically with avoiding [[ethnocentrism]] or the application of one's own cultural standards to the assessment of other cultures.<ref>[http://physicsworld.com/cws/article/print/1607 physicsworld.com]</ref> This is also the basis of the so-called "[[emic]]" and "[[etic]]" distinction, in which:
[[Anthropological relativism]] refers to a [[methodology|methodological]] stance, in which the researcher suspends (or brackets) their own cultural prejudice while trying to understand beliefs or behaviors in their contexts. This has become known as [[methodological relativism]], and concerns itself specifically with avoiding [[ethnocentrism]] or the application of one's own cultural standards to the assessment of other cultures.<ref>{{Cite news
|first=Harry

|last=Collins
*An '''emic''' or insider account of behavior is a description of a society in terms that are meaningful to the participant or actor's own culture; an emic account is therefore culture-specific, and typically refers to what is considered "[[common sense]]" within the culture under observation.
|author-link=Harry Collins
*An '''etic''' or outsider account is a description of a society by an observer, in terms that can be applied to other cultures; that is, an etic account is culturally neutral, and typically refers to the conceptual framework of the social scientist. (This is complicated when it is scientific research itself that is under study, or when there is theoretical or terminological disagreement within the social sciences.)
|title=What's wrong with relativism?
|url=http://physicsworld.com/cws/article/print/1607
|work=[[Physics World]]
|publisher=IOP Publishing
|location=[[Bristol, UK]]
|date=1998-04-01
|access-date=2008-04-16
|quote=...methodological relativism - impartial assessment of how knowledge develops - is the key idea for sociology of scientific knowledge...}}</ref> This is also the basis of the so-called "[[emic]]" and "[[etic]]" distinction, in which:
* An ''emic'' or ''insider'' account of behavior is a description of a society in terms that are meaningful to the participant or actor's own culture; an emic account is therefore culture-specific, and typically refers to what is considered "[[common sense]]" within the culture under observation.
* An ''etic'' or outsider account is a description of a society by an observer, in terms that can be applied to other cultures; that is, an etic account is culturally neutral, and typically refers to the conceptual framework of the social scientist. (This is complicated when it is scientific research itself that is under study, or when there is theoretical or terminological disagreement within the social sciences.)


[[Philosophical relativism]], in contrast, is simply an anti-dogmatic position that asserts that the truth of a proposition depends on who interprets it because no moral or cultural consensus can or will be reached.<ref>[http://books.google.com/books?id=oyloiiq0CYIC&pg=PA210&lpg=PA210&dq=methodological+and+philosophical+relativism&source=web&ots=WxK_nq52tb&sig=51Ff7uRU_CkJ9q8vVLilPJ5Jx7s Locke, Shaftesbury, and Hutcheson: Contesting Diversity in the Enlightenment and Beyond by Dr. Daniel Carey]</ref>
Philosophical relativism, in contrast, asserts that the truth of a proposition depends on the metaphysical, or theoretical frame, or the instrumental method, or the context in which the proposition is expressed, or on the person, groups, or culture who interpret the proposition.<ref>{{cite book| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=U5lKIVkSPtcC| title = Locke, Shaftesbury, and Hutcheson: Contesting Diversity in the Enlightenment and Beyond|first1=Daniel|last1=Carey|year=2005|location=Cambridge|publisher=Cambridge University Press| isbn = 9781139447904}}</ref>


Methodological relativism and philosophical relativism can exist independently from one another, or one can be based on the other.<ref>[http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0025-1496(196609)2%3A1%3A3%3C368%3AMAPR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-4 Methodological and Philosophical Relativism by Gananath Obeyesekere]</ref>
Methodological relativism and philosophical relativism can exist independently from one another, but most anthropologists base their methodological relativism on that of the philosophical variety.<ref>{{cite web| url = https://www.jstor.org/stable/2796798| title = Methodological and Philosophical Relativism by Gananath Obeyesekere| jstor = 2796798}}</ref>


===Descriptive versus normative relativism===
===Descriptive versus normative relativism===
The concept of relativism also has importance both for [[philosophy|philosophers]] and for [[anthropology|anthropologists]] in another way. In general, anthropologists engage in [[descriptive relativism]], whereas philosophers engage in [[normative relativism]], although there is some overlap (for example, descriptive relativism can pertain to concepts, normative relativism to truth).
The concept of relativism also has importance both for [[philosophy|philosophers]] and for [[anthropology|anthropologists]] in another way. In general, anthropologists engage in descriptive relativism ("how things are" or "how things seem"), whereas philosophers engage in [[Norm (philosophy)|normative]] relativism ("how things ought to be"), although there is some overlap (for example, descriptive relativism can pertain to concepts, normative relativism to truth).


'''Descriptive relativism''' assumes that certain cultural groups have different modes of thought, standards of reasoning, and so forth, and it is the anthropologist's task to describe, but not to evaluate the validity of these principles and practices of a cultural group. It is possible for an anthropologist in his or her fieldwork to be a descriptive relativist about some things that typically concern the philosopher (e.g., ethical principles) but not about others (e.g., logical principles). However, the descriptive relativist's empirical claims about epistemic principles, moral ideals and the like are often countered by anthropological arguments that such things are universal, and much of the recent literature on these matters is explicitly concerned with the extent of, and evidence for, cultural or moral or linguistic or human universals (see Brown, 1991 for a good discussion).
Descriptive relativism assumes that certain cultural groups have different modes of thought, standards of reasoning, and so forth, and it is the anthropologist's task to describe, but not to evaluate the validity of these principles and practices of a cultural group. It is possible for an anthropologist in his or her fieldwork to be a descriptive relativist about some things that typically concern the philosopher (e.g., ethical principles) but not about others (e.g., logical principles). However, the descriptive relativist's empirical claims about epistemic principles, moral ideals and the like are often countered by anthropological arguments that such things are universal, and much of the recent literature on these matters is explicitly concerned with the extent of, and evidence for, cultural or moral or linguistic or human universals.<ref>{{Cite book |first = Donald E. |last = Brown |author-link = Donald Brown (anthropologist) |title = Human Universals |publisher = [[McGraw-Hill]] |year = 1991 |isbn = 0-87722-841-8 |url-access = registration |url = https://archive.org/details/culturalconnecti00voge }}</ref>


The fact that the various species of descriptive relativism are empirical claims may tempt the philosopher to conclude that they are of little philosophical interest, but there are several reasons why this isn't so. First, some philosophers, notably Kant, argue that certain sorts of cognitive differences between human beings (or even all rational beings) are impossible, so such differences could never be found to obtain in fact, an argument that places a priori limits on what empirical inquiry could discover and on what versions of descriptive relativism could be true. Second, claims about actual differences between groups play a central role in some arguments for normative relativism (for example, arguments for normative ethical relativism often begin with claims that different groups in fact have different moral codes or ideals). Finally, the anthropologist's descriptive account of relativism helps to separate the fixed aspects of human nature from those that can vary, and so a descriptive claim that some important aspect of experience or thought does (or does not) vary across groups of human beings tells us something important about human nature and the human condition.
The fact that the various species of descriptive relativism are empirical claims may tempt the philosopher to conclude that they are of little philosophical interest, but there are several reasons why this is not so. First, some philosophers, notably Kant, argue that certain sorts of cognitive differences between human beings (or even all rational beings) are impossible, so such differences could never be found to obtain in fact, an argument that places a priori limits on what empirical inquiry could discover and on what versions of descriptive relativism could be true. Second, claims about actual differences between groups play a central role in some arguments for normative relativism (for example, arguments for normative ethical relativism often begin with claims that different groups in fact have different moral codes or ideals). Finally, the anthropologist's descriptive account of relativism helps to separate the fixed aspects of human nature from those that can vary, and so a descriptive claim that some important aspect of experience or thought does (or does not) vary across groups of human beings tells us something important about human nature and the human condition.


'''Normative relativism''' concerns normative or evaluative claims that modes of thought, standards of reasoning, or the like are only right or wrong relative to a framework. ‘Normative’ is meant in a general sense, applying to a wide range of views; in the case of beliefs, for example, normative correctness equals truth. This does not mean, of course, that framework-relative correctness or truth is always clear, the first challenge being to explain what it amounts to in any given case (e.g., with respect to concepts, truth, epistemic norms). Normative relativism (say, in regard to normative ethical relativism) therefore implies that things (say, ethical claims) are not simply true in themselves, but only have truth values relative to broader frameworks (say, moral codes). (Many normative ethical relativist arguments run from premises about ethics to conclusions that assert the relativity of truth values, bypassing general claims about the nature of truth, but it is often more illuminating to consider the type of relativism under question directly.)<ref>[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relativism/#1.2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]</ref>
Normative relativism concerns normative or [[Value (ethics)|evaluative]] claims that modes of thought, standards of reasoning, or the like are only right or wrong relative to a framework. 'Normative' is meant in a general sense, applying to a wide range of views; in the case of beliefs, for example, normative correctness equals truth. This does not mean, of course, that framework-relative correctness or truth is always clear, the first challenge being to explain what it amounts to in any given case (e.g., with respect to concepts, truth, epistemic norms). Normative relativism (say, in regard to normative ethical relativism) therefore implies that things (say, ethical claims) are not simply true in themselves, but only have [[truth value]]s relative to broader frameworks (say, moral codes). (Many normative ethical relativist arguments run from premises about ethics to conclusions that assert the relativity of truth values, bypassing general claims about the nature of truth, but it is often more illuminating to consider the type of relativism under question directly.)<ref>{{cite book| chapter-url = http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relativism/#1.2| title = Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy| chapter = Relativism| year = 2022| publisher = Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University}}</ref>


=== Indian religions ===
===Legal relativism===
In English [[common law]], two (perhaps three) separate standards of proof are recognized:
[[Indian religions]] tend to be naturally relativistic. [[Mahavira]] (599-527 BC), the 24th [[Tirthankara]] of [[Jainism]], developed an early philosophy regarding relativism and [[subjectivism]] known as [[Anekantavada]]. [[Hinduism|Hindu religion]] has no theological difficulties in accepting degrees of truth in other religions. A [[Rig Veda|Rig Vedic]] hymn states that "Truth is One, though the sages know it variously." (Ékam sat vipra bahudā vadanti)
* proof based on the [[Burden of proof (law)#Preponderance of the evidence|balance of probabilities]] is the lesser standard used in [[Civil law (common law)|civil litigation]], which cases mostly concern money or some other penalty, that, if further and better evidence should emerge, is reasonably reversible.
* proof [[reasonable doubt|beyond reasonable doubt]] is used in [[criminal law]] cases where an accused's right to [[personal freedom]] or [[survival]] is in question, because such [[punishment]] is not reasonably reversible.
* Absolute truth is so complex as to be only capable of being fully understood by the [[Omniscience|omniscient]] established during the [[Tudor period]] as the one true [[God in Christianity|God]] <ref>[https://www.lawyersnjurists.com/article/reasonable-doubt-v-balance-of-probability/Lawyers & Jurists website: Reasonable doubt v balance of probability]</ref>


==Related and contrasting positions==
The [[Sikh Gurus]] (spiritual teacher ) have propagated the message of "many paths" leading to the [[Ek Onkar|one God]] and ultimate [[salvation]] for all souls who tread on the path of [[righteousness]]. They have supported the view that proponents of all faiths can, by doing good and virtuous deeds and by remembering the [[Lord]], certainly achieve salvation. The students of the Sikh faith are told to accept all leading faiths as possible vehicle for attaining spiritual enlightenment provided the faithful study, ponder and practice the teachings of their prophets and leaders. The holy book of the [[Sikh]]s called the [[Sri Guru Granth Sahib]] says: "Do not say that the Vedas, the Bible and the Koran are false. Those who do not contemplate them are false." [[Guru Granth Sahib]] page 1350.<ref>[http://www.srigranth.org/servlet/gurbani.gurbani?Action=Page&Param=1350&english=t&id=57718 Guru Granth Sahib page 1350]</ref> and "The seconds, minutes, and hours, days, weeks and months, and the various seasons originate from the one Sun; O nanak, in just the same way, the many forms originate from the Creator." [[Guru Granth Sahib]] page 12,13.
[[Relational theory|Relationism]] is the theory that there are only relations between individual entities, and no intrinsic
properties. Despite the similarity in name, it is held by some to be a position distinct from relativism—for instance, because "statements about relational properties [...] assert an absolute truth about things in the world".<ref>[[Maria Baghramian|Baghramian, M.]] ''Relativism'', 2004, p43</ref>
On the other hand, others wish to equate relativism, relationism and even [[Theory of relativity|relativity]], which is a precise theory of relationships between physical objects:<ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.nakedpunch.com/6/106-108.pdf| title = Interview with Bruno Latour''On Relativism, Pragmatism, and Critical Theory''}}</ref> Nevertheless, "This confluence of relativity theory with relativism became a strong contributing factor in the increasing prominence of relativism".<ref>Baghramian, M. ''Relativism'', 2004, p85</ref>


Whereas previous investigations of science only sought sociological or psychological explanations of failed scientific theories or pathological science, the '[[strong programme]]' is more relativistic, assessing scientific truth and falsehood equally in a historic and cultural context.
Ethnocentrism of any sort (including the idea of belonging to a 'school of Buddhism' as well as evangelism and religious supremacism) is, according to Buddhist thought, rooted in self-grasping and reified thought - the cause of [[Samsara]] itself. The current [[Dalai Lama]] has repeatedly pointed out that any attempt to convert individuals from their beliefs is not only non-Buddhist, but abusive: the identification of evangelism as an expression of compassion is considered to be false, and indeed the idea that Buddhism is the ''one true path'' is likewise false for Buddhists.


===Sophists===
==Criticisms==
{{anchor|paradox_of_relativism}}A common argument<ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.asa3.org/ASA/education/views/reality.htm| title = Craig Rusbult. ''Reality 101''}}</ref><ref>Keith Dixon. ''Is Cultural Relativism Self-Refuting''? (British Journal of Sociology, vol 28, No. 1)</ref><ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.allaboutphilosophy.org/cultural-relativism.htm| title = ''Cultural Relativism'' at All About Philosophy.}}</ref> against relativism suggests that it inherently [[self-refuting idea|refutes itself]]: the statement "all is relative" classes either as a relative statement or as an absolute one. If it is relative, then this statement does not rule out absolutes. If the statement is [[wikt:absolute|absolute]], on the other hand, then it provides an example of an absolute statement, proving that not all truths are relative. However, this argument against relativism only applies to relativism that positions truth as relative–i.e. epistemological/truth-value relativism. More specifically, it is only extreme forms of epistemological relativism that can come in for this criticism as there are many epistemological relativists{{Who|date=July 2015}} who posit that some aspects of what is regarded as factually "true" are not universal, yet still accept that other universal truths exist (e.g. [[gas laws]] or moral laws).
[[Sophists]] are considered the founding fathers of relativism in the [[Western World]]. Elements of relativism emerged among the [[Sophist]]s in the 5th century [[Before Christ|BC]]. Notably, it was [[Protagoras]] who coined the phrase, "Man (i.e. a human being) is the measure of all things: of things which are, that they are, and of things which are not, that they are not." The thinking of the Sophists is mainly known through their opponents, [[Plato]] and [[Socrates]].


Another argument against relativism posits the existence of [[Natural Law|natural law]]. Simply put, the physical universe works under basic principles: the "Laws of Nature". Some contend that a natural moral law may also exist, for example as argued by, [[Immanuel Kant]] in ''[[Critique of Practical Reason]]'', [[Richard Dawkins]] in ''[[The God Delusion]]'' (2006)<ref>[[The God Delusion]], Chapter 6</ref> and addressed by [[C. S. Lewis]] in ''[[Mere Christianity]]'' (1952).<ref>Mere Christianity, Chapter 1</ref> Dawkins said "I think we face an equal but much more sinister challenge from the left, in the shape of cultural relativism - the view that scientific truth is only one kind of truth and it is not to be especially privileged".<ref>{{cite web| url = https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2007/may/28/dawkinschristmascardlist| title = Richard Dawkins quoted in ''Dawkins' Christmas card list; Dawkins at the Hay Festival,'' The Guardian, 28 May 2007| website = [[TheGuardian.com]]| date = 28 May 2007}}</ref>
===Bernard Crick===
<!-- Forced to exclude this too - it hangs. --><!--[[Plato]] opposed relativism. He criticized the views of the [[sophist]] [[Protagoras]] in his dialogue ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Thaetetus]]''. In a paraphrased dialogue, the philosopher [[Socrates]] argued that relativism is self-defeating with the following: "My opinion is: Truth must be absolute and that you Mr. Protagoras, are absolutely in error. Since this is indeed my opinion, then you must concede that it is true according to your philosophy."<ref name=socratesdialogue/>
Another important advocate of relativism, [[Bernard Crick]], a British political scientist, wrote the book ''In Defence of Politics'' (first published in 1962), suggesting the inevitability of moral conflict between people. Crick stated that only [[ethics]] could resolve such conflict, and when that occurred in public it resulted in [[politics]]. Accordingly, Crick saw the process of [[dispute resolution]], [[harms reduction]], [[mediation]] or [[peacemaking]] as central to all of moral philosophy. He became an important influence on the [[feminists]] and later on the [[Green movement|Greens]].
must be absolute and that you Mr. Protagoras, are absolutely in error. Since this is indeed my opinion, then you must concede that it is true according to your philosophy."<ref name=socratesdialogue/>--><!-- Quite a mess. (Plato could be o'k, but 1) make it chronologically, 2) make it clear.) --><!-- "In Defense of Relativity." claims that Protagoras had but to respond, “but my view says that truth is relative to viewpoint, thus you have demonstrated by your very viewpoint that truth is relative,” and thus demonstrated the “truth” that truth is relative." It goes further to state that "Socrates declared that (from his view), Protagoras' idea of relative truth is wrong, thus it is wrong relative to Socrates' view. Protagoras merely needed to respond that from his view, truth is relative to viewpoint, his statement is therefore true from his viewpoint and false from Socrates' viewpoint, denoting the relative truths found in their respective relative views, and thus demonstrating the relative truth of Protagoras..." --> <!-- See above. --> <!-- Would you mind not corrupting other text next time? Etc. -->
Philosopher [[Hilary Putnam]],<ref>[[Maria Baghramian|Baghramian, M.]] ''Relativism'', 2004</ref> among others,<ref>Including Julien Beillard, who presents his case on the impossibility of moral relativism in the July 2013 issue of [[Philosophy Now|Philosophy Now magazine]], accessible [http://philosophynow.org/issues/97/Moral_Relativism_Is_Unintelligible here]</ref> states that some forms of relativism make it impossible to believe one is in error. If there is no truth beyond an individual's [[belief]] that something is true, then an individual cannot hold their own beliefs to be false or mistaken. A related criticism is that relativizing truth to individuals destroys the distinction between truth and belief.


==Views==
===Paul Feyerabend===
===Philosophical===
The philosopher-of-science [[Paul Feyerabend]] wholeheartedly embraced relativism, and even "epistemological anarchy".<ref>[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feyerabend/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Paul Feyerabend]</ref>
====Ancient====


=====Sophism=====
:"All methodologies have their limitations and the only rule that survives is 'anything goes'"<ref>Feyerabend, P. ''Against Method'', p. 296</ref>
[[Sophists]] are considered the founding fathers of relativism in [[Western philosophy]]. Elements of relativism emerged among the [[Sophist]]s in the 5th century [[Before Christ|BC]]. Notably, it was [[Protagoras]] who coined the phrase, "Man is the measure of all things: of things which are, that they are, and of things which are not, that they are not." The thinking of the Sophists is mainly known through their opponent, [[Plato]]. In a paraphrase from Plato's dialogue ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'', Protagoras said: "What is true for you is true for you, and what is true for me is true for me."<ref name=socratesdialogue>
{{cite book | title=Scientific Inquiry: Applied to the Doctrine of Jesus Christ | author=Richard Austin Gudmundsen | page = 50 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3C-ZdOSwRJcC&q=Protagoras+%22what+is+true+for+you%22&pg=PA50
|year=2000 |publisher=Cedar Fort | access-date=2011-01-24 |isbn=978-1-55517-497-2}}
</ref><ref>
{{Cite book
| publisher = Barnes & Noble Publishing
| isbn = 978-1-56619-271-2
| last = Sahakian
| first = William S.
|author2=Mabel Lewis Sahakian
| title = Ideas of the great philosophers
| page = 28
| year = 1993
| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=Vi7cQMw8SwYC&q=Protagoras+Plato+%22what+is+true+for+you%22&pg=PA28
| quote = What is true for you is true for you.
}}</ref><ref>
{{Cite book
| publisher = Schenkman Pub. Co.
| last = Sahakian
| first = W. S.
|author2=M. L. Sahakian
| title = Realms of philosophy
| year = 1965
|page = 40
| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=6FEYAAAAIAAJ
| access-date = 2011-01-24
}}</ref>


====Modern====
Or, in a more conciliatory mood:
=====Bernard Crick=====
[[Bernard Crick]], a British political scientist and advocate of relativism, suggested in ''In Defence of Politics'' (1962) that moral conflict between people is inevitable. He thought that only [[ethics]] can resolve such conflict, and when that occurs in public it results in [[politics]]. Accordingly, Crick saw the process of [[dispute resolution]], [[harms reduction]], [[mediation]] or [[peacemaking]] as central to all of moral philosophy. He became an important influence on [[feminists]] and later on the [[Green movement|Greens]].


=====Paul Feyerabend=====
:"I argue that all rules have their limits, and there is no comprehensive 'rationality', I do not argue that we should proceed without rules and standards"<ref>Feyerabend, P. ''Against Method'' p. 231</ref>
Philosopher of science [[Paul Feyerabend]] is often considered to be a relativist, although he denied being one.<ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.timeshighereducation.co.uk/story.asp?storyCode=156973&sectioncode=39| title = Cooper, David E., "Voodoo and the monster of science", ''Times Higher Education'', 17 March 2000| date = 17 March 2000}}</ref>


Feyerabend argued that modern science suffers from being methodologically monistic (the belief that only a single methodology can produce [[scientific progress]]).<ref>Lloyd, Elisabeth. "Feyerabend, Mill, and Pluralism", ''Philosophy of Science'' 64, p. S397.</ref> Feyerabend summarises his case in ''[[Against Method]]'' with the phrase "anything goes".<ref>Feyerabend, ''Against Method'', 3rd ed., p. vii</ref>
===Thomas Kuhn===
[[Thomas Samuel Kuhn|Thomas Kuhn]]'s philosophy of science, as expressed in ''[[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]]'' is often seen as relativistic (and enthusiastically proclaimed as such within the humanities). He claimed that as well as progressing steadily and incrementally ("[[normal science]]"), science undergoes periodic revolutions or "[[paradigm shift]]s", leaving scientists working in different paradigms with difficulty in even communicating.


:In an aphorism [Feyerabend] often repeated, "potentially every culture is all cultures". This is intended to convey that world views are not hermetically closed, since their leading concepts have an "ambiguity" - better, an open-endedness - which enables people from other cultures to engage with them. [...] It follows that relativism, understood as the doctrine that truth is relative to closed systems, can get no purchase. [...] For Feyerabend, both hermetic relativism and its absolutist rival [realism] serve, in their different ways, to "devalue human existence". The former encourages that unsavoury brand of political correctness which takes the refusal to criticise "other cultures" to the extreme of condoning murderous dictatorship and barbaric practices. The latter, especially in its favoured contemporary form of "scientific realism", with the excessive prestige it affords to the abstractions of "the monster 'science'", is in bed with a politics which likewise disdains variety, richness and everyday individuality - a politics which likewise "hides" its norms behind allegedly neutral facts, "blunts choices and imposes laws".<ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.timeshighereducation.co.uk/story.asp?storyCode=156973&sectioncode=39| title = Cooper, David E., "Voodoo and the monster of science," ''Times Higher Education'', 17 March 2000| date = 17 March 2000}}</ref>
:"the third and most fundamental aspect of the incommensurability of competing paradigms: this is a sense that I am unable to explicate further, [in which] the proponents of competing paradigms practice their trades in different worlds. One contains constrained bodies that fall slowly, the other pendulums that repeat their motions again and again. In one, solutions are compounds, in the other mixtures. One is embedded in a flat, the other in a curved, matrix of space. Practicing in two different worlds, the two groups of scientists see different things when they look from the same point in the same direction. Again, that is not to say that they can see anything they please. Both are looking at the world, and what they look at has not changed. However in some areas they see different things and they see them in different relations one to the other. That is why a law that cannot even be demonstrated to one group of scientists may occasionally seem intuitively obvious to another. Equally, it is why, before they can hope to communicate fully, one group or the other must experience the conversion that we have been calling a paradigm shift."<ref>Kuhn, S. ''Structure of Scientific Revolutions'', p. 158</ref>


=====Thomas Kuhn=====
Thus the truth of a claim, or the existence of a posited entity is relative to the paradigm employed. However, he was reluctant to fully embrace relativism.
[[Thomas Samuel Kuhn|Thomas Kuhn]]'s philosophy of science, as expressed in ''[[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]]'', is often interpreted as relativistic. He claimed that, as well as progressing steadily and incrementally ("[[normal science]]"), science undergoes periodic revolutions or "[[paradigm shift]]s", leaving scientists working in different paradigms with difficulty in even communicating. Thus the truth of a claim, or the existence of a posited entity, is relative to the paradigm employed. However, it is not necessary for him to embrace relativism because every paradigm presupposes the prior, building upon itself through history and so on. This leads to there being a fundamental, incremental, and referential structure of development which is not relative but again, fundamental.


:From these remarks, one thing is however certain: Kuhn is not saying that incommensurable theories cannot be compared - what they can’t be is compared in terms of a system of common measure. He very plainly says that they can be compared, and he reiterates this repeatedly in later work, in a (mostly in vain) effort to avert the crude and sometimes catastrophic misinterpretations he suffered from mainstream philosophers and post-modern relativists alike.<ref>[http://www.uea.ac.uk/~j339/Kuhntogo.htm Sharrock. W., Read R. ''Kuhn: Philosopher of Scientific Revolutions'']</ref>
:From these remarks, one thing is however certain: Kuhn is not saying that incommensurable theories cannot be compared - what they can't be is compared in terms of a system of common measure. He very plainly says that they can be compared, and he reiterates this repeatedly in later work, in a (mostly in vain) effort to avert the crude and sometimes catastrophic misinterpretations he suffered from mainstream philosophers and post-modern relativists alike.<ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.uea.ac.uk/~j339/Kuhntogo.htm| title = Sharrock. W., Read R. ''Kuhn: Philosopher of Scientific Revolutions''}}</ref>


But Kuhn rejected the accusation of being a relativist later in his postscript:
===George Lakoff and Mark Johnson===
[[George Lakoff]] and [[Mark Johnson]] define relativism in their book ''[[Metaphors We Live By]]'' as the rejection of both [[subject (philosophy)|subjectivism]] and [[objectivism|metaphysical objectivism]] in order to focus on the relationship between them, i.e. the [[metaphors|metaphor]] by which we relate our current experience to our previous experience. In particular, Lakoff and Johnson characterize "objectivism" as a "[[straw man]]", and, to a lesser degree, criticize the views of [[Karl Popper]], [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] and [[Aristotle]].


:scientific development is ... a unidirectional and irreversible process. Later scientific theories are better than earlier ones for solving puzzles ... That is not a relativist's position, and it displays the sense in which I am a convinced believer in scientific progress.<ref>Kuhn, ''[[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]]'', p. 206.</ref>
===Robert Nozick===
In his book ''[[Invariances]]'', [[Robert Nozick]] expresses a complex set of theories about the absolute and the relative. He thinks the absolute/relative distinction should be recast in terms of a variant/invariant distinction, where there are many things a proposition can vary with, or be invariant with regard to. He thinks it is coherent for truth to be relative, and speculates that it might vary with time. He thinks necessity is an unobtainable notion, but can be approximated by robust invariance across a variety of conditions &mdash; although we can never identify a proposition that is invariant with regard to everything. Finally, he is not particularly warm to the most (in)famous form of relativism, [[moral relativism]], preferring an evolutionary account.


Some have argued that one can also read Kuhn's work as essentially positivist in its ontology: the revolutions he posits are epistemological, lurching toward a presumably 'better' understanding of an objective reality through the lens presented by the new paradigm. However, a number of passages in ''Structure'' do indeed appear to be distinctly relativist, and to directly challenge the notion of an objective reality and the ability of science to progress towards an ever-greater grasp of it, particularly through the process of paradigm change.
===Joseph Margolis===
[[Joseph Margolis]] advocates a view he calls "robust relativism" and defends it in his books: ''Historied Thought, Constructed World'', Chapter 4 (California, 1995) and ''The Truth about Relativism'' (Blackwells, 1991). He opens his account by stating that our logics should depend on what we take to be the nature of the sphere to which we wish to apply our logics. Holding that there can be no distinctions which are not "privileged" between the [[alethic]], the [[ontic]], and the [[epistemic]], he maintains that a [[many valued logic]] just might be the most apt for [[aesthetics]] or [[history]] since, because in these practices, we are loath to hold to simple [[binary logic]]; and he also holds that many-valued logic is relativistic. (This is perhaps an unusual definition of "relativistic". Compare with his comments on "relationism"). "True" and "False" as mutually exclusive and exhaustive judgements on [[Hamlet]], for instance, really does seem absurd. A many valued logic — "apt", "reasonable", "likely", and so on — seems intuitively more applicable to Hamlet interpretation. Where apparent contradictions arise between such interpretations, we might call the interpretations "incongruent", rather than dubbing either "false". <!--because....?-->


:In the sciences there need not be progress of another sort. We may, to be more precise, have to relinquish the notion, explicit or implicit, that changes of paradigm carry scientists and those who learn from them closer and closer to the truth.<ref>Kuhn, ''[[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]]'', p. 170.</ref>
The problem with the standard two-valued logic is simply that it only ever applies to [[sentential formula]]s and not to interpreted sentences in use. The principle of non-contradiction can easily be made ''not'' to obtain by reinterpreting the terms involved, as is the case with the corpuscular versus the wave theory of light{{Fact|date=April 2007}}.


:We are all deeply accustomed to seeing science as the one enterprise that draws constantly nearer to some goal set by nature in advance. But need there be any such goal? Can we not account for both science's existence and its success in terms of evolution from the community's state of knowledge at any given time? Does it really help to imagine that there is some one full, objective, true account of nature and that the proper measure of scientific achievement is the extent to which it brings us closer to that ultimate goal?<ref>Kuhn, ''[[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]]'', p. 171.</ref>
It was Aristotle who held that relativism implied we should, sticking with appearances only, end up contradicting ourselves somewhere if we could apply all attributes to all ''ousiai'' ([[being]]s). [[Aristotle]], however, made non-contradiction dependent upon his [[essentialism]]. If his essentialism is false, then so too is his ground for disallowing relativism.(Subsequent philosophers have found other reasons for supporting the principle of non-contradiction).


=====George Lakoff and Mark Johnson=====
Beginning with [[Protagoras]] and invoking [[Charles Peirce]], Margolis shows that the historic struggle to discredit relativism is an attempt to impose an unexamined belief in the world's essentially rigid rule-like nature. Plato and Aristotle merely attacked "relationalism"--the doctrine of true-for l or true for k, and the like, where l and k are different speakers or different world, or the something similar (Most philosophers would call this positions "relativism"). For Margolis "true" means true. That is the alethic use of "true" remains untouched. However, in real world contexts, and context is ubiquitous in the real world, we must apply truth values. Here, in epistemic terms, we might retire "true" tout court as an evaluation and keep "false". The rest of our value-judgements could be graded from "extremely plausible" down to "false". Judgements which on a bivalent logic would be incompatible or contradictory are further seen as "incongruent", though one may well have more weight than the other. In short, relativistic logic is not, or need not be, the bugbear it is often presented to be. It may simply be the best type of logic to apply to certain very uncertain spheres of our real experiences in the world (although some sort of logic needs to be applied to make that judgement). Those who swear by [[bivalent]] logic might simply be the ultimate keepers of the great fear of the flux.
[[George Lakoff]] and [[Mark Johnson (professor)|Mark Johnson]] define relativism in ''[[Metaphors We Live By]]'' as the rejection of both [[subjectivism]] and [[Metaphysical realism|metaphysical objectivism]] in order to focus on the relationship between them, i.e. the [[metaphors|metaphor]] by which we relate our current experience to our previous experience. In particular, Lakoff and Johnson characterize "objectivism" as a "[[straw man]]", and, to a lesser degree, criticize the views of [[Karl Popper]], [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] and [[Aristotle]].{{Page needed|date=September 2010}}


===Richard Rorty===
===== Robert Nozick =====
In his book ''[[Invariances]]'', [[Robert Nozick]] expresses a complex set of theories about the absolute and the relative. He thinks the absolute/relative distinction should be recast in terms of an invariant/variant distinction, where there are many things a proposition can be invariant with regard to or vary with. He thinks it is coherent for truth to be relative, and speculates that it might vary with time. He thinks necessity is an unobtainable notion, but can be approximated by robust invariance across a variety of conditions—although we can never identify a proposition that is invariant with regard to everything. Finally, he is not particularly warm to one of the most famous forms of relativism, [[moral relativism]], preferring an evolutionary account.
Philosopher [[Richard Rorty]] has a somewhat [[paradox]]ical role in the debate over relativism: he is criticized for his relativistic views, but prefers to describe himself not as a relativist, but as a [[pragmatist]].


=====Joseph Margolis=====
:'In short, my strategy for escaping the self-referential difficulties into which "the Relativist" keeps getting himself is to move everything over from epistemology and metaphysics into cultural politics, from claims to knowledge and appeals to self-evidence to suggestions about what we should try.'<ref>Rorty, R. ''Hilary Putnam and the Relativist Menace''</ref>
[[Joseph Margolis]] advocates a view he calls "robust relativism" and defends it in his books ''Historied Thought, Constructed World'', Chapter 4 (California, 1995) and ''The Truth about Relativism'' (Blackwell, 1991). He opens his account by stating that our logics should depend on what we take to be the nature of the sphere to which we wish to apply our logics. Holding that there can be no distinctions which are not "privileged" between the [[alethic possibility|alethic]], the [[ontic]], and the [[epistemic]], he maintains that a [[many-valued logic]] just might be the most apt for [[aesthetics]] or [[history]] since, because in these practices, we are loath to hold to simple [[Principle of bivalence|binary logic]]; and he also holds that many-valued logic is relativistic. (This is perhaps an unusual definition of "relativistic". Compare with his comments on "relationism".) To say that "True" and "False" are mutually exclusive and exhaustive judgements on ''[[Hamlet]]'', for instance, really does seem absurd. A many-valued logic{{mdash}}with its values "apt", "reasonable", "likely", and so on{{mdash}}seems intuitively more applicable to interpreting ''Hamlet''. Where apparent contradictions arise between such interpretations, we might call the interpretations "incongruent", rather than dubbing either of them "false", because using many-valued logic implies that a measured value is a mixture of two extreme possibilities. Using the subset of many-valued logic, [[fuzzy logic]], it can be said that various interpretations can be represented by membership in more than one possible truth set simultaneously. Fuzzy logic is therefore probably the best mathematical structure for understanding "robust relativism" and has been interpreted by [[Bart Kosko]] as philosophically being related to Zen Buddhism.


It was [[Aristotle]] who held that relativism implies that we should, sticking with appearances only, end up contradicting ourselves somewhere if we could apply all attributes to all ''ousiai'' ([[being]]s). Aristotle, however, made non-contradiction dependent upon his [[essentialism]]. If his essentialism is false, then so too is his ground for disallowing relativism. (Subsequent philosophers have found other reasons for supporting the principle of non-contradiction.){{clarify|date=December 2012}}
Rorty takes a [[deflationary]] attitude to [[truth]], believing there is nothing of interest to be said about truth in general, including the contention that it is generally subjective. He also argues that the notion of [[Theory of justification|warrant]] or [[justification]] can do most of the work traditionally assigned to the concept of truth, and that justification ''is'' relative; justification is justification to an audience, for Rorty. Thus his position, in the view of many commentators, adds up to relativism.


Beginning with [[Protagoras]] and invoking [[Charles Sanders Peirce]], Margolis shows that the historic struggle to discredit relativism is an attempt to impose an unexamined belief in the world's essentially rigid rule-like nature. Plato and Aristotle merely attacked "relationalism"{{mdash}}the doctrine of true for l or true for k, and the like, where l and k are different speakers or different worlds{{mdash}}or something similar (most philosophers would call this position "relativism"). For Margolis, "true" means true; that is, the alethic use of "true" remains untouched. However, in real world contexts, and context is ubiquitous in the real world, we must apply truth values. Here, in epistemic terms, we might ''tout court'' retire "true" as an evaluation and keep "false". The rest of our value-judgements could be graded from "extremely plausible" down to "false". Judgements which on a bivalent logic would be incompatible or contradictory are further seen as "incongruent", although one may well have more weight than the other. In short, relativistic logic is not, or need not be, the bugbear it is often presented to be. It may simply be the best type of logic to apply to certain very uncertain spheres of real experiences in the world (although some sort of logic needs to be applied in order to make that judgement). Those who swear by [[bivalent logic]] might simply be the ultimate keepers of the great fear of the flux.{{Citation needed|date=July 2011}}
In ''[[Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity]]'' he argues that the debate between so-called relativists and so-called objectivists is beside the point because they don't have enough premises in common for either side to prove anything to the other.


=====Richard Rorty=====
==Critics of relativism==
Philosopher [[Richard Rorty]] has a somewhat [[paradox]]ical role in the debate over relativism: he is criticized for his relativistic views by many commentators, but has always denied that relativism applies to much anybody, being nothing more than a Platonic scarecrow. Rorty claims, rather, that he is a [[pragmatism|pragmatist]], and that to construe pragmatism as relativism is to [[beg the question]].
Philosopher [[Paul Boghossian]] has written a book called ''Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism''.


:'"Relativism" is the traditional epithet applied to pragmatism by realists'<ref>Rorty, R. ''Consequences of Pragmatism''</ref>
In ''Science and Relativism'', [[Larry Laudan]] writes "The displacement of the idea that facts and evidence matter by the idea that everything boils down to subjective interest and perspectives, is &mdash; second only to American political campaigns &mdash; the most prominent and pernicious manifestation of relativism of our time."


:'"Relativism" is the view that every belief on a certain topic, or perhaps about any topic, is as good as every other. No one holds this view. Except for the occasional cooperative freshman, one cannot find anybody who says that two incompatible opinions on an important topic are equally good. The philosophers who get called 'relativists' are those who say that the grounds for choosing between such opinions are less algorithmic than had been thought.'<ref>Richard Rorty, ''Pragmatism, Relativism, and Irrationalism''</ref>
The literary theorist [[Christopher Norris (critic)|Christopher Norris]] has written a book entitled "Against Relativism". He is an expert on [[postmodern]] thought, particularly [[deconstruction]], and argues that deconstruction, properly understood, does not equate to relativism.


:'In short, my strategy for escaping the self-referential difficulties into which "the Relativist" keeps getting himself is to move everything over from epistemology and metaphysics into cultural politics, from claims to knowledge and appeals to self-evidence to suggestions about what we should try.'<ref>Rorty, R. ''Hilary Putnam and the Relativist Menace''</ref>
[[Plato]] was the first great critic of relativism. He criticizes the views of the [[sophist]] [[Protagoras]] in his dialogue ''[[Thaetetus]]''.


Rorty takes a [[Deflationary theory of truth|deflationary]] attitude to [[truth]], believing there is nothing of interest to be said about truth in general, including the contention that it is generally subjective. He also argues that the notion of [[Theory of justification|warrant]] or justification can do most of the work traditionally assigned to the concept of truth, and that justification ''is'' relative; justification is justification to an audience, for Rorty.
Physicist [[Alan Sokal]] initiated the [[science wars]] with his [[hoax]] paper entitled "[[Transgressing the Boundaries]]: Towards a Transformative Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity".<ref> {{cite journal | author= Sokal A. | title =Transgressing the Boundaries: Towards a Transformative Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity |year= 1996 | journal = Social Text |volume= 46/47| pages= 217-252| url=http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0164-2472%28199621%2F22%290%3A46%2F47%3C217%3ATTBTAT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-S}}</ref>
. He later co-authored the book ''[[Fashionable Nonsense]]'' (also known as ''Intellectual Impostures'') with [[Jean Bricmont]], which criticises the [[postmodernist]] use of science.


In ''[[Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity]]'' he argues that the debate between so-called relativists and so-called objectivists is beside the point because they do not have enough premises in common for either side to prove anything to the other.
==Postmodern relativism==
The term "relativism" often comes up in debates over [[postmodernism]], [[poststructuralism]] and [[phenomenology]]. Critics of these perspectives often identify advocates with the label "relativism." For example, the [[Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis]] is often considered a relativist view because it posits that linguistic categories and structures shape the way people view the world. Similarly, [[deconstruction]] is often termed a relativist perspective because of the ways it locates the meaning of a text in its appropriation and reading, implying that there is no "true" reading of a text and no text apart from its reading. Claims by literary critic [[Stanley Fish]] are also often discussed as "relativist".


===== Nalin de Silva =====
These perspectives do not strictly count as relativist in the philosophical sense, because they express agnosticism on the nature of reality and make [[epistemological]] rather than [[ontological]] claims. Nevertheless, the term is useful to differentiate them from [[Philosophical realism|realists]] who believe that the purpose of philosophy, science, or literary critique is to locate externally true meanings. Important philosophers and theorists such as [[Michel Foucault]], [[Max Stirner]] and [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], political movements such as [[post-anarchism]] or [[post-left anarchy]] can also be considered as relativist in this sense - though a better term might be social constructivist.
In his book ''Mage Lokaya'' (My World), 1986, [[Nalin de Silva]] criticized the basis of the established western system of knowledge, and its propagation, which he refers as "domination throughout the world".He explained in this book that mind independent reality is impossible and knowledge is not found but constructed. Further he has introduced and developed the concept of "Constructive Relativism" as the basis on which knowledge is constructed relative to the sense organs, culture and the mind completely based on [[Avidyā (Buddhism)|Avidya]].<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://repository.kln.ac.lk/jspui/bitstream/123456789/5923/1/109.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200129072609/http://repository.kln.ac.lk/jspui/bitstream/123456789/5923/1/109.pdf |archive-date=2020-01-29 |url-status=live|title=Constructive Relativism}}</ref>


====Postmodernism<!--'Postmodern relativism' redirects here-->====
The spread and popularity of this kind of "soft" relativism varies between academic disciplines. It has wide support in [[anthropology]] and has a majority following in cultural studies. It also has advocates in political theory and political science, sociology, and [[continental philosophy]] (as distinct from Anglo-American analytical philosophy). It has inspired empirical studies of the social construction of meaning such as those associated with labelling theory, which defenders can point to as evidence of the validity of their theories (albeit risking accusations of [[performative contradiction]] in the process). Advocates of this kind of relativism often also claim that recent developments in the natural sciences, such as Heisenberg's [[uncertainty principle]], [[quantum mechanics]], [[chaos theory]] and [[complexity theory]] show that science is now becoming relativistic. However, many scientists who use these methods continue to identify as realist or [[post-positivist]], and some sharply criticize the association<ref>[http://www.physics.nyu.edu/faculty/sokal/ Sokal and the Science Wars]</ref><ref>[http://www.csicop.org/si/9701/quantum-quackery.html Quantum quackery]</ref>
The term "relativism" often comes up in debates over [[postmodernism]], [[poststructuralism]] and [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]]. Critics of these perspectives often identify advocates with the label "relativism". For example, the [[Sapir–Whorf hypothesis]] is often considered a relativist view because it posits that linguistic categories and structures shape the way people view the world. [[Stanley Fish]] has defended postmodernism and relativism.<ref>[http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/rcq/Fish.pdf ''Don't Blame Relativism''] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130521230254/http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/rcq/Fish.pdf |date=2013-05-21 }} as "serious thought"</ref>


These perspectives do not strictly count as relativist in the philosophical sense, because they express agnosticism on the nature of reality and make [[epistemological]] rather than [[ontological]] claims. Nevertheless, the term is useful to differentiate them from [[Philosophical realism|realists]] who believe that the purpose of philosophy, science, or literary critique is to locate externally true meanings. Important philosophers and theorists such as [[Michel Foucault]], [[Max Stirner]], political movements such as [[post-anarchism]] or [[post-Marxism]] can also be considered as relativist in this sense - though a better term might be [[social constructivist]].
==Relativism: pro and con==
===Criticisms===
* One common argument<ref>[http://www.carm.org/relativism/relativism_refute.htm Christian Apologetics Research Ministry.]</ref><ref>[http://www.asa3.org/ASA/education/views/reality.htm Craig Rusbult. ''Reality 101'']</ref><ref>Keith Dixon. ''Is Cultural Relativism Self-Refuting''? (British Journal of Sociology, vol 28, No. 1)</ref><ref>[http://www.allaboutphilosophy.org/cultural-relativism.htm ''Cultural Relativism'' at All About Philosophy.]</ref><ref>[http://www.friesian.com/relative.htm The Friesian School on relativism.]</ref> against relativism suggests that it inherently [[self-refuting idea|contradicts, refutes, or stultifies itself]]: the statement "all is relative" classes either as a relative statement or as an absolute one. If it is relative, then this statement does not rule out absolutes. If the statement is [[Wiktionary:absolute|absolute]], on the other hand, then it provides an example of an absolute statement, proving that not all truths are relative. However, this argument against relativism only applies to relativism that positions truth as relative – i.e. epistemological/truth-value relativism. More specifically, it is only ''strong'' forms of epistemological relativism that can come in for this criticism as there are many epistemological relativists who posit that some aspects of what is regarded as "true" are not universal, yet still accept that other universal truths exist (e.g. [[gas laws]]). However, such exceptions need to be carefully justified, or "anything goes".


The spread and popularity of this kind of "soft" relativism varies between academic disciplines. It has wide support in [[anthropology]] and has a majority following in cultural studies. It also has advocates in political theory and political science, sociology, and [[continental philosophy]] (as distinct from Anglo-American analytical philosophy). It has inspired empirical studies of the social construction of meaning such as those associated with labelling theory, which defenders can point to as evidence of the validity of their theories (albeit risking accusations of [[performative contradiction]] in the process). Advocates of this kind of relativism often also claim that recent developments in the natural sciences, such as Heisenberg's [[uncertainty principle]], [[quantum mechanics]], [[chaos theory]] and [[Complex systems|complexity theory]] show that science is now becoming relativistic. However, many scientists who use these methods continue to identify as realist or [[post-positivist]], and some sharply criticize the association.<ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.physics.nyu.edu/faculty/sokal/| title = Sokal and the Science Wars}}</ref><ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.csicop.org/si/show/quantum_quackery/| title = Quantum quackery| date = January 1997}}</ref>
* Another argument against relativism posits a [[Natural Law]]. Simply put, the physical universe works under basic principles: the "Laws of Nature". Some contend that a natural Moral Law may also exist, for example as argued by [[Richard Dawkins]] in ''[[The God Delusion]]'' (2006).<ref>[[The God Delusion]], Chapter 6</ref> and addressed by [[C. S. Lewis]] in "[[Mere Christianity]]" (1952).<ref>[[Mere Christianity]], Chapter 1</ref>


===Religious===
* Aside from whether relativism is true, critics say it undermines morality, possibly resulting in [[anomie]] and complete [[Social Darwinism]]. Relativism denies that harming others is wrong in any absolute sense. The majority of relativists, of course, consider it immoral to harm others, but relativist theory allows for the opposite belief. If I can believe it wrong for me to harm others, I can also believe it right – no matter what the circumstances.
====Buddhism====
[[Madhyamaka|Madhyamaka Buddhism]], which forms the basis for many [[Mahayana]] Buddhist schools and which was founded by [[Nagarjuna|Nāgārjuna]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Garfield |first=Jay L. |title=Engaging Buddhism: Why it Matters in Philosophy |publisher=Oxford U.P. |year=2015 |isbn=978-0-19-020434-1 |location=Oxford}}</ref> Nāgārjuna taught the idea of relativity. In the Ratnāvalī, he gives the example that shortness exists only in relation to the idea of length. The determination of a thing or object is only possible in relation to other things or objects, especially by way of contrast. He held that the relationship between the ideas of "short" and "long" is not due to intrinsic nature ([[svabhāva]]). This idea is also found in the Pali Nikāyas and Chinese Āgamas, in which the idea of relativity is expressed similarly: "That which is the element of light ... is seen to exist on account of [in relation to] darkness; that which is the element of good is seen to exist on account of bad; that which is the element of space is seen to exist on account of form."<ref>[[David Kalupahana]], ''Causality: The Central Philosophy of Buddhism.'' The University Press of Hawaii, 1975, pp. 96–97. In the Nikayas the quote is found at SN 2.150.</ref>


Madhyamaka Buddhism discerns two levels of truth: relative and ultimate. The [[two truths doctrine]] states that there are ''Relative'' or conventional, common-sense truth, which describes our daily experience of a concrete world, and ''Ultimate'' truth, which describes the ultimate reality as ''[[sunyata]]'', empty of concrete and inherent characteristics. Conventional truth may be understood, in contrast, as "obscurative truth" or "that which obscures the true nature". It is constituted by the appearances of mistaken awareness. Conventional truth would be the appearance that includes a duality of apprehender and apprehended, and objects perceived within that. Ultimate truth is the phenomenal world free from the duality of apprehender and apprehended.<ref name="LevinsonAug06">Levinson, Jules (August 2006) ''[http://www.berotsana.org/pdf/lotsawa_timesII_sc.pdf Lotsawa Times Volume II]'' {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080724083326/http://www.berotsana.org/pdf/lotsawa_timesII_sc.pdf|date=2008-07-24}}</ref>
* The problem of negation also arises. If everyone with differing opinions is right, then no one is. Thus instead of saying "all beliefs (ideas, truths, etc.) are equally valid," one might just as well say "all beliefs are equally worthless". (see article on [[Doublethink]]).


==== Catholicism ====
*Relativism is also sometimes seen as an over-reaction to [[colonialism]]. Those upset with the quick evaluation of different cultures and ideas as inferior have over-reacted into 'all cultures and ideas are equal'.{{Fact|date=May 2007}}
{{missing information|a historical perspective on Catholic thinking|date=January 2024}}


The [[Catholic Church]], especially under [[John Paul II]] and [[Pope Benedict XVI]], has identified relativism as one of the most significant problems for faith and morals today.<ref>{{cite web |title=World Youth Day News August August 21, 2005<!-- Bot generated title --> |url=http://www.nationalcatholicreporter.org/word/wyd082105.htm}}</ref>
*Another argument is that if relativism presupposes that "all beliefs are equally valid," it is then saying belief systems that believe they are the only individual valid belief system nullifies it as being one of many valid beliefs. For example, relativism presupposes all beliefs are equally valid. Most monotheistic religions, [[Christianity]] or [[Islam]] for example, however, presuppose that they are, individually, the only valid belief systems. This creates a direct self-contradiction: relativism presupposes that any belief, including one such as Christianity, is valid. On the other hand, Christianity believes that only Christianity (and therefore ''not'' relativism) is valid. Relativism states Christianity is one of many true beliefs, while Christianity states it is the ''only'' true belief, which only results in contradicting relativism's presupposition that Christianity is one of many truths. In simple terms: ''If A, then B. If B, then not A.'' (In this case, A is relativism, while B is a belief system such as Christianity or Islam.)


According to the Church and to some theologians,{{who|date=January 2024}} relativism, as a denial of absolute truth, leads to moral license and a denial of the possibility of [[sin]] and of [[God]]. Whether moral or epistemological, relativism constitutes a denial of the capacity of the human mind and reason to arrive at truth. Truth, according to Catholic theologians and philosophers (following Aristotle) consists of ''adequatio rei et intellectus'', the [[correspondence theory of truth|correspondence]] of the mind and reality. Another way of putting it states that the [[mind]] has the same form as reality. This means when the form of the computer in front of someone (the type, color, shape, capacity, etc.) is also the form that is in their mind, then what they know is true because their mind corresponds to objective reality.
*Another criticism is that modest admissions of disbelief are impossible. If it was true for me yesterday when I said, "I aced that exam", how can I say today "I failed the exam yesterday that I thought I did so well on"?


The denial of an absolute reference, of an ''axis mundi'', denies God, who equates to Absolute Truth, according to these Christian theologians. They link relativism to [[secularism]], an obstruction of religion in [[human condition|human life.]]
===Responses===
* Contradictions such as "all beliefs are equally worthless" are nonsensical, as they constitute arguing from the premise. Once you have said ''if the X is absolute'' (e.g. "all beliefs are equally worthless") you have presupposed relativism is false. And one cannot prove a statement using that statement as a premise. There is a contradiction, but the contradiction is between relativism and the presuppositions of absoluteness in the ordinary logic used. Nothing has been proven wrong and nothing has been proven in and of itself, only the known incompatibility has been restated inefficiently.


=====Leo XIII=====
* Another counter-argument {{Fact|date=February 2007}} uses [[Russell's paradox|Bertrand Russell's Paradox]], which refers to the "List of all lists that do not contain themselves". [[Kurt Gödel]], [[Jorge Luis Borges]], and [[Jean Baudrillard]] have famously debated this paradox.
[[Pope Leo XIII]] (1810–1903) was the first known Pope to use the word "relativism", in his encyclical ''[[Humanum genus]]'' (1884). Leo condemned [[Freemasonry]] and claimed that its philosophical and political system was largely based on relativism.<ref>{{cite web |title=Humanum genus |url=https://www.vatican.va/holy_father/leo_xiii/encyclicals/documents/hf_l-xiii_enc_18840420_humanum-genus_it.html}}</ref>


=====John Paul II=====
* A very different approach explicates the rhetorical production of supposedly 'bottom-line' arguments against relativism. Edwards et al’s influential and controversial "Death and Furniture"<ref>http://www-staff.lboro.ac.uk/~ssde/Death%20and%20furniture.pdf</ref> paper takes this line in its staunch defense of relativism. Part of the rhetoric discussed here involves the portrayal of relativists who say (for example), "torture is not an absolute evil", as saying, in effect, "we don't disapprove of torture as strongly as you do". Relativists argue that this is a rhetorical trick, akin to claiming "you can't throw out the bath water without throwing out the baby too": denying absolute truths still leaves relativists free to be utterly and passionately opposed to torture. Further [[cultural relativism]] only implies that differing cultural contexts have to be taken into account when making judgements about what is good or bad relative to that culture. It does not limit one's ability to disagree with a cultural norm.
[[Pope John Paul II|John Paul II]] wrote in ''[[Veritatis Splendor]]''


:As is immediately evident, the crisis of truth is not unconnected with this development. Once the idea of a universal truth about the good, knowable by human reason, is lost, inevitably the notion of conscience also changes. Conscience is no longer considered in its primordial reality as an act of a person's intelligence, the function of which is to apply the universal knowledge of the good in a specific situation and thus to express a judgment about the right conduct to be chosen here and now. Instead, there is a tendency to grant to the individual conscience the prerogative of independently determining the criteria of good and evil and then acting accordingly. Such an outlook is quite congenial to an individualist ethic, wherein each individual is faced with his own truth, different from the truth of others. Taken to its extreme consequences, this individualism leads to a denial of the very idea of human nature.
* A strong epistemological relativist could theoretically argue that it does not matter that his theory is only relative according to itself. As long as it remains "true" according to a relative framework, then it is just as true as any apparently "absolute" truth that a realist would postulate. The dispute lies in the distinction between whether the framework is relative or absolute, but if a realist could be persuaded it was relative, then the relativist theory could exist logically within that framework, albeit accepting that its "truth" is relative. A strong epistemological relativist must remove his own notions of universal truth if he is to embrace his theory fully, he must accept some form of truth to validate his theory logically, and this truth, by definition, must be relative. So if the initial framework is relativistic and something is true within its context arguments that it is not true outside its context have no value.


In ''[[Evangelium Vitae]]'' (The Gospel of Life), he says:
==Theater and relativism==
Relativism found its voice in theater through [[Pirandello]] who believed that nothing, neither time nor morals, is absolute.


:Freedom negates and destroys itself, and becomes a factor leading to the destruction of others, when it no longer recognizes and respects its essential link with the truth. When freedom, out of a desire to emancipate itself from all forms of tradition and authority, shuts out even the most obvious evidence of an objective and universal truth, which is the foundation of personal and social life, then the person ends up by no longer taking as the sole and indisputable point of reference for his own choices the truth about good and evil, but only his subjective and changeable opinion or, indeed, his selfish interest and whim.
Pirandello examines the relationship between reality, illusion and relativity, and we should not forget that Einstein’s theory of Relativity was popular in Pirandello’s day. Indeed Einstein reputedly went up to Pirandello after the performance of one of his plays and said to him ‘We are kindred souls.’


===== Benedict XVI =====
==The Catholic Church and relativism==
In April 2005, in his homily during Mass prior to the conclave which would elect him as [[Pope]], then [[Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger]] talked about the world "moving towards a dictatorship of relativism":
The [[Roman Catholic Church]], especially under [[John Paul II]] and [[Pope Benedict XVI]], has identified relativism as one of the most significant problems for faith and morals today.<ref>http://www.nationalcatholicreporter.org/word/wyd082105.htm</ref>


:How many winds of doctrine we have known in recent decades, how many ideological currents, how many ways of thinking. The small boat of thought of many Christians has often been tossed about by these waves – thrown from one extreme to the other: from Marxism to liberalism, even to libertinism; from collectivism to radical individualism; from atheism to a vague religious mysticism; from agnosticism to syncretism, and so forth. Every day new sects are created and what [[Saint Paul]] says about human trickery comes true, with cunning which tries to draw those into error (cf [[Ephesians]] 4, 14). Having a clear Faith, based on the Creed of the Church, is often labeled today as a fundamentalism. Whereas, relativism, which is letting oneself be tossed and "swept along by every wind of teaching", looks like the only attitude acceptable to today's standards. We are moving towards a dictatorship of relativism which does not recognize anything as certain and which has as its highest goal one's own ego and one's own desires. However, we have a different goal: the Son of God, true man. He is the measure of true humanism. Being an "Adult" means having a faith which does not follow the waves of today's fashions or the latest novelties. A faith which is deeply rooted in friendship with [[Christ]] is adult and mature. It is this friendship which opens us up to all that is good and gives us the knowledge to judge true from false, and deceit from truth.<ref>{{cite web |title=Mass "Pro Eligendo Romano Pontifice": Homily of Card. Joseph Ratzinger<!-- Bot generated title --> |url=https://www.vatican.va/gpII/documents/homily-pro-eligendo-pontifice_20050418_en.html}}</ref>
According to the Church and to some philosophers, relativism, as a denial of absolute truth, leads to moral license and a denial of the [[possibility]] of [[sin]] and of [[God]]. Whether moral or epistemological, relativism constitutes a denial of the capacity of the human mind and reason to arrive at truth. Truth, according to Catholic theologians and philosophers (following Aristotle and Plato) consists of ''adequatio rei et intellectus'', the [[correspondence theory of truth|correspondence]] of the mind and reality. Another way of putting it states that the [[mind]] has the same [[form]] as reality. This means when the form of the computer in front of me (the type, color, shape, capacity, etc.) is also the form that is in my mind, then what I know is true because my mind corresponds to objective reality.


On June 6, 2005, Pope Benedict XVI told educators:
The denial of an absolute reference, of an ''axis mundi,'' denies God, who equates to Absolute Truth, according to these Christian philosophers. They link relativism to [[secularism]], an obstruction of God in human [[personal life|life]].


:Today, a particularly insidious obstacle to the task of education is the massive presence in our society and culture of that relativism which, recognizing nothing as definitive, leaves as the ultimate criterion only the self with its desires. And under the semblance of freedom it becomes a prison for each one, for it separates people from one another, locking each person into his or her own 'ego'.<ref>{{cite web |title=Inaugural Address at the Ecclesial Diocesan Convention of Rome<!-- Bot generated title --> |url=https://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/speeches/2005/june/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20050606_convegno-famiglia_en.html}}</ref>
===John Paul II===
[[Pope John Paul II|John Paul II]] in ''[[Veritatis Splendor]]'' ("The Splendor of the Truth") stressed the dependence of man on God and his law ("Without the Creator, the creature disappears") and the "dependence of freedom on the truth". He warned that man "giving himself over to relativism and skepticism, goes off in search of an illusory freedom apart from truth itself".


Then during the [[World Youth Day 2005|World Youth Day]] in August 2005, he also traced to relativism the problems produced by the communist and sexual revolutions, and provided a counter-counter argument.<ref>{{cite web |title=20th World Youth Day - Cologne - Marienfeld, Youth Vigil<!-- Bot generated title --> |url=https://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/speeches/2005/august/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20050820_vigil-wyd_en.html}}</ref>
In ''[[Evangelium Vitae]]'' (The Gospel of Life), he says:


:In the last century we experienced revolutions with a common programme–expecting nothing more from God, they assumed total responsibility for the cause of the world in order to change it. And this, as we saw, meant that a human and partial point of view was always taken as an absolute guiding principle. Absolutizing what is not absolute but relative is called totalitarianism. It does not liberate man, but takes away his dignity and enslaves him. It is not ideologies that save the world, but only a return to the living God, our Creator, the Guarantor of our freedom, the Guarantor of what is really good and true.{{citation needed|date=May 2023}}
:The original and inalienable right to life is questioned or denied on the basis of a parliamentary vote or the will of one part of the people-even if it is the majority. ''This is the sinister result of a relativism which reigns unopposed: the "right" ceases to be such, because it is no longer firmly founded on the inviolable dignity of the person, but is made subject to the will of the stronger part.'' In this way democracy, contradicting its own principles, effectively moves towards a form of totalitarianism. The State is no longer the "common home" where all can live together on the basis of principles of fundamental equality, but is transformed into a tyrant State, which arrogates to itself the right to dispose of the life of the weakest and most defenceless members, from the unborn child to the elderly, in the name of a public interest which is really nothing but the interest of one part. [Italics added]


===Benedict XVI===
=====Pope Francis=====
[[Pope Francis]] refers in ''[[Evangelii gaudium]]'' to two forms of relativism, "doctrinal relativism" and a "practical relativism" typical of "our age".<ref>Pope Francis, [https://www.vatican.va/content/francesco/en/apost_exhortations/documents/papa-francesco_esortazione-ap_20131124_evangelii-gaudium.html Evangelii gaudium], paragraph 80, published 24 November 2013, accessed 14 January 2024</ref> The latter is allied to "widespread indifference" to systems of belief.<ref>Olsen, C. E., [https://www.catholicworldreport.com/2013/11/26/a-helpful-summary-of-the-apostolic-exhortation-evangelii-gaudium/ A helpful summary of the Apostolic Exhortation, "Evangelii Gaudium"], ''The Catholic World Report'', published 26 November 2013, accessed 14 January 2024</ref>
In April [[2005]], in his homily<ref>[http://www.vatican.va/gpII/documents/homily-pro-eligendo-pontifice_20050418_en.html]</ref> during Mass prior to the conclave which would elect him as [[Pope]], then [[Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger]] talked about the world "moving towards a ''dictatorship of relativism''":


==== Jainism ====
:How many winds of doctrine we have known in recent decades, how many ideological currents, how many ways of thinking. The small boat of thought of many Christians has often been tossed about by these waves ¬ thrown from one extreme to the other: from Marxism to liberalism, even to libertinism; from collectivism to radical individualism; from atheism to a vague religious mysticism; from agnosticism to syncretism, and so forth. Every day new sects are created and what Saint Paul says about human trickery comes true, with cunning which tries to draw those into error (cf Eph 4, 14). Having a clear faith, based on the Creed of the Church, is often labeled today as a fundamentalism. Whereas, relativism, which is letting oneself be tossed and "swept along by every wind of teaching", looks like the only attitude acceptable to today's standards. We are moving towards a dictatorship of relativism which does not recognize anything as certain and which has as its highest goal one's own ego and one's own desires. However, we have a different goal: the Son of God, true man. He is the measure of true humanism. Being an "Adult" means having a faith which does not follow the waves of today's fashions or the latest novelties. A faith which is deeply rooted in friendship with Christ is adult and mature. It is this friendship which opens us up to all that is good and gives us the knowledge to judge true from false, and deceit from truth.
[[Mahavira]] (599-527 BC), the 24th [[Tirthankara]] of [[Jainism]], developed a philosophy known as [[Anekantavada]]. John Koller describes ''anekāntavāda'' as "epistemological respect for view of others" about the nature of existence, whether it is "inherently enduring or constantly changing", but "not relativism; it does not mean conceding that all arguments and all views are equal".<ref name="koller89">{{cite book|author=John Koller|editor=Tara Sethia|title=Ahimsā, Anekānta, and Jainism|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QYdlKv8wBiYC |year=2004 |publisher=Motilal Banarsidass |isbn=978-81-208-2036-4|pages=88–89}}</ref>


====Sikhism====
On [[June 6]] [[2005]], Pope Benedict XVI told educators:
In [[Sikhism]] the [[Sikh Gurus|Gurus]] (spiritual teachers) have propagated the message of "many paths" leading to the [[Ek Onkar|one God]] and ultimate [[salvation]] for all souls who tread on the path of [[righteousness]]. They have supported the view that proponents of all faiths can, by doing good and virtuous deeds and by remembering the [[Lord]], certainly achieve salvation. The students of the Sikh faith are told to accept all leading faiths as possible vehicles for attaining spiritual enlightenment provided the faithful study, ponder and practice the teachings of their prophets and leaders. The holy book of the [[Sikh]]s called the [[Sri Guru Granth Sahib]] says: "Do not say that the Vedas, the Bible and the Koran are false. Those who do not contemplate them are false." [[Guru Granth Sahib]] page 1350;<ref>{{cite web| url = http://www.srigranth.org/servlet/gurbani.gurbani?Action=Page&Param=1350&english=t&id=57718| title = Guru Granth Sahib page 1350}}</ref> later stating: "The seconds, minutes, and hours, days, weeks and months, and the various seasons originate from the one Sun; O nanak, in just the same way, the many forms originate from the Creator." [[Guru Granth Sahib]] page 12,13.

:"Today, a particularly insidious obstacle to the task of education is the massive presence in our society and culture of that relativism which, recognizing nothing as definitive, leaves as the ultimate criterion only the self with its desires. And under the semblance of freedom it becomes a prison for each one, for it separates people from one another, locking each person into his or her own 'ego'".<ref>[http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/speeches/2005/june/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20050606_convegno-famiglia_en.html]</ref>

Then during the [[World Youth Day 2005|World Youth Day]] in August 2005, he also traced to relativism the problems produced by the communist and sexual revolutions, and provided a '''counter-counter argument'''.<ref>[http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/speeches/2005/august/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20050820_vigil-wyd_en.html]</ref>

:In the last century we experienced revolutions with a common programme – expecting nothing more from God, they assumed total responsibility for the cause of the world in order to change it. And this, as we saw, meant that a human and partial point of view was always taken as an absolute guiding principle. ''Absolutizing what is not absolute but relative is called totalitarianism.'' It does not liberate man, but takes away his dignity and enslaves him. It is not ideologies that save the world, but only a return to the living God, our Creator, the guarantor of our freedom, the guarantor of what is really good and true.

===Criticism===
These Church documents suggest the position that to accept its version of morality is the only alternative to relativism. ''[[Veritatis Splendor]]'' insists that we must retain ''respect for certain fundamental goods, without which one would fall into relativism and arbitrariness'' where it is further insisted that sodomy, contraception, etc. necessarily violate such respect for goods such as life. But the claim that rejection of these activities and relativism are the only choices is false, and as a lie could plausibly be labelled unethical itself. There are many other ethical systems which reject this dichotomy; see [[ethics]] and [[normative ethics]].

==Notes/References==
{{citation style}}
{{reflist|2}}
{{ISBN|date=February 2008}}
* ''Relativism, cognitive and moral'', edited Jack W. Meiland & Michael Krausz, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982
* ''Rationality, relativism, and the human sciences'', edited by Joseph Margolis, M. Krausz, R.M. Burian. Dordrecht: Boston, M. Nijhoff, 1986
* ''Rationality and Relativism'', Hollis, Martin and Lukes, Stephen, ed., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982.
* ''Varieties of Relativism'', ed. Rom Harré. Oxford, UK; New York, NY: Blackwell, 1996


==See also==
==See also==
{{columns-list|colwidth=30em|
* [[Anthropology]]
* [[Baháʼí Faith and the unity of religion]]
* [[Moral relativism]]
* [[Philosophical realism]]
* [[Degree of truth]]
* [[False dilemma]]
* [[Graded absolutism]]
* [[Heraclitus]]
* [[John Hick]]
* [[Multi-valued logic]]
* [[Normative ethics]]
* [[Perspectivism]]
* [[Pluralism (philosophy)]]
* [[Polylogism]]
* [[Principle of Bivalence]]
* [[Propositional logic]]
* [[Relationalism|Relationism]]
* [[Religiocentrism]]
* [[Science Wars]]
* [[Scientism]]
* [[Social constructionism]]
* [[Social constructionism]]
* The [[Science Wars]]
* [[Subjective logic]]
* [[Worldview]]
* [[Worldview]]
}}
* [[Subjectivism]]

==References==
{{Reflist}}

==Bibliography==
* [[Maria Baghramian]], ''Relativism,'' London: Routledge, 2004, {{ISBN|0-415-16150-9}}
* Gad Barzilai, ''Communities and Law: Politics and Cultures of Legal Identities,'' Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2003, {{ISBN|0-472-11315-1}}
* Andrew Lionel Blais, ''On the Plurality of Actual Worlds,'' [[University of Massachusetts Press]], 1997, {{ISBN|1-55849-072-8}}
* Benjamin Brown, Thoughts and Ways of Thinking: Source Theory and Its Applications. London: [[Ubiquity Press]], 2017. [https://www.ubiquitypress.com/site/books/10.5334/bbh/].
* {{cite journal | last1 = Buchbinder | first1 = David | last2 = McGuire | first2 = Ann Elizabeth | author-link1 = David Buchbinder | title = The backlash against relativism: the new curricular fundamentalism | journal = The International Journal of the Humanities: Annual Review | volume = 5 | issue = 5 | pages = 51&ndash;59 | publisher = Common Ground Journals and Books | doi = 10.18848/1447-9508/CGP/v05i05/42109 | date = 2007 }}
* [[Ernest Gellner]], ''Relativism and the Social Sciences,'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985, {{ISBN|0-521-33798-4}}
* [[Rom Harré]] and [[Michael Krausz]], ''Varieties of Relativism'', Oxford, UK; New York, NY: Blackwell, 1996, {{ISBN|0-631-18409-0}}
* Knight, Robert H. ''The Age of Consent: the Rise of Relativism and the Corruption of Popular Culture''. Dallas, Tex.: Spence Publishing Co., 1998. xxiv, 253, [1] p. {{ISBN|1-890626-05-8}}
* [[Michael Krausz]], ed., ''Relativism: A Contemporary Anthology'', New York: Columbia University Press, 2010, {{ISBN|978-0-231-14410-0}}
* [[Martin Hollis (philosopher)|Martin Hollis]], [[Steven Lukes]], ''Rationality and Relativism,'' Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982, {{ISBN|0-631-12773-9}}
* [[Joseph Margolis]], [[Michael Krausz]], R. M. Burian, Eds., ''Rationality, Relativism, and the Human Sciences'', Dordrecht: Boston, M. Nijhoff, 1986, {{ISBN|90-247-3271-9}}
* [[Jack W. Meiland]], [[Michael Krausz]], Eds. ''Relativism, Cognitive and Moral,'' Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982, {{ISBN|0-268-01611-9}}
* Markus Seidel, ''Epistemic Relativism: A Constructive Critique,'' Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014, {{ISBN|978-1-137-37788-3}}


==External links==
==External links==
{{Wikiquote|Relativism}}
* [http://www.philosophicalsociety.com/Archives/What%20'Being%20Relative'%20Means.htm What 'Being Relative' Means] A passage from [[Pierre Lecomte du Nouy]]'s "Human Destiny" (1947).
{{Wiktionary|relativism}}
* [http://www.bbc.co.uk/radio4/history/inourtime/inourtime_20060119.shtml BBC Radio 4 series "In Our Time", on ''Relativism - the battle against transcendent knowledge'', 19 January 2006]
{{Commons category}}
* [http://www.cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/reviews/norris-against-relativism/ Christopher Noriss's ''Against Relativism'']
*{{IEP|epis-rel|Epistemology and Relativism}}
* [http://www.science.uva.nl/~seop/entries/relativism/ Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Relativism]
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/c/cog-rel.htm Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Cognitive Relativism]
* Westacott, E. ''[http://www.iep.utm.edu/relativi/ Relativism]'', 2005, [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
* Westacott, E. ''[http://www.iep.utm.edu/c/cog-rel.htm Cognitive Relativism]'', 2006, [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
* [http://www.friesian.com/relative.htm The Friesian School on Relativism]
*[http://www.frieze.com/comment/article/best_before_1995/ Professor Ronald Jones on relativism] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080808140205/http://www.frieze.com/comment/article/best_before_1995/ |date=2008-08-08 }} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080808140205/http://www.frieze.com/comment/article/best_before_1995/ |date=2008-08-08 }}<!-- Broken 2013-07-23 -->
* [http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/12731d.htm The Catholic Encyclopedia]
*[http://www.philosophicalsociety.com/Archives/What%20'Being%20Relative'%20Means.htm ''What 'Being Relative' Means''], a passage from [[Pierre Lecomte du Nouy]]'s "Human Destiny" (1947)
* [http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=8364 Harvey Siegel reviews] [[Paul Boghossian]]'s ''Fear of Knowledge''
*[http://www.bbc.co.uk/radio4/history/inourtime/inourtime_20060119.shtml BBC Radio 4 series "In Our Time", on ''Relativism - the battle against transcendent knowledge'', 19 January 2006]

*[http://www.cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/reviews/norris-against-relativism/ ''Against Relativism''], by Christopher Noriss
{{skepticism}}
*{{cite SEP |url-id=relativism |title=Relativism}}
{{Philosophy (navigation)}}
*[http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/12731d.htm The Catholic Encyclopedia]
*[http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=8364 Harvey Siegel reviews] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070630101539/http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=8364 |date=2007-06-30 }} [[Paul Boghossian]]'s ''Fear of Knowledge''


{{Western culture}}
[[Category:Philosophical terminology]]
{{Skepticism}}
[[Category:Philosophy articles needing attention]]
{{Philosophy topics}}
[[Category:Relativism]]
{{Metaphysics}}
{{Authority control}}


[[Category:Relativism| ]]
[[ar:نسبوية]]
[[Category:Epistemological schools and traditions]]
[[bg:Релативизъм]]
[[ca:Relativisme]]
[[da:Relativisme]]
[[de:Relativismus]]
[[et:Relativism]]
[[el:Σχετικισμός]]
[[es:Relativismo]]
[[fr:Relativisme]]
[[ko:상대주의]]
[[is:Afstæðishyggja]]
[[it:Relativismo]]
[[he:רלטיביזם]]
[[lt:Reliatyvizmas]]
[[hu:Relativizmus]]
[[nl:Relativisme]]
[[ja:相対主義]]
[[no:Relativisme]]
[[pl:Relatywizm]]
[[pt:Relativismo]]
[[ro:Relativism]]
[[ru:Релятивизм]]
[[sk:Relativizmus]]
[[fi:Relativismi]]
[[sv:Relativism]]
[[tr:Görecilik]]
[[zh:相對主義]]

Latest revision as of 11:27, 13 December 2024

Relativism is a family of philosophical views which deny claims to objectivity within a particular domain and assert that valuations in that domain are relative to the perspective of an observer or the context in which they are assessed.[1] There are many different forms of relativism, with a great deal of variation in scope and differing degrees of controversy among them.[2] Moral relativism encompasses the differences in moral judgments among people and cultures.[3] Epistemic relativism holds that there are no absolute principles regarding normative belief, justification, or rationality, and that there are only relative ones.[4] Alethic relativism (also factual relativism) is the doctrine that there are no absolute truths, i.e., that truth is always relative to some particular frame of reference, such as a language or a culture (cultural relativism), while linguistic relativism asserts that a language's structures influence a speaker's perceptions.[5][6] Some forms of relativism also bear a resemblance to philosophical skepticism.[7] Descriptive relativism seeks to describe the differences among cultures and people without evaluation, while normative relativism evaluates the word truthfulness of views within a given framework.

Forms of relativism

[edit]

Anthropological versus philosophical relativism

[edit]

Anthropological relativism refers to a methodological stance, in which the researcher suspends (or brackets) their own cultural prejudice while trying to understand beliefs or behaviors in their contexts. This has become known as methodological relativism, and concerns itself specifically with avoiding ethnocentrism or the application of one's own cultural standards to the assessment of other cultures.[8] This is also the basis of the so-called "emic" and "etic" distinction, in which:

  • An emic or insider account of behavior is a description of a society in terms that are meaningful to the participant or actor's own culture; an emic account is therefore culture-specific, and typically refers to what is considered "common sense" within the culture under observation.
  • An etic or outsider account is a description of a society by an observer, in terms that can be applied to other cultures; that is, an etic account is culturally neutral, and typically refers to the conceptual framework of the social scientist. (This is complicated when it is scientific research itself that is under study, or when there is theoretical or terminological disagreement within the social sciences.)

Philosophical relativism, in contrast, asserts that the truth of a proposition depends on the metaphysical, or theoretical frame, or the instrumental method, or the context in which the proposition is expressed, or on the person, groups, or culture who interpret the proposition.[9]

Methodological relativism and philosophical relativism can exist independently from one another, but most anthropologists base their methodological relativism on that of the philosophical variety.[10]

Descriptive versus normative relativism

[edit]

The concept of relativism also has importance both for philosophers and for anthropologists in another way. In general, anthropologists engage in descriptive relativism ("how things are" or "how things seem"), whereas philosophers engage in normative relativism ("how things ought to be"), although there is some overlap (for example, descriptive relativism can pertain to concepts, normative relativism to truth).

Descriptive relativism assumes that certain cultural groups have different modes of thought, standards of reasoning, and so forth, and it is the anthropologist's task to describe, but not to evaluate the validity of these principles and practices of a cultural group. It is possible for an anthropologist in his or her fieldwork to be a descriptive relativist about some things that typically concern the philosopher (e.g., ethical principles) but not about others (e.g., logical principles). However, the descriptive relativist's empirical claims about epistemic principles, moral ideals and the like are often countered by anthropological arguments that such things are universal, and much of the recent literature on these matters is explicitly concerned with the extent of, and evidence for, cultural or moral or linguistic or human universals.[11]

The fact that the various species of descriptive relativism are empirical claims may tempt the philosopher to conclude that they are of little philosophical interest, but there are several reasons why this is not so. First, some philosophers, notably Kant, argue that certain sorts of cognitive differences between human beings (or even all rational beings) are impossible, so such differences could never be found to obtain in fact, an argument that places a priori limits on what empirical inquiry could discover and on what versions of descriptive relativism could be true. Second, claims about actual differences between groups play a central role in some arguments for normative relativism (for example, arguments for normative ethical relativism often begin with claims that different groups in fact have different moral codes or ideals). Finally, the anthropologist's descriptive account of relativism helps to separate the fixed aspects of human nature from those that can vary, and so a descriptive claim that some important aspect of experience or thought does (or does not) vary across groups of human beings tells us something important about human nature and the human condition.

Normative relativism concerns normative or evaluative claims that modes of thought, standards of reasoning, or the like are only right or wrong relative to a framework. 'Normative' is meant in a general sense, applying to a wide range of views; in the case of beliefs, for example, normative correctness equals truth. This does not mean, of course, that framework-relative correctness or truth is always clear, the first challenge being to explain what it amounts to in any given case (e.g., with respect to concepts, truth, epistemic norms). Normative relativism (say, in regard to normative ethical relativism) therefore implies that things (say, ethical claims) are not simply true in themselves, but only have truth values relative to broader frameworks (say, moral codes). (Many normative ethical relativist arguments run from premises about ethics to conclusions that assert the relativity of truth values, bypassing general claims about the nature of truth, but it is often more illuminating to consider the type of relativism under question directly.)[12]

[edit]

In English common law, two (perhaps three) separate standards of proof are recognized:

[edit]

Relationism is the theory that there are only relations between individual entities, and no intrinsic properties. Despite the similarity in name, it is held by some to be a position distinct from relativism—for instance, because "statements about relational properties [...] assert an absolute truth about things in the world".[14] On the other hand, others wish to equate relativism, relationism and even relativity, which is a precise theory of relationships between physical objects:[15] Nevertheless, "This confluence of relativity theory with relativism became a strong contributing factor in the increasing prominence of relativism".[16]

Whereas previous investigations of science only sought sociological or psychological explanations of failed scientific theories or pathological science, the 'strong programme' is more relativistic, assessing scientific truth and falsehood equally in a historic and cultural context.

Criticisms

[edit]

A common argument[17][18][19] against relativism suggests that it inherently refutes itself: the statement "all is relative" classes either as a relative statement or as an absolute one. If it is relative, then this statement does not rule out absolutes. If the statement is absolute, on the other hand, then it provides an example of an absolute statement, proving that not all truths are relative. However, this argument against relativism only applies to relativism that positions truth as relative–i.e. epistemological/truth-value relativism. More specifically, it is only extreme forms of epistemological relativism that can come in for this criticism as there are many epistemological relativists[who?] who posit that some aspects of what is regarded as factually "true" are not universal, yet still accept that other universal truths exist (e.g. gas laws or moral laws).

Another argument against relativism posits the existence of natural law. Simply put, the physical universe works under basic principles: the "Laws of Nature". Some contend that a natural moral law may also exist, for example as argued by, Immanuel Kant in Critique of Practical Reason, Richard Dawkins in The God Delusion (2006)[20] and addressed by C. S. Lewis in Mere Christianity (1952).[21] Dawkins said "I think we face an equal but much more sinister challenge from the left, in the shape of cultural relativism - the view that scientific truth is only one kind of truth and it is not to be especially privileged".[22] Philosopher Hilary Putnam,[23] among others,[24] states that some forms of relativism make it impossible to believe one is in error. If there is no truth beyond an individual's belief that something is true, then an individual cannot hold their own beliefs to be false or mistaken. A related criticism is that relativizing truth to individuals destroys the distinction between truth and belief.

Views

[edit]

Philosophical

[edit]

Ancient

[edit]
Sophism
[edit]

Sophists are considered the founding fathers of relativism in Western philosophy. Elements of relativism emerged among the Sophists in the 5th century BC. Notably, it was Protagoras who coined the phrase, "Man is the measure of all things: of things which are, that they are, and of things which are not, that they are not." The thinking of the Sophists is mainly known through their opponent, Plato. In a paraphrase from Plato's dialogue Theaetetus, Protagoras said: "What is true for you is true for you, and what is true for me is true for me."[25][26][27]

Modern

[edit]
Bernard Crick
[edit]

Bernard Crick, a British political scientist and advocate of relativism, suggested in In Defence of Politics (1962) that moral conflict between people is inevitable. He thought that only ethics can resolve such conflict, and when that occurs in public it results in politics. Accordingly, Crick saw the process of dispute resolution, harms reduction, mediation or peacemaking as central to all of moral philosophy. He became an important influence on feminists and later on the Greens.

Paul Feyerabend
[edit]

Philosopher of science Paul Feyerabend is often considered to be a relativist, although he denied being one.[28]

Feyerabend argued that modern science suffers from being methodologically monistic (the belief that only a single methodology can produce scientific progress).[29] Feyerabend summarises his case in Against Method with the phrase "anything goes".[30]

In an aphorism [Feyerabend] often repeated, "potentially every culture is all cultures". This is intended to convey that world views are not hermetically closed, since their leading concepts have an "ambiguity" - better, an open-endedness - which enables people from other cultures to engage with them. [...] It follows that relativism, understood as the doctrine that truth is relative to closed systems, can get no purchase. [...] For Feyerabend, both hermetic relativism and its absolutist rival [realism] serve, in their different ways, to "devalue human existence". The former encourages that unsavoury brand of political correctness which takes the refusal to criticise "other cultures" to the extreme of condoning murderous dictatorship and barbaric practices. The latter, especially in its favoured contemporary form of "scientific realism", with the excessive prestige it affords to the abstractions of "the monster 'science'", is in bed with a politics which likewise disdains variety, richness and everyday individuality - a politics which likewise "hides" its norms behind allegedly neutral facts, "blunts choices and imposes laws".[31]
Thomas Kuhn
[edit]

Thomas Kuhn's philosophy of science, as expressed in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, is often interpreted as relativistic. He claimed that, as well as progressing steadily and incrementally ("normal science"), science undergoes periodic revolutions or "paradigm shifts", leaving scientists working in different paradigms with difficulty in even communicating. Thus the truth of a claim, or the existence of a posited entity, is relative to the paradigm employed. However, it is not necessary for him to embrace relativism because every paradigm presupposes the prior, building upon itself through history and so on. This leads to there being a fundamental, incremental, and referential structure of development which is not relative but again, fundamental.

From these remarks, one thing is however certain: Kuhn is not saying that incommensurable theories cannot be compared - what they can't be is compared in terms of a system of common measure. He very plainly says that they can be compared, and he reiterates this repeatedly in later work, in a (mostly in vain) effort to avert the crude and sometimes catastrophic misinterpretations he suffered from mainstream philosophers and post-modern relativists alike.[32]

But Kuhn rejected the accusation of being a relativist later in his postscript:

scientific development is ... a unidirectional and irreversible process. Later scientific theories are better than earlier ones for solving puzzles ... That is not a relativist's position, and it displays the sense in which I am a convinced believer in scientific progress.[33]

Some have argued that one can also read Kuhn's work as essentially positivist in its ontology: the revolutions he posits are epistemological, lurching toward a presumably 'better' understanding of an objective reality through the lens presented by the new paradigm. However, a number of passages in Structure do indeed appear to be distinctly relativist, and to directly challenge the notion of an objective reality and the ability of science to progress towards an ever-greater grasp of it, particularly through the process of paradigm change.

In the sciences there need not be progress of another sort. We may, to be more precise, have to relinquish the notion, explicit or implicit, that changes of paradigm carry scientists and those who learn from them closer and closer to the truth.[34]
We are all deeply accustomed to seeing science as the one enterprise that draws constantly nearer to some goal set by nature in advance. But need there be any such goal? Can we not account for both science's existence and its success in terms of evolution from the community's state of knowledge at any given time? Does it really help to imagine that there is some one full, objective, true account of nature and that the proper measure of scientific achievement is the extent to which it brings us closer to that ultimate goal?[35]
George Lakoff and Mark Johnson
[edit]

George Lakoff and Mark Johnson define relativism in Metaphors We Live By as the rejection of both subjectivism and metaphysical objectivism in order to focus on the relationship between them, i.e. the metaphor by which we relate our current experience to our previous experience. In particular, Lakoff and Johnson characterize "objectivism" as a "straw man", and, to a lesser degree, criticize the views of Karl Popper, Kant and Aristotle.[page needed]

Robert Nozick
[edit]

In his book Invariances, Robert Nozick expresses a complex set of theories about the absolute and the relative. He thinks the absolute/relative distinction should be recast in terms of an invariant/variant distinction, where there are many things a proposition can be invariant with regard to or vary with. He thinks it is coherent for truth to be relative, and speculates that it might vary with time. He thinks necessity is an unobtainable notion, but can be approximated by robust invariance across a variety of conditions—although we can never identify a proposition that is invariant with regard to everything. Finally, he is not particularly warm to one of the most famous forms of relativism, moral relativism, preferring an evolutionary account.

Joseph Margolis
[edit]

Joseph Margolis advocates a view he calls "robust relativism" and defends it in his books Historied Thought, Constructed World, Chapter 4 (California, 1995) and The Truth about Relativism (Blackwell, 1991). He opens his account by stating that our logics should depend on what we take to be the nature of the sphere to which we wish to apply our logics. Holding that there can be no distinctions which are not "privileged" between the alethic, the ontic, and the epistemic, he maintains that a many-valued logic just might be the most apt for aesthetics or history since, because in these practices, we are loath to hold to simple binary logic; and he also holds that many-valued logic is relativistic. (This is perhaps an unusual definition of "relativistic". Compare with his comments on "relationism".) To say that "True" and "False" are mutually exclusive and exhaustive judgements on Hamlet, for instance, really does seem absurd. A many-valued logic—with its values "apt", "reasonable", "likely", and so on—seems intuitively more applicable to interpreting Hamlet. Where apparent contradictions arise between such interpretations, we might call the interpretations "incongruent", rather than dubbing either of them "false", because using many-valued logic implies that a measured value is a mixture of two extreme possibilities. Using the subset of many-valued logic, fuzzy logic, it can be said that various interpretations can be represented by membership in more than one possible truth set simultaneously. Fuzzy logic is therefore probably the best mathematical structure for understanding "robust relativism" and has been interpreted by Bart Kosko as philosophically being related to Zen Buddhism.

It was Aristotle who held that relativism implies that we should, sticking with appearances only, end up contradicting ourselves somewhere if we could apply all attributes to all ousiai (beings). Aristotle, however, made non-contradiction dependent upon his essentialism. If his essentialism is false, then so too is his ground for disallowing relativism. (Subsequent philosophers have found other reasons for supporting the principle of non-contradiction.)[clarification needed]

Beginning with Protagoras and invoking Charles Sanders Peirce, Margolis shows that the historic struggle to discredit relativism is an attempt to impose an unexamined belief in the world's essentially rigid rule-like nature. Plato and Aristotle merely attacked "relationalism"—the doctrine of true for l or true for k, and the like, where l and k are different speakers or different worlds—or something similar (most philosophers would call this position "relativism"). For Margolis, "true" means true; that is, the alethic use of "true" remains untouched. However, in real world contexts, and context is ubiquitous in the real world, we must apply truth values. Here, in epistemic terms, we might tout court retire "true" as an evaluation and keep "false". The rest of our value-judgements could be graded from "extremely plausible" down to "false". Judgements which on a bivalent logic would be incompatible or contradictory are further seen as "incongruent", although one may well have more weight than the other. In short, relativistic logic is not, or need not be, the bugbear it is often presented to be. It may simply be the best type of logic to apply to certain very uncertain spheres of real experiences in the world (although some sort of logic needs to be applied in order to make that judgement). Those who swear by bivalent logic might simply be the ultimate keepers of the great fear of the flux.[citation needed]

Richard Rorty
[edit]

Philosopher Richard Rorty has a somewhat paradoxical role in the debate over relativism: he is criticized for his relativistic views by many commentators, but has always denied that relativism applies to much anybody, being nothing more than a Platonic scarecrow. Rorty claims, rather, that he is a pragmatist, and that to construe pragmatism as relativism is to beg the question.

'"Relativism" is the traditional epithet applied to pragmatism by realists'[36]
'"Relativism" is the view that every belief on a certain topic, or perhaps about any topic, is as good as every other. No one holds this view. Except for the occasional cooperative freshman, one cannot find anybody who says that two incompatible opinions on an important topic are equally good. The philosophers who get called 'relativists' are those who say that the grounds for choosing between such opinions are less algorithmic than had been thought.'[37]
'In short, my strategy for escaping the self-referential difficulties into which "the Relativist" keeps getting himself is to move everything over from epistemology and metaphysics into cultural politics, from claims to knowledge and appeals to self-evidence to suggestions about what we should try.'[38]

Rorty takes a deflationary attitude to truth, believing there is nothing of interest to be said about truth in general, including the contention that it is generally subjective. He also argues that the notion of warrant or justification can do most of the work traditionally assigned to the concept of truth, and that justification is relative; justification is justification to an audience, for Rorty.

In Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity he argues that the debate between so-called relativists and so-called objectivists is beside the point because they do not have enough premises in common for either side to prove anything to the other.

Nalin de Silva
[edit]

In his book Mage Lokaya (My World), 1986, Nalin de Silva criticized the basis of the established western system of knowledge, and its propagation, which he refers as "domination throughout the world".He explained in this book that mind independent reality is impossible and knowledge is not found but constructed. Further he has introduced and developed the concept of "Constructive Relativism" as the basis on which knowledge is constructed relative to the sense organs, culture and the mind completely based on Avidya.[39]

Postmodernism

[edit]

The term "relativism" often comes up in debates over postmodernism, poststructuralism and phenomenology. Critics of these perspectives often identify advocates with the label "relativism". For example, the Sapir–Whorf hypothesis is often considered a relativist view because it posits that linguistic categories and structures shape the way people view the world. Stanley Fish has defended postmodernism and relativism.[40]

These perspectives do not strictly count as relativist in the philosophical sense, because they express agnosticism on the nature of reality and make epistemological rather than ontological claims. Nevertheless, the term is useful to differentiate them from realists who believe that the purpose of philosophy, science, or literary critique is to locate externally true meanings. Important philosophers and theorists such as Michel Foucault, Max Stirner, political movements such as post-anarchism or post-Marxism can also be considered as relativist in this sense - though a better term might be social constructivist.

The spread and popularity of this kind of "soft" relativism varies between academic disciplines. It has wide support in anthropology and has a majority following in cultural studies. It also has advocates in political theory and political science, sociology, and continental philosophy (as distinct from Anglo-American analytical philosophy). It has inspired empirical studies of the social construction of meaning such as those associated with labelling theory, which defenders can point to as evidence of the validity of their theories (albeit risking accusations of performative contradiction in the process). Advocates of this kind of relativism often also claim that recent developments in the natural sciences, such as Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, quantum mechanics, chaos theory and complexity theory show that science is now becoming relativistic. However, many scientists who use these methods continue to identify as realist or post-positivist, and some sharply criticize the association.[41][42]

Religious

[edit]

Buddhism

[edit]

Madhyamaka Buddhism, which forms the basis for many Mahayana Buddhist schools and which was founded by Nāgārjuna.[43] Nāgārjuna taught the idea of relativity. In the Ratnāvalī, he gives the example that shortness exists only in relation to the idea of length. The determination of a thing or object is only possible in relation to other things or objects, especially by way of contrast. He held that the relationship between the ideas of "short" and "long" is not due to intrinsic nature (svabhāva). This idea is also found in the Pali Nikāyas and Chinese Āgamas, in which the idea of relativity is expressed similarly: "That which is the element of light ... is seen to exist on account of [in relation to] darkness; that which is the element of good is seen to exist on account of bad; that which is the element of space is seen to exist on account of form."[44]

Madhyamaka Buddhism discerns two levels of truth: relative and ultimate. The two truths doctrine states that there are Relative or conventional, common-sense truth, which describes our daily experience of a concrete world, and Ultimate truth, which describes the ultimate reality as sunyata, empty of concrete and inherent characteristics. Conventional truth may be understood, in contrast, as "obscurative truth" or "that which obscures the true nature". It is constituted by the appearances of mistaken awareness. Conventional truth would be the appearance that includes a duality of apprehender and apprehended, and objects perceived within that. Ultimate truth is the phenomenal world free from the duality of apprehender and apprehended.[45]

Catholicism

[edit]

The Catholic Church, especially under John Paul II and Pope Benedict XVI, has identified relativism as one of the most significant problems for faith and morals today.[46]

According to the Church and to some theologians,[who?] relativism, as a denial of absolute truth, leads to moral license and a denial of the possibility of sin and of God. Whether moral or epistemological, relativism constitutes a denial of the capacity of the human mind and reason to arrive at truth. Truth, according to Catholic theologians and philosophers (following Aristotle) consists of adequatio rei et intellectus, the correspondence of the mind and reality. Another way of putting it states that the mind has the same form as reality. This means when the form of the computer in front of someone (the type, color, shape, capacity, etc.) is also the form that is in their mind, then what they know is true because their mind corresponds to objective reality.

The denial of an absolute reference, of an axis mundi, denies God, who equates to Absolute Truth, according to these Christian theologians. They link relativism to secularism, an obstruction of religion in human life.

Leo XIII
[edit]

Pope Leo XIII (1810–1903) was the first known Pope to use the word "relativism", in his encyclical Humanum genus (1884). Leo condemned Freemasonry and claimed that its philosophical and political system was largely based on relativism.[47]

John Paul II
[edit]

John Paul II wrote in Veritatis Splendor

As is immediately evident, the crisis of truth is not unconnected with this development. Once the idea of a universal truth about the good, knowable by human reason, is lost, inevitably the notion of conscience also changes. Conscience is no longer considered in its primordial reality as an act of a person's intelligence, the function of which is to apply the universal knowledge of the good in a specific situation and thus to express a judgment about the right conduct to be chosen here and now. Instead, there is a tendency to grant to the individual conscience the prerogative of independently determining the criteria of good and evil and then acting accordingly. Such an outlook is quite congenial to an individualist ethic, wherein each individual is faced with his own truth, different from the truth of others. Taken to its extreme consequences, this individualism leads to a denial of the very idea of human nature.

In Evangelium Vitae (The Gospel of Life), he says:

Freedom negates and destroys itself, and becomes a factor leading to the destruction of others, when it no longer recognizes and respects its essential link with the truth. When freedom, out of a desire to emancipate itself from all forms of tradition and authority, shuts out even the most obvious evidence of an objective and universal truth, which is the foundation of personal and social life, then the person ends up by no longer taking as the sole and indisputable point of reference for his own choices the truth about good and evil, but only his subjective and changeable opinion or, indeed, his selfish interest and whim.
Benedict XVI
[edit]

In April 2005, in his homily during Mass prior to the conclave which would elect him as Pope, then Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger talked about the world "moving towards a dictatorship of relativism":

How many winds of doctrine we have known in recent decades, how many ideological currents, how many ways of thinking. The small boat of thought of many Christians has often been tossed about by these waves – thrown from one extreme to the other: from Marxism to liberalism, even to libertinism; from collectivism to radical individualism; from atheism to a vague religious mysticism; from agnosticism to syncretism, and so forth. Every day new sects are created and what Saint Paul says about human trickery comes true, with cunning which tries to draw those into error (cf Ephesians 4, 14). Having a clear Faith, based on the Creed of the Church, is often labeled today as a fundamentalism. Whereas, relativism, which is letting oneself be tossed and "swept along by every wind of teaching", looks like the only attitude acceptable to today's standards. We are moving towards a dictatorship of relativism which does not recognize anything as certain and which has as its highest goal one's own ego and one's own desires. However, we have a different goal: the Son of God, true man. He is the measure of true humanism. Being an "Adult" means having a faith which does not follow the waves of today's fashions or the latest novelties. A faith which is deeply rooted in friendship with Christ is adult and mature. It is this friendship which opens us up to all that is good and gives us the knowledge to judge true from false, and deceit from truth.[48]

On June 6, 2005, Pope Benedict XVI told educators:

Today, a particularly insidious obstacle to the task of education is the massive presence in our society and culture of that relativism which, recognizing nothing as definitive, leaves as the ultimate criterion only the self with its desires. And under the semblance of freedom it becomes a prison for each one, for it separates people from one another, locking each person into his or her own 'ego'.[49]

Then during the World Youth Day in August 2005, he also traced to relativism the problems produced by the communist and sexual revolutions, and provided a counter-counter argument.[50]

In the last century we experienced revolutions with a common programme–expecting nothing more from God, they assumed total responsibility for the cause of the world in order to change it. And this, as we saw, meant that a human and partial point of view was always taken as an absolute guiding principle. Absolutizing what is not absolute but relative is called totalitarianism. It does not liberate man, but takes away his dignity and enslaves him. It is not ideologies that save the world, but only a return to the living God, our Creator, the Guarantor of our freedom, the Guarantor of what is really good and true.[citation needed]
Pope Francis
[edit]

Pope Francis refers in Evangelii gaudium to two forms of relativism, "doctrinal relativism" and a "practical relativism" typical of "our age".[51] The latter is allied to "widespread indifference" to systems of belief.[52]

Jainism

[edit]

Mahavira (599-527 BC), the 24th Tirthankara of Jainism, developed a philosophy known as Anekantavada. John Koller describes anekāntavāda as "epistemological respect for view of others" about the nature of existence, whether it is "inherently enduring or constantly changing", but "not relativism; it does not mean conceding that all arguments and all views are equal".[53]

Sikhism

[edit]

In Sikhism the Gurus (spiritual teachers) have propagated the message of "many paths" leading to the one God and ultimate salvation for all souls who tread on the path of righteousness. They have supported the view that proponents of all faiths can, by doing good and virtuous deeds and by remembering the Lord, certainly achieve salvation. The students of the Sikh faith are told to accept all leading faiths as possible vehicles for attaining spiritual enlightenment provided the faithful study, ponder and practice the teachings of their prophets and leaders. The holy book of the Sikhs called the Sri Guru Granth Sahib says: "Do not say that the Vedas, the Bible and the Koran are false. Those who do not contemplate them are false." Guru Granth Sahib page 1350;[54] later stating: "The seconds, minutes, and hours, days, weeks and months, and the various seasons originate from the one Sun; O nanak, in just the same way, the many forms originate from the Creator." Guru Granth Sahib page 12,13.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, [1] "The label “relativism” has been attached to a wide range of ideas and positions which may explain the lack of consensus on how the term should be defined."
  2. ^ Maria Baghramian identifies 16 (Relativism, 2004, Baghramian)
  3. ^ Swoyer, Chris (February 22, 2003). "Relativism". Retrieved May 10, 2010.
  4. ^ "Epistemic Relativism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 6 July 2020.
  5. ^ Ahearn, Laura M. (2012). Living language : an introduction to linguistic anthropology. Chichester, West Sussex, U.K. p. 69. ISBN 978-1-4443-4056-3. OCLC 729731177.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  6. ^ Baghramian, Maria and Carter, Adam, "Relativism", "The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition)", Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/relativism/#RelAboTruAleRel/ "Relativism about truth, or alethic relativism, at its simplest, is the claim that what is true for one individual or social group may not be true for another"
  7. ^ "Relativism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
  8. ^ Collins, Harry (1998-04-01). "What's wrong with relativism?". Physics World. Bristol, UK: IOP Publishing. Retrieved 2008-04-16. ...methodological relativism - impartial assessment of how knowledge develops - is the key idea for sociology of scientific knowledge...
  9. ^ Carey, Daniel (2005). Locke, Shaftesbury, and Hutcheson: Contesting Diversity in the Enlightenment and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781139447904.
  10. ^ "Methodological and Philosophical Relativism by Gananath Obeyesekere". JSTOR 2796798.
  11. ^ Brown, Donald E. (1991). Human Universals. McGraw-Hill. ISBN 0-87722-841-8.
  12. ^ "Relativism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2022.
  13. ^ & Jurists website: Reasonable doubt v balance of probability
  14. ^ Baghramian, M. Relativism, 2004, p43
  15. ^ "Interview with Bruno LatourOn Relativism, Pragmatism, and Critical Theory" (PDF).
  16. ^ Baghramian, M. Relativism, 2004, p85
  17. ^ "Craig Rusbult. Reality 101".
  18. ^ Keith Dixon. Is Cultural Relativism Self-Refuting? (British Journal of Sociology, vol 28, No. 1)
  19. ^ "Cultural Relativism at All About Philosophy".
  20. ^ The God Delusion, Chapter 6
  21. ^ Mere Christianity, Chapter 1
  22. ^ "Richard Dawkins quoted in Dawkins' Christmas card list; Dawkins at the Hay Festival, The Guardian, 28 May 2007". TheGuardian.com. 28 May 2007.
  23. ^ Baghramian, M. Relativism, 2004
  24. ^ Including Julien Beillard, who presents his case on the impossibility of moral relativism in the July 2013 issue of Philosophy Now magazine, accessible here
  25. ^ Richard Austin Gudmundsen (2000). Scientific Inquiry: Applied to the Doctrine of Jesus Christ. Cedar Fort. p. 50. ISBN 978-1-55517-497-2. Retrieved 2011-01-24.
  26. ^ Sahakian, William S.; Mabel Lewis Sahakian (1993). Ideas of the great philosophers. Barnes & Noble Publishing. p. 28. ISBN 978-1-56619-271-2. What is true for you is true for you.
  27. ^ Sahakian, W. S.; M. L. Sahakian (1965). Realms of philosophy. Schenkman Pub. Co. p. 40. Retrieved 2011-01-24.
  28. ^ "Cooper, David E., "Voodoo and the monster of science", Times Higher Education, 17 March 2000". 17 March 2000.
  29. ^ Lloyd, Elisabeth. "Feyerabend, Mill, and Pluralism", Philosophy of Science 64, p. S397.
  30. ^ Feyerabend, Against Method, 3rd ed., p. vii
  31. ^ "Cooper, David E., "Voodoo and the monster of science," Times Higher Education, 17 March 2000". 17 March 2000.
  32. ^ "Sharrock. W., Read R. Kuhn: Philosopher of Scientific Revolutions".
  33. ^ Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, p. 206.
  34. ^ Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, p. 170.
  35. ^ Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, p. 171.
  36. ^ Rorty, R. Consequences of Pragmatism
  37. ^ Richard Rorty, Pragmatism, Relativism, and Irrationalism
  38. ^ Rorty, R. Hilary Putnam and the Relativist Menace
  39. ^ "Constructive Relativism" (PDF). Archived (PDF) from the original on 2020-01-29.
  40. ^ Don't Blame Relativism Archived 2013-05-21 at the Wayback Machine as "serious thought"
  41. ^ "Sokal and the Science Wars".
  42. ^ "Quantum quackery". January 1997.
  43. ^ Garfield, Jay L. (2015). Engaging Buddhism: Why it Matters in Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford U.P. ISBN 978-0-19-020434-1.
  44. ^ David Kalupahana, Causality: The Central Philosophy of Buddhism. The University Press of Hawaii, 1975, pp. 96–97. In the Nikayas the quote is found at SN 2.150.
  45. ^ Levinson, Jules (August 2006) Lotsawa Times Volume II Archived 2008-07-24 at the Wayback Machine
  46. ^ "World Youth Day News August August 21, 2005".
  47. ^ "Humanum genus".
  48. ^ "Mass "Pro Eligendo Romano Pontifice": Homily of Card. Joseph Ratzinger".
  49. ^ "Inaugural Address at the Ecclesial Diocesan Convention of Rome".
  50. ^ "20th World Youth Day - Cologne - Marienfeld, Youth Vigil".
  51. ^ Pope Francis, Evangelii gaudium, paragraph 80, published 24 November 2013, accessed 14 January 2024
  52. ^ Olsen, C. E., A helpful summary of the Apostolic Exhortation, "Evangelii Gaudium", The Catholic World Report, published 26 November 2013, accessed 14 January 2024
  53. ^ John Koller (2004). Tara Sethia (ed.). Ahimsā, Anekānta, and Jainism. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 88–89. ISBN 978-81-208-2036-4.
  54. ^ "Guru Granth Sahib page 1350".

Bibliography

[edit]
[edit]