Jump to content

Noumenon: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Rashad9607 (talk | contribs)
 
(707 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Object or event that exists independently of the senses}}
{{unreferenced}}
{{about|the philosophical concept|other uses}}
{{Distinguish|Numinous}}
{{Related|[[Noema]]}}
{{use dmy dates|date=August 2023}}
In [[philosophy]], a '''noumenon''' ({{IPAc-en|ˈ|n|uː|m|ə|n|ɒ|n}}, {{IPAc-en|ˈ|n|aʊ|-}}; from {{langx|grc|νοούμενoν}}; {{plural form}}: '''noumena''') is knowledge<ref>{{cite book | chapter-url=https://plato.stanford.edu/search/r?entry=/entries/formal-epistemology/&page=1&total_hits=1035&pagesize=10&archive=None&rank=7&query=Epistemology | title=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy | chapter=Formal Epistemology | year=2021 | publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University }}</ref> posited as an [[Object (philosophy)|object]] that exists independently of human [[sense]].<ref>{{cite web|quote=1. intellectual conception of a thing as it is in itself, not as it is known through perception; 2. The of-itself-unknown and unknowable rational object, or thing-in-itself, which is distinguished from the phenomenon through which it is apprehended by the physical senses, and by which it is interpreted and understood;&nbsp;– so used in the philosophy of Kant and his followers.|url=http://www.websters-dictionary-online.org/definitions/Noumenon|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110928115535/http://www.websters-dictionary-online.org/definitions/Noumenon?cx=partner-pub-0939450753529744:v0qd01-tdlq&cof=FORID:9&ie=UTF-8&q=Noumenon&sa=Search|archive-date=2011-09-28|url-status=dead|title=Noumenon &#124; Definition of Noumenon by Webster's Online Dictionary|access-date=2015-09-10}}</ref> The term ''noumenon'' is generally used in contrast with, or in relation to, the term ''[[Phenomena (philosophy)|phenomenon]]'', which refers to any [[Object (philosophy)|object]] of the senses. [[Immanuel Kant]] first developed the notion of the noumenon as part of his [[transcendental idealism]], suggesting that while we know the noumenal world to exist because human [[sensibility]] is merely receptive, it is not itself sensible and must therefore remain otherwise [[Epistemology|unknowable]] to us.<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia|url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/noumenon|title=noumenon {{!}} philosophy|encyclopedia=Encyclopedia Britannica|access-date=2017-09-04|language=en}}</ref> In [[Kantianism|Kantian philosophy]], the noumenon is often associated with the unknowable "[[thing-in-itself]]" ({{langx|de|Ding an sich}}). However, the nature of the relationship between the two is not made explicit in Kant's work, and remains a subject of debate among Kant scholars as a result.


==Etymology==
The '''noumenon''' or ''thing in itself'' ([[German language|German]]: ''Ding [[an sich]]'') is a basic reality underlying observable [[phenomenon|phenomena]].
The [[Ancient Greek|Greek]] word {{langx|grc|νοούμενoν|nooúmenon|label=none}} (plural {{langx|grc|νοούμενα|nooúmena|label=none}}) is the [[Ancient Greek grammar#Participles|neuter middle-passive present participle]] of {{langx|grc|νοεῖν|noeîn|to think, to mean|label=none}}, which in turn originates from the word {{langx|grc|νοῦς|[[nous|noûs]]|label=none}}, an [[Attic Greek|Attic]] [[synaeresis|contracted]] form of {{langx|grc|[[wikt:νόος|νόος]]|nóos|perception, understanding, mind|label=none}}.{{efn|Ontology}}<ref>{{LSJ|noe/w|νοεῖν}}, {{LSJ|nou{{=}}s|νοῦς}}, {{LSJ|no/os|νόος|ref}}.</ref><ref>{{OEtymD|noumenon}}</ref> A rough equivalent in English would be "that which is thought", or "the object of an act of thought".


==Historical predecessors==
== Kant's usage ==
The Indian [[Vedānta]] philosophy (specifically [[Advaita]]), the roots of which go back to the [[Vedic period]], talks of the [[Ātman_(Hinduism)|ātman]] (self) in similar terms as the noumenon.<ref>{{cite book | chapter-url=https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/9783110226249.2.194/pdf | doi=10.1515/9783110226249.2.194 | chapter=9. Kant's Critical Concept of a Person: The Noumenal Sphere Grounding the Principle of Spirituality | title=Cultivating Personhood: Kant and Asian Philosophy | date=2010 | last1=Bickmann | first1=Claudia | pages=194–204 | isbn=978-3-11-022623-2 }}</ref>
The word came into its modern usage through [[Immanuel Kant]]. The [[etymology]] of the word derives from the [[Greek language|Greek]] ''nooúmenon'' (thought-of) and ultimately reflects ''nous'' (mind). ''Noumena'' is the plural form. Noumenon ("Ding an sich") is distinguished from [[phenomenon]] ("Erscheinung"), an observable event or physical manifestation, and the two words serve as interrelated technical terms in Kant's philosophy.


Regarding the equivalent concepts in [[Plato]], [[Ted Honderich]] writes: "[[Platonic form|Platonic Ideas and Forms]] are noumena, and phenomena are things displaying themselves to the senses... This dichotomy is the most characteristic feature of Plato's dualism; that noumena and the noumenal world are objects of the highest knowledge, truths, and values is Plato's principal legacy to philosophy."<ref>{{Cite book |editor-last=Honderich |editor-first=Ted |editor-link=Ted Honderich |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |url=https://archive.org/details/oxfordcompaniont00hond/page/657 |publisher=[[Oxford University Press]] |date=31 August 1995 |page=[https://archive.org/details/oxfordcompaniont00hond/page/657 657] |isbn=0198661320 |access-date=2014-10-28 |url-access=registration }}</ref>
Explaining the relationship between the ''noumenal'' and the ''phenomenal'' forms is one of the most difficult problems for Kant's philosophy. On Kant's view, as expressed in his ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]],'' reality is structured by "concepts of the understanding", or innate categories that the mind engages in order to make sense of raw unstructured experience. Since these categories include [[causality]] and number, it is problematic to say that many noumena exist or that they individually cause us to have perceptions of phenomena. But if the noumenal does not ''cause'' the phenomenal, then what is the relationship? The suggested answer is that the noumenal and phenomenal coexist simultaneously; we cannot say that either causes the other.


==Kantian noumena==
It can be said that for Kant, the noumenal realm is radically ''unknowable''—for when we employ a concept of some type to describe or categorize ''noumena'', we are in fact merely employing a way of describing or categorizing ''phenomena''. Kant posited a number of methods by which human beings make sense out of the interrelationships among phenomena: the concepts of the ''[[transcendental aesthetic]]'', as well as that of the ''[[transcendental analytic]]'', ''[[transcendental logic]]'' and ''[[transcendental deduction]]''. Taken together, they are Kant's description of the sum of human reasoning and use of language to describe the world in which we exist. In each instance the word "transcendental" refers to the process that the human mind uses to increasingly understand or grasp the form of, and order among, phenomena. Kant, here, is using a metaphor that is the opposite of "understand" ("to stand under"), saying instead that to "transcend" a direct observation or experience is to use reason and classifications (the forms of thought we engage in, including organizing and manipulating words and/or other symbolic representations) which strive to correlate with the phenomena we observe. By Kant's view, we can make sense out of phenomena in these various ways, but can never directly know the noumena, the "things-in-themselves," the actual objects and dynamics of the [[natural world]]. In other words, by Kant's ''Critique'', our minds may attempt to correlate in useful ways, perhaps even closely accurate ways, with the structure and order of the universe, but cannot know these "things" directly. Rather, we must infer the extent to which thoughts correspond with things by our further observations of the manifestations of those things that can be seen, heard, touched, smelled, tasted, and/or measured in some way by instrumentation, that is, of phenomena.
{{anchor|Kant's usage}}
===Overview===
As expressed in Kant's ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]],'' [[Understanding|human understanding]] is structured by "concepts of the understanding" or pure [[categories of understanding]], found prior to experience in the [[mind]] and which make outer experiences possible as counterpart to the [[rational]] faculties of the mind.<ref>Hanna, Robert (2009). [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-judgment/supplement2.html Completing the Picture of Kant's Metaphysics of Judgment]. ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''.</ref><ref>[http://www.science.uva.nl/~seop/entries/kant-metaphysics/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Kant's metaphysics].</ref>


By Kant's account, when one employs a concept to describe or categorize ''noumena'' (the objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis of the workings of the world), one is also employing a way of describing or categorizing ''phenomena'' (the observable manifestations of those objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis). Kant posited methods by which human understanding makes sense of and thus intuits phenomena that appear to the mind: the concepts of the ''[[transcendental aesthetic]]'', as well as that of the ''transcendental analytic'', ''[[transcendental logic]]'' and ''transcendental deduction''.<ref name="EOP, K2">''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ''ff''.</ref><ref name="EOP, K3">''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Transcendental Aesthetic", p. 310 ''ff''.</ref><ref name="EOP, K4">''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ''ff''.</ref> Taken together, Kant's "categories of understanding" are the principles of the human mind which necessarily are brought to bear in attempting to understand the world in which we [[Existence|exist]] (that is, to understand, or attempt to understand, "things in themselves"). In each instance the word "transcendental" refers to the process that the human mind must exercise to understand or grasp the form of, and order among, phenomena. Kant asserts that to "transcend" a direct observation or experience is to use reason and classifications to strive to correlate with the phenomena that are observed.{{Citation needed|date = February 2016}} Humans can make sense out of phenomena in these various ways, but in doing so can never know the "things-in-themselves", the actual objects and dynamics of the natural world in their noumenal dimension - this being the negative, correlate to phenomena and that which escapes the limits of human understanding. By Kant's Critique, our minds may attempt to correlate in useful ways, perhaps even closely accurate ways, with the structure and order of the various aspects of the universe, but cannot know these "things-in-themselves" (noumena) directly. Rather, we must infer the extent to which the human rational faculties can reach the object of "things-in-themselves" by our observations of the manifestations of those things that can be perceived via the physical senses, that is, of phenomena, and by ordering these perceptions in the mind help infer the validity of our perceptions to the rational categories used to understand them in a rational system. This rational system (''transcendental analytic''), being the categories of the understanding as free from empirical contingency.<ref>See, e.g., ''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ''ff''.</ref><ref>See also, e.g., ''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ''ff''.</ref>
The relationship between noumenon and phenomenon is further complicated by the way in which our minds have been constructed. According to Kant, objects of which we are sensibly cognizant are merely representations of ''unknown somethings''—what Kant refers to as the ''transcendental object''—as interpreted through the ''[[a priori]]'' or ''[[categories of the understanding]]''. These ''unknown somethings'' are manifested within the noumenon—although we can never know how or why as our perceptions of these ''unknown somethings'' are bound by the limitations of the ''categories of the understanding'' and we are therefore never able to apprehend the noumenon as it is actally manifest. It can be said that Kant is arguing that the ''categories of the understanding'' are required for our sensible apprehension of representations, and the noumenon is a prerequisite for the function of these ''categories''. The direct link, however, between the noumenon and phenomena is assumed to be naturally existing by Kant, but he has much difficulty explaining exactly why or how they are naturally linked—that is to say, how it is that our minds are naturally capable of interpreting the world. In short, his methodology categorizes the various modes of understanding without demonstrating the processes of understanding and how they are correlated with each other.


According to Kant, objects of which we are cognizant via the physical senses are merely representations of ''unknown somethings''—what Kant refers to as the ''transcendental object''—as interpreted through the ''[[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]'' or ''categories of the understanding''. These ''unknown somethings'' are manifested within the noumenon—although we can never know how or why as our perceptions of these ''unknown somethings'' via our physical senses are bound by the limitations of the ''categories of the understanding'' and we are therefore never able to fully know the "thing-in-itself".{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=A256/B312|p=27}}
==Criticisms==
=== Schopenhauer's critique ===
[[Schopenhauer]] claimed that [[Kant]] used the word incorrectly. He explained in "[[Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy]]", which first appeared as an appendix to ''[[The World as Will and Representation]]'':
<blockquote>"But it was just this difference between abstract knowledge and knowledge of perception, entirely overlooked by Kant, which the ancient philosophers denoted by [[noumena]] and [[phenomena]]. (See [[Sextus Empiricus]], ''[[Outlines of Pyrrhonism]]'', Book I, Chapter 13, '' ' What is thought (noumena) is opposed to what appears or is perceived (phenomena).' '') This contrast and utter disproportion greatly occupied these philosophers in the philosophemes of the [[Eleatics]], in [[Plato]]'s doctrine of the [[Idea#Plato|Ideas]], in the [[dialectic]] of the [[Megarics]], and later the [[scholastics]] in the dispute between [[nominalism]] and [[realism]], whose seed, so late in developing, was already contained in the opposite mental tendencies of Plato and [[Aristotle]]. But Kant who, in an unwarrantable manner, entirely neglected the thing for the expression of which those words ''phenomena'' and ''noumena'' had already been taken, now takes possession of the words, as if they were still unclaimed, in order to denote by them his things-in-themselves and his phenomena." (vol. 1, Dover edition 1966, ISBN 0-486-21761-2 p. 476)</blockquote>


===Noumenon and the thing-in-itself===
=== Nietzsche's critique ===
[[Nietzsche]], having been profoundly influenced by Schopenhauer's work, went on to criticise Kant's noumenon on slightly different grounds; he later similarly criticised Schopenhauer's work: he found fault in the noumenon's lack of definite properties and its complete inability to [[interact]] with other things. Nietzsche argued that a thing in itself would necessarily be outside of any [[causal chain]] since it cannot interact with any other things without demonstrating other [[properties]] than being the "ground of being". He and later philosophers argued that the noumenon is of an utterly [[Indeterminacy (Philosophy)|indeterminate]] nature and that any discussion that does not treat it as such thus cannot, in fact, be a discussion of the noumenon. In demonstrating any definite properties, the noumenon would cease to be so.


Many accounts of Kant's philosophy treat "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" as synonymous, and there is textual evidence for this relationship.<ref>Immanuel Kant (1781) ''Critique of Pure Reason,'' for example in A254/B310, p. 362 (Guyer and Wood), "The concept of a '''noumenon''', i.e., of a thing that is not to be thought of as an object of the senses but rather as a thing-in-itself [...]"; But note that the terms are not used interchangeably throughout. The first reference to ''thing-in-itself'' comes many pages (A30) before the first reference to '''noumenon''' (A250). For a secondary or tertiary source, see: [http://www.britannica.com/eb/article-9056357/noumenon "Noumenon"] in the ''Encyclopædia Britannica''</ref> However, [[Stephen Palmquist]] holds that "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" are only ''loosely'' synonymous, inasmuch as they represent the same concept viewed from two different perspectives,<ref>"Noumenon: the name given to a thing when it is viewed as a transcendent object. The term 'negative noumenon' refers only to the recognition of something which is not an object of sensible intuition, while 'positive noumenon' refers to the (quite mistaken) attempt to know such a thing as an empirical object. These two terms are sometimes used loosely as synonyms for 'transcendental object' and 'thing-in-itself', respectively. (Cf. phenomenon.)"&nbsp;– [http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1/KSPglos.html Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms]</ref><ref>Thing-in-itself: an object considered transcendentally apart from all the conditions under which a subject can gain knowledge of it via the physical senses. Hence the thing-in-itself is, by definition, unknowable via the physical senses. Sometimes used loosely as a synonym of noumenon. (Cf. appearance.)"&nbsp;– [http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1/KSPglos.html Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms]. Palmquist defends his definitions of these terms in his article, "Six Perspectives on the Object in Kant's Theory of Knowledge", ''Dialectica'' 40:2 (1986), pp.121–151; revised and reprinted as Chapter VI in Palmquist's book, ''Kant's System of Perspectives'' (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).</ref> and other scholars also argue that they are not identical.<ref>[[Teodor Oizerman|Oizerman, T. I.]], "Kant's Doctrine of the "Things in Themselves" and Noumena", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 41, No. 3, Mar., 1981, 333–350; Karin de Boer, "Kant's Multi-Layered Conception of Things in Themselves, Transcendental Objects, and Monads", Kant-Studien 105/2, 2014, 221-260.</ref> [[Schopenhauer's criticism of the Kantian philosophy|Schopenhauer criticised Kant]] for changing the meaning of "noumenon". However, this opinion is far from unanimous.<ref>"Other interpreters have introduced an almost unending stream of varying suggestions as to how these terms ought to be used. A handful of examples will be sufficient to make this point clear, without any claim to represent an exhaustive overview. Perhaps the most commonly accepted view is expressed by Paulsen, who equates 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon', equates 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', distinguishes 'positive noumenon' and 'negative noumenon', and treats 'negative noumenon' as equivalent to 'transcendental object' [pp. 4:148-50, 154-5, 192]. Al-Azm and Wolff also seem satisfied to equate 'phenomenon' and 'appearance', though they both carefully distinguish 'thing-in-itself' from 'negative noumenon' and 'positive noumenon' [A4:520; W21:165, 313–5; s.a. W9:162]. Gotterbarn similarly equates the former pair, as well as 'thing-in-itself' and 'positive noumenon', but distinguishes between 'transcendental object', 'negative noumenon' and 'thing-in-itself' [G11: 201]. By contrast, Bird and George both distinguish between 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', but not between 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon' [B20:18,19, 53–7; G7:513-4n]; and Bird sometimes blurs the distinction between 'thing-in-itself' and 'transcendental object' as well.[2] Gram equates 'thing-in-itself' not with 'noumenon', but with 'phenomenon' [G13:1,5-6]! Allison cites different official meanings for each term, yet he tends to equate 'thing-in-itself' at times with 'negative noumenon' and at times with 'transcendental-object', usually ignoring the role of the 'positive noumenon' [A7:94; A10:58,69]. And Buchdahl responds to the fact that the thing-in-itself seems to be connected with each of the other object-terms by regarding it as 'Kant's umbrella term'.[3]" [http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1/KSP6A.html Stephen Palmquist on Kant's object terms]</ref> Kant's writings show points of difference between noumena and things-in-themselves. For instance, he regards things-in-themselves as existing:
Nietzscheanistic criticism of the noumenon found, for example, in his ''[[Beyond Good and Evil]]'', was arguably a precursor of the sort of scientific thought underlying later formulations of the [[scientific method]] in that both rely heavily on quantifiability, precise definition, and, above all, on falsifiability as a means of gaining knowledge, and in that both find fault with the noumenon's lack of quantifiability, observability, etc. While arguing against what he held to be the negative influence of the Kantian noumenon in the philosophy and science of his day, Nietzsche roughly approximated the scientific philosopher [[Karl Popper]]'s assertion that falsifiability was the basis of scientific knowledge:


<blockquote>
<blockquote>"Popper's account of the logical asymmetry between verification and falsification lies at the heart of his philosophy of science. It also inspired him to take falsifiability as his criterion of demarcation between what is and is not genuinely scientific: a theory should be considered scientific if and only if it is falsifiable,"[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Karl_Popper]</blockquote>
...though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears.{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=Bxxvi-xxvii}}
</blockquote>


He is much more doubtful about noumena:
while Nietzsche wrote in the eighteenth section of the first chapter of ''Beyond Good and Evil'' that
<blockquote>
But in that case a noumenon is not for our understanding a special [kind of] object, namely, an intelligible object; the [sort of] understanding to which it might belong is itself a problem. For we cannot in the least represent to ourselves the possibility of an understanding which should know its object, not discursively through categories, but intuitively in a non-sensible intuition.{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=A256, B312|p=273}}
</blockquote>


A crucial difference between the noumenon and the thing-in-itself is that to call something a noumenon is to claim a kind of knowledge, whereas Kant insisted that the thing-in-itself is unknowable. Interpreters have debated whether the latter claim makes sense: it seems to imply that we know at least one thing about the thing-in-itself (i.e., that it is unknowable). But Stephen Palmquist explains that this is part of Kant's definition of the term, to the extent that anyone who claims to have found a way of making the thing-in-itself knowable must be adopting a non-Kantian position.<ref>"The Radical Unknowability of Kant's 'Thing in Itself'", Cogito 3:2 (March 1985), pp.101–115; revised and reprinted as Appendix V in Stephen Palmquist, [http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1 Kant's System of Perspectives] (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).</ref>
<blockquote>"It is certainly not the least charm of a theory that it is refutable; it is precisely thereby that it attracts the more subtle minds."[http://www.gutenberg.org/dirs/etext03/bygdv10.txt]</blockquote>


===Positive and negative noumena===
=== Critique via [[Occam's razor]] ===
Kant also makes a distinction between ''positive'' and ''negative'' noumena:<ref>[http://hume.ucdavis.edu/mattey/phi175/phenomlec.html Mattey, G. J.]</ref><ref>[http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/APPEAR.HTM Lecture notes by G. J. Mattey] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100612165634/http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/APPEAR.HTM |date=2010-06-12 }}</ref>
Occam's razor would eliminate the thing in itself from an explanation of any [[observable]], quantifiable phenomenon whatsoever, since explanations of observable phenomena need not draw meaning from "descriptions" of inobservable ones.
<blockquote>
If by 'noumenon' we mean a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensible intuition, and so abstract from our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the ''negative'' sense of the term.{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=A250/B307|p=267 (NKS)}}
</blockquote>


<blockquote>
=== Criticism via the scientific method ===
But if we understand by it an object of a non-sensible intuition, we thereby presuppose a special mode of intuition, namely, the intellectual, which is not that which we possess, and of which we cannot comprehend even the possibility. This would be 'noumenon' in the ''positive'' sense of the term.{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=A250/B307|p=267 (NKS)}}
The [[scientific method]] similarly eliminates the thing in itself via attempting to construct an [[experiment]] to prove or disprove its existence. Since no aspect of an existent thing in itself could possibly be quantified, multiple observers couldn't ever be sure that they were looking at the same data "supporting" its existence, and thus no such experiment could possibly be replicated even if it could conceivably be formulated. Thus, experimental proof of the noumenon could not be demonstrated by anyone to anyone else, and there can never be any compelling [[evidence]] for its existence.
</blockquote>


The positive noumena, if they existed, would be immaterial entities that can only be apprehended by a special, non-sensory faculty: "intellectual intuition" (''nicht sinnliche [[Anschauung]]'').{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=A250/B307|p=267 (NKS)}} Kant doubts that we have such a faculty, because for him intellectual intuition would mean that thinking of an entity, and its being represented, would be the same. He argues that humans have no way to apprehend positive noumena:
== Influences on later philosophy ==
References to indeterminate things like the noumenon are widely scattered in philosophy. Discussions of "''l'art pour l'art''", for example, reflect a loop in the definition of art's purpose similar to the [[causal loop]] generated by a thing in itself. More importantly, [[qualia]] are things in themselves in that they are considered to be unquantifiable, indeterminate, indescribable, and, by their proponents, essential to consciousness (the "ground of being").
Any incommunicable feeling or any inexpressible thing would strongly relate to the idea of the noumenon in that all share this indeterminacy: discussions of "properties" of things in themselves are necessarily fruitless, since to bear any metaphorical fruit in such discussions the thing in itself would necessarily have to interact with observable phenomena. Any description of the noumenon, including Kant's, would be a [[property]] of it; it is always only descriptible in terms of observable phenomena.
[[Quantifiability]], or at least [[definition]], are essential to productive philosophical and scientific discussion; in its complete [[Indeterminacy (Philosophy)|indeterminacy]], the thing in itself was in the opinion of many modern philosophers one of the greatest blunders in Western philosophical thought.


<blockquote>
== Etymology ==
Since, however, such a type of intuition, intellectual intuition, forms no part whatsoever of our faculty of knowledge, it follows that the employment of the categories can never extend further than to the objects of experience. Doubtless, indeed, there are intelligible entities corresponding to the sensible entities; there may also be intelligible entities to which our sensible faculty of intuition has no relation whatsoever; but our concepts of understanding, being mere forms of thought for our sensible intuition, could not in the least apply to them. That, therefore, which we entitle 'noumenon' must be understood as being such only in a negative sense.{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=B309|p=270 (NKS)}}
"Noumenon" is the neuter form of the present passive participle of "noein", which in turn originates from "nous" (roughly, "mind"). Noumenon is linguistically unrelated to "[[numinous]]," a term coined by [[Rudolf Otto]] and based on the [[Latin]] [[numen]] (deity).
</blockquote>


===The noumenon as a limiting concept===
== External links ==
Even if noumena are unknowable, they are still needed as a ''limiting concept'',<ref>{{Cite journal|url=http://journals.cambridge.org/action/displayAbstract;jsessionid=295CBB027ADE6D31BEA8AAABA8A8D8DC.journals?&aid=8201604|last=Allison|first= H|title=Transcendental Realism, Empirical Realism, and Transcendental Idealism| journal=Kantian Review | year=2006 | volume=11 | pages=1–28 | doi=10.1017/S1369415400002223 | s2cid=171078596 }}</ref> Kant tells us. Without them, there would be only phenomena, and since potentially we have complete knowledge of our phenomena, we would in a sense know everything. In his own words:
*[http://www.geometricvisions.com/Madness/schizoaffective-disorder/reality.html The Reality Construction Kit], in which constructing a new phenomenal reality aids recovery from mental illness.


<blockquote>
== See also ==
Further, the concept of a noumenon is necessary, to prevent sensible intuition from being extended to things in themselves, and thus to limit the objective validity of sensible knowledge.{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=A253/B310}}
</blockquote>
<blockquote>
What our understanding acquires through this concept of a noumenon, is a negative extension; that is to say, understanding is not limited through sensibility; on the contrary, it itself limits sensibility by applying the term noumena to things in themselves (things not regarded as appearances). But in so doing it at the same time sets limits to itself, recognising that it cannot know these noumena through any of the categories, and that it must therefore think them only under the title of an unknown something.{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=A256/B312|p=273}}
</blockquote>


Furthermore, for Kant, the existence of a noumenal world limits reason to what he perceives to be its proper bounds, making many questions of traditional metaphysics, such as the existence of God, the soul, and free will unanswerable by reason. Kant derives this from his [[definition of knowledge]] as "the determination of given representations to an object".{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=B/137|p=156}} As there are no appearances of these entities in the phenomenal, Kant is able to make the claim that they cannot be known to a mind that works upon "such knowledge that has to do only with appearances".{{sfn|Kant|1999|loc=B/xx.|p=24}} These questions are ultimately the "proper object of faith, but not of reason".<ref>Rohmann, Chris. "Kant" ''A World of Ideas: A Dictionary of Important Theories, Concepts, Beliefs, and Thnkers.'' Ballantine Books, 1999.</ref>
* [[Unobservables]]

===The dual-object and dual-aspect interpretations===
Kantian scholars have long debated two contrasting interpretations of the thing-in-itself. One is the ''dual object'' view, according to which the thing-in-itself is an entity distinct from the phenomena to which it gives rise. The other is the ''dual aspect'' view, according to which the thing-in-itself and the thing-as-it-appears are two "sides" of the same thing. This view is supported by the textual fact that "Most occurrences of the phrase 'things-in-themselves' are shorthand for the phrase, 'things considered in themselves' (Dinge an sich selbst betrachtet)."<ref>{{cite web|url=http://hume.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/TIILEC.HTM|author=Mattey, GJ.|title=Lecture Notes on the Critique of Pure Reason}}</ref>
Although we cannot ''see'' things apart from the way we do in fact perceive them via the physical senses, we can ''think'' them apart from our mode of sensibility (physical perception); thus making the thing-in-itself a kind of noumenon or object of thought.

==Criticisms of Kant's noumenon==

===Pre-Kantian critique===
Though the term ''noumenon'' did not come into common usage until Kant, the idea that undergirds it, that matter has an absolute existence which causes it to emanate certain phenomena, had historically been subjected to criticism. [[George Berkeley]], who pre-dated Kant, asserted that matter, independent of an observant mind, is metaphysically impossible. Qualities associated with matter, such as shape, color, smell, texture, weight, temperature, and sound are all dependent on minds, which allow only for relative perception, not absolute perception. The complete absence of such minds (and more importantly an [[Omnipotence|omnipotent mind]]) would render those same qualities unobservable and even unimaginable. Berkeley called this philosophy [[immaterialism]]. Essentially there could be no such thing as matter without a mind.<ref>Anon., "Caird's Philosophy of Kant", [[Saturday Review (London newspaper)|''Saturday Review of Politics, Literature, Science and Art'']], vol 44, Nov 3, 1877, [https://books.google.com/books?id=t_-zm4WJVCQC&pg=PA559&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false pp. 559–560].</ref>{{rp|559–560}}

===Schopenhauer's critique===
[[Schopenhauer]] claimed that [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] used the word ''noumenon'' incorrectly. He explained in his "[[Critique of the Kantian philosophy]]", which first appeared as an appendix to ''[[The World as Will and Representation]]'':
<blockquote>
The difference between abstract and intuitive cognition, which Kant entirely overlooks, was the very one that ancient philosophers indicated as φαινόμενα [''phainomena''] and νοούμενα [''nooumena'']; the opposition and incommensurability between these terms proved very productive in the philosophemes of the [[Eleatics]], in [[Plato]]'s doctrine of [[Theory of forms|Ideas]], in the dialectic of the [[Megarics]], and later in the [[scholastics]], in the conflict between [[nominalism]] and [[Philosophical realism|realism]]. This latter conflict was the late development of a seed already present in the opposed tendencies of Plato and [[Aristotle]]. But Kant, who completely and irresponsibly neglected the issue for which the terms φαινομένα and νοούμενα were already in use, then took possession of the terms as if they were stray and ownerless, and used them as designations of [[Thing-in-itself|things in themselves]] and their appearances.<ref>{{cite book |last=Schopenhauer |first=Arthur |translator-last1=Norman |translator-first1=Judith |translator-last2=Welchman |translator-first2=Alistair |translator-last3=Janaway |translator-first3=Christopher |title=The World as Will and Representation, Volume 1 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2014 |location=Cambridge |page=506 |isbn= 9780521871846}}</ref>
</blockquote>

The noumenon's original meaning of "that which is thought" is not compatible with the "[[thing-in-itself]]," the latter being Kant's term for things as they exist apart from their existence as images in the mind of an observer.{{Citation needed|date=September 2015}} In a footnote to this passage, Schopenhauer provides the following passage from the ''Outlines of Pyrrhonism'' (Bk. I, ch. 13) of [[Sextus Empiricus]] to demonstrate the original distinction between phenomenon and noumenon according to ancient philosophers: νοούμενα φαινομένοις ἀντετίθη Ἀναξαγόρας ('Anaxagoras opposed what is thought to what appears.')

==See also==
{{cols|colwidth=21em}}
* [[Always already]]
* [[Anatta]]
* [[Condition of possibility]]
* [[Essence–energies distinction]]
* [[Haecceity]]
* [[Hypokeimenon]]
* [[Hypokeimenon]]
* [[Ineffability]]
* [[Master argument]] by [[George Berkeley]]
* [[Observation]]
* [[Qualia]]
* [[Schopenhauer's criticism of the Kantian philosophy]]
* [[Transcendental idealism]]
* [[Unobservable]]
{{colend}}

==Notes==
{{notelist}}

==References==
{{Reflist}}

==Bibliography==
* {{cite book |last=Kant|first=Immanuel|title=Critique of Pure Reason (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant)|year=1999|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0521657297 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=qqeX8MJurLkC}}


==External links==
{{Philosophy navigation}}
{{wiktionary}}
* [https://archive.org/details/surdofmetaphysic00caru ''The surd of metaphysics; an inquiry into the question: Are there things-in-themselves?'' (1903)] by [[Paul Carus]], 1852–1919


{{Philosophy topics}}
[[Category:Epistemology]]
{{Authority control}}
[[Category:Metaphysics]]
[[Category:Philosophical concepts]]
[[Category:Philosophical terminology]]


[[Category:Concepts in metaphysics]]
[[ar:نومينون]]
[[Category:Kantianism]]
[[bg:Ноумен]]
[[cs:Noumenon]]
[[de:Noumenon]]
[[es:Noúmeno]]
[[eo:Noumeno]]
[[fr:Noumène]]
[[it:Noumeno]]
[[nl:Ding an sich]]
[[pl:Rzecz sama w sobie]]
[[ru:Ноумен]]
[[fi:An sich]]
[[sv:Tinget i sig]]
[[tr:Noumenon]]

Latest revision as of 13:45, 28 December 2024

In philosophy, a noumenon (/ˈnmənɒn/, /ˈn-/; from Ancient Greek: νοούμενoν; pl.: noumena) is knowledge[1] posited as an object that exists independently of human sense.[2] The term noumenon is generally used in contrast with, or in relation to, the term phenomenon, which refers to any object of the senses. Immanuel Kant first developed the notion of the noumenon as part of his transcendental idealism, suggesting that while we know the noumenal world to exist because human sensibility is merely receptive, it is not itself sensible and must therefore remain otherwise unknowable to us.[3] In Kantian philosophy, the noumenon is often associated with the unknowable "thing-in-itself" (German: Ding an sich). However, the nature of the relationship between the two is not made explicit in Kant's work, and remains a subject of debate among Kant scholars as a result.

Etymology

[edit]

The Greek word νοούμενoν, nooúmenon (plural νοούμενα, nooúmena) is the neuter middle-passive present participle of νοεῖν, noeîn, 'to think, to mean', which in turn originates from the word νοῦς, noûs, an Attic contracted form of νόος, nóos, 'perception, understanding, mind'.[a][4][5] A rough equivalent in English would be "that which is thought", or "the object of an act of thought".

Historical predecessors

[edit]

The Indian Vedānta philosophy (specifically Advaita), the roots of which go back to the Vedic period, talks of the ātman (self) in similar terms as the noumenon.[6]

Regarding the equivalent concepts in Plato, Ted Honderich writes: "Platonic Ideas and Forms are noumena, and phenomena are things displaying themselves to the senses... This dichotomy is the most characteristic feature of Plato's dualism; that noumena and the noumenal world are objects of the highest knowledge, truths, and values is Plato's principal legacy to philosophy."[7]

Kantian noumena

[edit]

Overview

[edit]

As expressed in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, human understanding is structured by "concepts of the understanding" or pure categories of understanding, found prior to experience in the mind and which make outer experiences possible as counterpart to the rational faculties of the mind.[8][9]

By Kant's account, when one employs a concept to describe or categorize noumena (the objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis of the workings of the world), one is also employing a way of describing or categorizing phenomena (the observable manifestations of those objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis). Kant posited methods by which human understanding makes sense of and thus intuits phenomena that appear to the mind: the concepts of the transcendental aesthetic, as well as that of the transcendental analytic, transcendental logic and transcendental deduction.[10][11][12] Taken together, Kant's "categories of understanding" are the principles of the human mind which necessarily are brought to bear in attempting to understand the world in which we exist (that is, to understand, or attempt to understand, "things in themselves"). In each instance the word "transcendental" refers to the process that the human mind must exercise to understand or grasp the form of, and order among, phenomena. Kant asserts that to "transcend" a direct observation or experience is to use reason and classifications to strive to correlate with the phenomena that are observed.[citation needed] Humans can make sense out of phenomena in these various ways, but in doing so can never know the "things-in-themselves", the actual objects and dynamics of the natural world in their noumenal dimension - this being the negative, correlate to phenomena and that which escapes the limits of human understanding. By Kant's Critique, our minds may attempt to correlate in useful ways, perhaps even closely accurate ways, with the structure and order of the various aspects of the universe, but cannot know these "things-in-themselves" (noumena) directly. Rather, we must infer the extent to which the human rational faculties can reach the object of "things-in-themselves" by our observations of the manifestations of those things that can be perceived via the physical senses, that is, of phenomena, and by ordering these perceptions in the mind help infer the validity of our perceptions to the rational categories used to understand them in a rational system. This rational system (transcendental analytic), being the categories of the understanding as free from empirical contingency.[13][14]

According to Kant, objects of which we are cognizant via the physical senses are merely representations of unknown somethings—what Kant refers to as the transcendental object—as interpreted through the a priori or categories of the understanding. These unknown somethings are manifested within the noumenon—although we can never know how or why as our perceptions of these unknown somethings via our physical senses are bound by the limitations of the categories of the understanding and we are therefore never able to fully know the "thing-in-itself".[15]

Noumenon and the thing-in-itself

[edit]

Many accounts of Kant's philosophy treat "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" as synonymous, and there is textual evidence for this relationship.[16] However, Stephen Palmquist holds that "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" are only loosely synonymous, inasmuch as they represent the same concept viewed from two different perspectives,[17][18] and other scholars also argue that they are not identical.[19] Schopenhauer criticised Kant for changing the meaning of "noumenon". However, this opinion is far from unanimous.[20] Kant's writings show points of difference between noumena and things-in-themselves. For instance, he regards things-in-themselves as existing:

...though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears.[21]

He is much more doubtful about noumena:

But in that case a noumenon is not for our understanding a special [kind of] object, namely, an intelligible object; the [sort of] understanding to which it might belong is itself a problem. For we cannot in the least represent to ourselves the possibility of an understanding which should know its object, not discursively through categories, but intuitively in a non-sensible intuition.[22]

A crucial difference between the noumenon and the thing-in-itself is that to call something a noumenon is to claim a kind of knowledge, whereas Kant insisted that the thing-in-itself is unknowable. Interpreters have debated whether the latter claim makes sense: it seems to imply that we know at least one thing about the thing-in-itself (i.e., that it is unknowable). But Stephen Palmquist explains that this is part of Kant's definition of the term, to the extent that anyone who claims to have found a way of making the thing-in-itself knowable must be adopting a non-Kantian position.[23]

Positive and negative noumena

[edit]

Kant also makes a distinction between positive and negative noumena:[24][25]

If by 'noumenon' we mean a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensible intuition, and so abstract from our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the negative sense of the term.[26]

But if we understand by it an object of a non-sensible intuition, we thereby presuppose a special mode of intuition, namely, the intellectual, which is not that which we possess, and of which we cannot comprehend even the possibility. This would be 'noumenon' in the positive sense of the term.[26]

The positive noumena, if they existed, would be immaterial entities that can only be apprehended by a special, non-sensory faculty: "intellectual intuition" (nicht sinnliche Anschauung).[26] Kant doubts that we have such a faculty, because for him intellectual intuition would mean that thinking of an entity, and its being represented, would be the same. He argues that humans have no way to apprehend positive noumena:

Since, however, such a type of intuition, intellectual intuition, forms no part whatsoever of our faculty of knowledge, it follows that the employment of the categories can never extend further than to the objects of experience. Doubtless, indeed, there are intelligible entities corresponding to the sensible entities; there may also be intelligible entities to which our sensible faculty of intuition has no relation whatsoever; but our concepts of understanding, being mere forms of thought for our sensible intuition, could not in the least apply to them. That, therefore, which we entitle 'noumenon' must be understood as being such only in a negative sense.[27]

The noumenon as a limiting concept

[edit]

Even if noumena are unknowable, they are still needed as a limiting concept,[28] Kant tells us. Without them, there would be only phenomena, and since potentially we have complete knowledge of our phenomena, we would in a sense know everything. In his own words:

Further, the concept of a noumenon is necessary, to prevent sensible intuition from being extended to things in themselves, and thus to limit the objective validity of sensible knowledge.[29]

What our understanding acquires through this concept of a noumenon, is a negative extension; that is to say, understanding is not limited through sensibility; on the contrary, it itself limits sensibility by applying the term noumena to things in themselves (things not regarded as appearances). But in so doing it at the same time sets limits to itself, recognising that it cannot know these noumena through any of the categories, and that it must therefore think them only under the title of an unknown something.[30]

Furthermore, for Kant, the existence of a noumenal world limits reason to what he perceives to be its proper bounds, making many questions of traditional metaphysics, such as the existence of God, the soul, and free will unanswerable by reason. Kant derives this from his definition of knowledge as "the determination of given representations to an object".[31] As there are no appearances of these entities in the phenomenal, Kant is able to make the claim that they cannot be known to a mind that works upon "such knowledge that has to do only with appearances".[32] These questions are ultimately the "proper object of faith, but not of reason".[33]

The dual-object and dual-aspect interpretations

[edit]

Kantian scholars have long debated two contrasting interpretations of the thing-in-itself. One is the dual object view, according to which the thing-in-itself is an entity distinct from the phenomena to which it gives rise. The other is the dual aspect view, according to which the thing-in-itself and the thing-as-it-appears are two "sides" of the same thing. This view is supported by the textual fact that "Most occurrences of the phrase 'things-in-themselves' are shorthand for the phrase, 'things considered in themselves' (Dinge an sich selbst betrachtet)."[34] Although we cannot see things apart from the way we do in fact perceive them via the physical senses, we can think them apart from our mode of sensibility (physical perception); thus making the thing-in-itself a kind of noumenon or object of thought.

Criticisms of Kant's noumenon

[edit]

Pre-Kantian critique

[edit]

Though the term noumenon did not come into common usage until Kant, the idea that undergirds it, that matter has an absolute existence which causes it to emanate certain phenomena, had historically been subjected to criticism. George Berkeley, who pre-dated Kant, asserted that matter, independent of an observant mind, is metaphysically impossible. Qualities associated with matter, such as shape, color, smell, texture, weight, temperature, and sound are all dependent on minds, which allow only for relative perception, not absolute perception. The complete absence of such minds (and more importantly an omnipotent mind) would render those same qualities unobservable and even unimaginable. Berkeley called this philosophy immaterialism. Essentially there could be no such thing as matter without a mind.[35]: 559–560 

Schopenhauer's critique

[edit]

Schopenhauer claimed that Kant used the word noumenon incorrectly. He explained in his "Critique of the Kantian philosophy", which first appeared as an appendix to The World as Will and Representation:

The difference between abstract and intuitive cognition, which Kant entirely overlooks, was the very one that ancient philosophers indicated as φαινόμενα [phainomena] and νοούμενα [nooumena]; the opposition and incommensurability between these terms proved very productive in the philosophemes of the Eleatics, in Plato's doctrine of Ideas, in the dialectic of the Megarics, and later in the scholastics, in the conflict between nominalism and realism. This latter conflict was the late development of a seed already present in the opposed tendencies of Plato and Aristotle. But Kant, who completely and irresponsibly neglected the issue for which the terms φαινομένα and νοούμενα were already in use, then took possession of the terms as if they were stray and ownerless, and used them as designations of things in themselves and their appearances.[36]

The noumenon's original meaning of "that which is thought" is not compatible with the "thing-in-itself," the latter being Kant's term for things as they exist apart from their existence as images in the mind of an observer.[citation needed] In a footnote to this passage, Schopenhauer provides the following passage from the Outlines of Pyrrhonism (Bk. I, ch. 13) of Sextus Empiricus to demonstrate the original distinction between phenomenon and noumenon according to ancient philosophers: νοούμενα φαινομένοις ἀντετίθη Ἀναξαγόρας ('Anaxagoras opposed what is thought to what appears.')

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Ontology

References

[edit]
  1. ^ "Formal Epistemology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
  2. ^ "Noumenon | Definition of Noumenon by Webster's Online Dictionary". Archived from the original on 28 September 2011. Retrieved 10 September 2015. 1. intellectual conception of a thing as it is in itself, not as it is known through perception; 2. The of-itself-unknown and unknowable rational object, or thing-in-itself, which is distinguished from the phenomenon through which it is apprehended by the physical senses, and by which it is interpreted and understood; – so used in the philosophy of Kant and his followers.
  3. ^ "noumenon | philosophy". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 4 September 2017.
  4. ^ νοεῖν, νοῦς, νόος. Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert; A Greek–English Lexicon at the Perseus Project.
  5. ^ Harper, Douglas. "noumenon". Online Etymology Dictionary.
  6. ^ Bickmann, Claudia (2010). "9. Kant's Critical Concept of a Person: The Noumenal Sphere Grounding the Principle of Spirituality". Cultivating Personhood: Kant and Asian Philosophy. pp. 194–204. doi:10.1515/9783110226249.2.194. ISBN 978-3-11-022623-2.
  7. ^ Honderich, Ted, ed. (31 August 1995). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 657. ISBN 0198661320. Retrieved 28 October 2014.
  8. ^ Hanna, Robert (2009). Completing the Picture of Kant's Metaphysics of Judgment. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  9. ^ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Kant's metaphysics.
  10. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ff.
  11. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Transcendental Aesthetic", p. 310 ff.
  12. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ff.
  13. ^ See, e.g., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ff.
  14. ^ See also, e.g., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ff.
  15. ^ Kant 1999, p. 27, A256/B312.
  16. ^ Immanuel Kant (1781) Critique of Pure Reason, for example in A254/B310, p. 362 (Guyer and Wood), "The concept of a noumenon, i.e., of a thing that is not to be thought of as an object of the senses but rather as a thing-in-itself [...]"; But note that the terms are not used interchangeably throughout. The first reference to thing-in-itself comes many pages (A30) before the first reference to noumenon (A250). For a secondary or tertiary source, see: "Noumenon" in the Encyclopædia Britannica
  17. ^ "Noumenon: the name given to a thing when it is viewed as a transcendent object. The term 'negative noumenon' refers only to the recognition of something which is not an object of sensible intuition, while 'positive noumenon' refers to the (quite mistaken) attempt to know such a thing as an empirical object. These two terms are sometimes used loosely as synonyms for 'transcendental object' and 'thing-in-itself', respectively. (Cf. phenomenon.)" – Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms
  18. ^ Thing-in-itself: an object considered transcendentally apart from all the conditions under which a subject can gain knowledge of it via the physical senses. Hence the thing-in-itself is, by definition, unknowable via the physical senses. Sometimes used loosely as a synonym of noumenon. (Cf. appearance.)" – Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms. Palmquist defends his definitions of these terms in his article, "Six Perspectives on the Object in Kant's Theory of Knowledge", Dialectica 40:2 (1986), pp.121–151; revised and reprinted as Chapter VI in Palmquist's book, Kant's System of Perspectives (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  19. ^ Oizerman, T. I., "Kant's Doctrine of the "Things in Themselves" and Noumena", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 41, No. 3, Mar., 1981, 333–350; Karin de Boer, "Kant's Multi-Layered Conception of Things in Themselves, Transcendental Objects, and Monads", Kant-Studien 105/2, 2014, 221-260.
  20. ^ "Other interpreters have introduced an almost unending stream of varying suggestions as to how these terms ought to be used. A handful of examples will be sufficient to make this point clear, without any claim to represent an exhaustive overview. Perhaps the most commonly accepted view is expressed by Paulsen, who equates 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon', equates 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', distinguishes 'positive noumenon' and 'negative noumenon', and treats 'negative noumenon' as equivalent to 'transcendental object' [pp. 4:148-50, 154-5, 192]. Al-Azm and Wolff also seem satisfied to equate 'phenomenon' and 'appearance', though they both carefully distinguish 'thing-in-itself' from 'negative noumenon' and 'positive noumenon' [A4:520; W21:165, 313–5; s.a. W9:162]. Gotterbarn similarly equates the former pair, as well as 'thing-in-itself' and 'positive noumenon', but distinguishes between 'transcendental object', 'negative noumenon' and 'thing-in-itself' [G11: 201]. By contrast, Bird and George both distinguish between 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', but not between 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon' [B20:18,19, 53–7; G7:513-4n]; and Bird sometimes blurs the distinction between 'thing-in-itself' and 'transcendental object' as well.[2] Gram equates 'thing-in-itself' not with 'noumenon', but with 'phenomenon' [G13:1,5-6]! Allison cites different official meanings for each term, yet he tends to equate 'thing-in-itself' at times with 'negative noumenon' and at times with 'transcendental-object', usually ignoring the role of the 'positive noumenon' [A7:94; A10:58,69]. And Buchdahl responds to the fact that the thing-in-itself seems to be connected with each of the other object-terms by regarding it as 'Kant's umbrella term'.[3]" Stephen Palmquist on Kant's object terms
  21. ^ Kant 1999, Bxxvi-xxvii.
  22. ^ Kant 1999, p. 273, A256, B312.
  23. ^ "The Radical Unknowability of Kant's 'Thing in Itself'", Cogito 3:2 (March 1985), pp.101–115; revised and reprinted as Appendix V in Stephen Palmquist, Kant's System of Perspectives (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  24. ^ Mattey, G. J.
  25. ^ Lecture notes by G. J. Mattey Archived 2010-06-12 at the Wayback Machine
  26. ^ a b c Kant 1999, p. 267 (NKS), A250/B307.
  27. ^ Kant 1999, p. 270 (NKS), B309.
  28. ^ Allison, H (2006). "Transcendental Realism, Empirical Realism, and Transcendental Idealism". Kantian Review. 11: 1–28. doi:10.1017/S1369415400002223. S2CID 171078596.
  29. ^ Kant 1999, A253/B310.
  30. ^ Kant 1999, p. 273, A256/B312.
  31. ^ Kant 1999, p. 156, B/137.
  32. ^ Kant 1999, p. 24, B/xx..
  33. ^ Rohmann, Chris. "Kant" A World of Ideas: A Dictionary of Important Theories, Concepts, Beliefs, and Thnkers. Ballantine Books, 1999.
  34. ^ Mattey, GJ. "Lecture Notes on the Critique of Pure Reason".
  35. ^ Anon., "Caird's Philosophy of Kant", Saturday Review of Politics, Literature, Science and Art, vol 44, Nov 3, 1877, pp. 559–560.
  36. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur (2014). The World as Will and Representation, Volume 1. Translated by Norman, Judith; Welchman, Alistair; Janaway, Christopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 506. ISBN 9780521871846.

Bibliography

[edit]
[edit]