Logical consequence: Difference between revisions
No reason to have anything personal in here that's not directly related to the article. I hope these examples are effective substitutes. |
→Syntactic consequence: use template ref, update pg |
||
(287 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|Relationship where one statement follows from another}} |
|||
'''Logical consequence''', arguably the most fundamental concept in [[logic]], is the [[Relation (mathematics)|relation]] that holds between a [[Set (mathematics)|set]] of [[Sentence (linguistics)|sentences]] (or [[proposition]]s) and a sentence (proposition) when the latter "follows from" the former. For example, ''Kermit is green'' is a logical consequence of ''All frogs are green'' and ''Kermit is a frog''. |
|||
{{Redirect|Entailment||Entail (disambiguation)}} |
|||
{{Redirect|Therefore|the therefore symbol ∴|Therefore sign}} |
|||
{{Redirect|Logical implication|the binary connective|Material conditional}} |
|||
{{Redirect|⊧|the symbol|Double turnstile}} |
|||
'''Logical consequence''' (also '''entailment''') is a fundamental [[concept]] in [[logic]] which describes the relationship between [[statement (logic)|statement]]s that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more statements. A [[Validity (logic)|valid]] logical [[argument]] is one in which the [[Consequent|conclusion]] is entailed by the [[premise]]s, because the conclusion is the consequence of the premises. The [[philosophical analysis]] of logical consequence involves the questions: In what sense does a conclusion follow from its premises? and What does it mean for a conclusion to be a consequence of premises?<ref name="sep" >Beall, JC and Restall, Greg, ''[http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/logical-consequence/ Logical Consequence]'' The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).</ref> All of [[philosophical logic]] is meant to provide accounts of the nature of logical consequence and the nature of [[logical truth]].<ref>[[Willard Van Orman Quine|Quine, Willard Van Orman]], ''Philosophy of Logic''.</ref> |
|||
A formally specified logical consequence relation may be characterized [[Model theory|model-theoretically]] or [[Proof theory|proof-theoretically]] (or both). |
|||
Logical consequence is [[logical truth|necessary]] and [[Formalism (philosophy of mathematics)|formal]], by way of examples that explain with [[formal proof]] and [[interpretation (logic)|models of interpretation]].<ref name="sep" /> A sentence is said to be a logical consequence of a set of sentences, for a given [[Formal language|language]], [[if and only if]], using only logic (i.e., without regard to any ''personal'' interpretations of the sentences) the sentence must be true if every sentence in the set is true.<ref name="iep">McKeon, Matthew, ''[http://www.iep.utm.edu/logcon/ Logical Consequence]'' Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.</ref> |
|||
Logical consequence can also be expressed as a [[Function (mathematics)|function]] from sets of sentences to sets of sentences ([[Alfred Tarski|Tarski]]'s preferred formulation), or as a relation between two sets of sentences ([[multiple-conclusion logic]]). |
|||
Logicians make precise accounts of logical consequence regarding a given [[formal language|language]] <math>\mathcal{L}</math>, either by constructing a [[deductive system]] for <math>\mathcal{L}</math> or by formal [[Intended interpretation|intended semantics]] for language <math>\mathcal{L}</math>. The Polish logician [[Alfred Tarski]] identified three features of an adequate characterization of entailment: (1) The logical consequence relation relies on the [[logical form]] of the sentences: (2) The relation is [[a priori and a posteriori|a priori]], i.e., it can be determined with or without regard to [[empirical evidence]] (sense experience); and (3) The logical consequence relation has a [[modal logic|modal]] component.<ref name="iep" /> |
|||
== Accounts of logical consequence == |
|||
== Formal accounts == |
|||
This section describes some common accounts of logical consequence. |
|||
The most widely prevailing view on how best to account for logical consequence is to appeal to formality. This is to say that whether statements follow from one another logically depends on the structure or [[logical form]] of the statements without regard to the contents of that form. |
|||
Syntactic accounts of logical consequence rely on [[schema (logic)|schemes]] using [[inference rule]]s. For instance, we can express the logical form of a valid argument as: |
|||
Γ will represent an arbitrary set of [[premise]]s and ''A'' an arbitrary [[conclusion]]. Γ/''A'' will denote the [[logical argument]] having Γ as its (set of) premises and ''A'' as its conclusion. Γ <math>\vdash</math>''A'' will mean that ''A'' is a logical consequence of Γ. |
|||
: All ''X'' are ''Y'' |
|||
=== Modal accounts === |
|||
: All ''Y'' are ''Z'' |
|||
: Therefore, all ''X'' are ''Z''. |
|||
This argument is formally valid, because every [[Substitution (logic)|instance]] of arguments constructed using this scheme is valid. |
|||
''Modal'' accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea: |
|||
This is in contrast to an argument like "Fred is Mike's brother's son. Therefore Fred is Mike's nephew." Since this argument depends on the meanings of the words "brother", "son", and "nephew", the statement "Fred is Mike's nephew" is a so-called [[material conditional|material consequence]] of "Fred is Mike's brother's son", not a formal consequence. A formal consequence must be true ''in all cases'', however this is an incomplete definition of formal consequence, since even the argument "''P'' is ''Q''{{'}}s brother's son, therefore ''P'' is ''Q''{{'}}s nephew" is valid in all cases, but is not a ''formal'' argument.<ref name="sep" /> |
|||
* Γ <math>\vdash</math>''A'' just in case it is ''necessary'' that if all of the elements of Γ are true, then ''A'' is true. |
|||
== A priori property of logical consequence == |
|||
Alternatively (and, most would say, equivalently): |
|||
If it is known that <math>Q</math> follows logically from <math>P</math>, then no information about the possible interpretations of <math>P</math> or <math>Q</math> will affect that knowledge. Our knowledge that <math>Q</math> is a logical consequence of <math>P</math> cannot be influenced by [[A priori and a posteriori|empirical knowledge]].<ref name="sep" /> Deductively valid arguments can be known to be so without recourse to experience, so they must be knowable a priori.<ref name="sep" /> However, formality alone does not guarantee that logical consequence is not influenced by empirical knowledge. So the a priori property of logical consequence is considered to be independent of formality.<ref name="sep" /> |
|||
* Γ <math>\vdash</math>''A'' just in case it is ''impossible'' for all of the elements of Γ to be true and ''A'' false. |
|||
== Proofs and models == |
|||
Such accounts are called "modal" because they appeal to the modal notions of [[Logical possibility|necessity and (im)possibility]]. ''It is necessary that'' is often cashed out as a [[universal quantifier]] over [[possible worlds]], so that the accounts above translate as: |
|||
The two prevailing techniques for providing accounts of logical consequence involve expressing the concept in terms of ''proofs'' and via ''models''. The study of the syntactic consequence (of a logic) is called (its) [[proof theory]] whereas the study of (its) semantic consequence is called (its) [[model theory]].<ref name="ChiaraDoets1996">{{cite book|editor1=Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara |editor1-link= Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara |editor2=Kees Doets |editor3=Daniele Mundici |editor4=Johan van Benthem |title=Logic and Scientific Methods: Volume One of the Tenth International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Florence, August 1995|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TCthvF8xLIAC&pg=PA292|year=1996|publisher=Springer|isbn=978-0-7923-4383-7|page=292|chapter=Logical consequence: a turn in style|author=Kosta Dosen}}</ref> |
|||
=== Syntactic consequence === |
|||
* Γ <math>\vdash</math>''A'' just in case there is no possible world at which all of the elements of Γ are true and ''A'' is false (untrue). |
|||
{{See also|Therefore_sign|label 1= ∴|Turnstile_(symbol)|label 2= ⊢}} |
|||
A formula <math>A</math> is a '''syntactic consequence'''<ref>[[Michael Dummett|Dummett, Michael]] (1993) [https://books.google.com/books?id=EYP7uCZIRQYC&q=syntactic+consequence%27%27Frege%3A&pg=PA82 ''philosophy of language''] Harvard University Press, p.82ff</ref><ref>[[Jonathan Lear|Lear, Jonathan]] (1986) [https://books.google.com/books?id=lXI7AAAAIAAJ&q=syntactic+consequence%27%27Aristotle&pg=PA1 ''and Logical Theory''] Cambridge University Press, 136p.</ref><ref>Creath, Richard, and [[Michael Friedman (philosopher)|Friedman, Michael]] (2007) [https://books.google.com/books?id=87BcFLgJmxMC&q=syntactic+consequence%27%27The&pg=PA189 ''Cambridge companion to Carnap''] Cambridge University Press, 371p.</ref><ref>[http://www.swif.uniba.it/lei/foldop/foldoc.cgi?syntactic+consequence FOLDOC: "syntactic consequence"] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130403201417/http://www.swif.uniba.it/lei/foldop/foldoc.cgi?syntactic+consequence |date=2013-04-03 }}</ref><ref name="Kleene52">S. C. Kleene, ''[https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/523942 Introduction to Metamathematics]'' (1952), Van Nostrand Publishing. p.88.</ref> within some [[formal system]] <math>\mathcal{FS}</math> of a set <math>\Gamma</math> of formulas if there is a [[formal proof]] in <math>\mathcal{FS}</math> of <math>A</math> from the set <math>\Gamma</math>. This is denoted <math>\Gamma \vdash_{\mathcal {FS} } A</math>. The turnstile symbol <math>\vdash</math> was originally introduced by Frege in 1879, but its current use only dates back to Rosser and Kleene (1934–1935). <ref name="Kleene52" /> |
|||
Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above: |
|||
Syntactic consequence does not depend on any [[interpretation (logic)|interpretation]] of the formal system.<ref>{{Hunter 1996|p=101}}</ref> |
|||
:All frogs are green.<br> |
|||
:Kermit is a frog.<br> |
|||
:Therefore, Kermit is green. |
|||
=== Semantic consequence === |
|||
The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can't imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green. |
|||
{{See also|Double turnstile|label 1= ⊨}} |
|||
A formula <math>A</math> is a '''semantic consequence''' within some formal system <math>\mathcal{FS}</math> of a set of statements <math>\Gamma</math> if and only if there is no model <math>\mathcal{I}</math> in which all members of <math>\Gamma</math> are true and <math>A</math> is false.<ref>[[John Etchemendy|Etchemendy, John]], ''Logical consequence'', The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy</ref> This is denoted <math>\Gamma \models_{\mathcal {FS} } A</math>. Or, in other words, the set of the interpretations that make all members of <math>\Gamma</math> true is a subset of the set of the interpretations that make <math>A</math> true. |
|||
=== Formal accounts === |
|||
== Modal accounts == |
|||
''Formal'' accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea: |
|||
[[Modal logic|Modal]] accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea: |
|||
* Γ <math>\vdash</math>''A'' just in case no argument with the same ''[[logical form]]'' as Γ/''A'' has true premises and a false conclusion. |
|||
:<math>\Gamma</math> <math>\vdash</math> <math>A</math> is true if and only if it is ''necessary'' that if all of the elements of <math>\Gamma</math> are true, then <math>A</math> is true. |
|||
Two common variations on this basic idea are: |
|||
Alternatively (and, most would say, equivalently): |
|||
# Γ <math>\vdash</math>''A'' just in case no ''uniform substitution'' of the nonlogical terms in Γ/''A'' yields an argument with true premises and a false conclusion. |
|||
# Γ <math>\vdash</math>''A'' just in case there is no way of ''interpreting'' the nonlogical terms in Γ/''A'' that yields an argument with true premises and a false conclusion. |
|||
:<math>\Gamma</math> <math>\vdash</math> <math>A</math> is true if and only if it is ''impossible'' for all of the elements of <math>\Gamma</math> to be true and <math>A</math> false. |
|||
Let us again consider the argument: |
|||
Such accounts are called "modal" because they appeal to the modal notions of [[Logical truth|logical necessity]] and [[logical possibility]]. 'It is necessary that' is often expressed as a [[universal quantification|universal quantifier]] over [[possible world]]s, so that the accounts above translate as: |
|||
: All frogs are green. |
|||
: Kermit is a frog. |
|||
: Therefore, Kermit is green. |
|||
:<math>\Gamma</math> <math>\vdash</math> <math>A</math> is true if and only if there is no possible world at which all of the elements of <math>\Gamma</math> are true and <math>A</math> is false (untrue). |
|||
Formal account (1) says that the conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because no matter how we ''uniformly replace'' the nonlogical terms (''frog'', ''green'', ''Kermit'') in the argument, we do not get true premises and a false conclusion. Consider for example: |
|||
Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above: |
|||
: All skyscrapers are tall. |
|||
: The Empire State Building is a skyscraper. |
|||
: Therefore, the Empire State Building is tall. |
|||
: |
:All frogs are green. |
||
:Kermit is a frog. |
|||
: All rectangles are quadrilaterals. |
|||
: |
:Therefore, Kermit is green. |
||
The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can not imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green. |
|||
: All matter has mass. |
|||
: Coffee tables are matter. |
|||
: Therefore, coffee tables have mass. |
|||
: All birds have feathers. |
|||
: Penguins are birds. |
|||
: Therefore, penguins have feathers. |
|||
We can make up arguments of this form all day, but we will never come up with one that has true premises and a false conclusion. The argument is [[Validity|deductively valid]] by virtue of its logical form, which might be characterized with the following template (in which '''F''', '''G''', and '''a''' are meaningless placeholders): |
|||
: All '''F'''s are '''G'''s. |
|||
: '''a''' is an '''F'''. |
|||
: Therefore, '''a''' is a '''G'''. |
|||
Formal account (2) says that the conclusion of the "Kermit" argument is a logical consequence of the premises because no matter how we ''interpret'' the nonlogical terms (''frog'', ''green'', ''Kermit'') in the argument, we do not get true premises and a false conclusion. Suppose, for example, we interpret ''frog'' to mean ''plumber'', ''green'' to mean ''shy'', and ''Kermit'' to mean ''Madonna'' (the singer). Then the argument has two false premises (for not all plumbers are shy, and Madonna is not a plumber) and a false conclusion (for Madonna is not shy). We can come up with as many interpretations of ''frog'', ''green'', and ''Kermit'' as we like, but this will never result in an argument with true premises and a false conclusion. |
|||
=== Modal-formal accounts === |
=== Modal-formal accounts === |
||
Modal-formal accounts of logical consequence combine the modal and formal accounts above, yielding variations on the following basic idea: |
|||
:<math>\Gamma</math> <math>\vdash</math> <math>A</math> if and only if it is impossible for an argument with the same logical form as <math>\Gamma</math>/<math>A</math> to have true premises and a false conclusion. |
|||
Most [[logicians]] would probably agree that logical consequence, as we intuitively understand it, has both a modal and a formal aspect, and that some version of the modal/formal account is therefore closest to being correct. |
|||
=== Warrant-based accounts === |
=== Warrant-based accounts === |
||
The accounts considered above are all "truth-preservational |
The accounts considered above are all "truth-preservational", in that they all assume that the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from true premises to an untrue conclusion. As an alternative, some have proposed "[[Theory of justification|warrant]]-preservational" accounts, according to which the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from justifiably assertible premises to a conclusion that is not justifiably assertible. This is (roughly) the account favored by [[intuitionist]]s such as [[Michael Dummett]]. |
||
== Non-monotonic logical consequence == |
=== Non-monotonic logical consequence === |
||
{{ |
{{See also|Non-monotonic logic|Belief revision#Non-monotonic inference relation}} |
||
The accounts discussed above all yield [[monotonic]] consequence relations, i.e. ones such that if |
The accounts discussed above all yield [[Monotonicity of entailment|monotonic]] consequence relations, i.e. ones such that if <math>A</math> is a consequence of <math>\Gamma</math>, then <math>A</math> is a consequence of any superset of <math>\Gamma</math>. It is also possible to specify non-monotonic consequence relations to capture the idea that, e.g., 'Tweety can fly' is a logical consequence of |
||
:{ |
:{Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird} |
||
but not of |
but not of |
||
:{ |
:{Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird, Tweety is a penguin}. |
||
==See also== |
|||
For more on this, see the article on [[non-monotonic logic]]. |
|||
{{div col begin}} |
|||
* [[Abstract algebraic logic]] |
|||
== See also == |
|||
* [[Ampheck]] |
|||
* [[Boolean algebra (logic)]] |
|||
* [[Boolean domain]] |
|||
* [[Boolean function]] |
|||
* [[Boolean logic]] |
|||
* [[Causality]] |
|||
* [[Deductive reasoning]] |
* [[Deductive reasoning]] |
||
* [[Logic gate]] |
|||
* [[Logical graph]] |
|||
* [[Peirce's law]] |
|||
* [[Probabilistic logic]] |
|||
* [[Propositional calculus]] |
|||
* [[Sole sufficient operator]] |
|||
* [[Strawson entailment]] |
|||
* [[Strict conditional]] |
|||
* [[Tautology (logic)]] |
* [[Tautology (logic)]] |
||
* [[Tautological consequence]] |
|||
* [[Validity]] |
|||
* [[Therefore sign]] |
|||
* [[Turnstile (symbol)]] |
|||
* [[Double turnstile]] |
|||
* [[Validity (logic)|Validity]] |
|||
{{div col end}} |
|||
== Notes == |
|||
{{Reflist}} |
|||
== Resources == |
== Resources == |
||
* {{citation|last1=Anderson|first1=A.R.|last2=Belnap|first2=N.D. Jr.|title=Entailment|year=1975|publisher=Princeton|location=Princeton, NJ|volume=1}}. |
|||
* [[Michael Dummett]], 1991. ''The Logical Basis of Metaphysics''. Harvard University Press. |
|||
* {{citation|last=Augusto|first=Luis M.|year=2017|title=Logical consequences. Theory and applications: An introduction.}} London: College Publications. Series: [http://www.collegepublications.co.uk/logic/mlf/?00029 Mathematical logic and foundations]. |
|||
* [[John Etchemendy]], 1990. ''The Concept of Logical Consequence''. Harvard University Press. |
|||
* {{citation|last1=Barwise|first1=Jon|author1-link=Jon Barwise|last2=Etchemendy|first2=John|author2-link=John Etchemendy|year=2008|title=Language, Proof and Logic|publisher=CSLI Publications|location=Stanford}}. |
|||
* Hanson, William H., 1997, "The concept of logical consequence," ''The Philosophical Review 106'': 365-409. |
|||
* {{citation|last=Brown | first=Frank Markham | year=2003 |title=Boolean Reasoning: The Logic of Boolean Equations}} 1st edition, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Norwell, MA. 2nd edition, Dover Publications, Mineola, NY, 2003. |
|||
* [[Vincent F. Hendricks]], 2005. ''Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression''. New York: Automatic Press / VIP. ISBN 87-991013-7-8 |
|||
* {{citation|author-link=Martin Davis (mathematician)|editor-last=Davis|editor-first= Martin|title=The Undecidable, Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions, Unsolvable Problems And Computable Functions|publisher=Raven Press|location=New York|year=1965|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=qW8x7sQ4JXgC&q=consequence|isbn=9780486432281}}. Papers include those by [[Gödel]], [[Alonzo Church|Church]], [[J. Barkley Rosser|Rosser]], [[Kleene]], and [[Emil Leon Post|Post]]. |
|||
*Planchette, P. A., 2001, "Logical Consequence," in Goble, Lou, ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell. |
|||
* {{citation |first=Michael |last=Dummett |year=1991 |title=The Logical Basis of Metaphysics |publisher=Harvard University Press|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=lvsVFxK3BPcC&q=consequence|isbn=9780674537866 }}. |
|||
* [[Stewart Shapiro]], 2002, "Necessity, meaning, and rationality: the notion of logical consequence" In D. Jacquette, ed., ''A Companion to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell. |
|||
* {{citation|last=Edgington| first=Dorothy|year=2001|title=Conditionals|publisher=Blackwell}} in Lou Goble (ed.), ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. |
|||
* [[Alfred Tarski]], 1936, "On the concept of logical consequence." Reprinted in Tarski, A., 1983. ''Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics'', 2nd ed. [[Oxford University Press]]. Originally published in [[Polish language|Polish]] and [[German language|German]]. |
|||
* {{citation|last=Edgington| first=Dorothy|year=2006|title=Conditionals|chapter-url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/conditionals| chapter=Indicative Conditionals| publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University}} in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. |
|||
* {{citation |first=John |last= Etchemendy |year= 1990 |title=The Concept of Logical Consequence |publisher= Harvard University Press}}. |
|||
* {{citation |editor-last=Goble |editor-first=Lou|year=2001 |title=The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic |publisher= Blackwell}}. |
|||
* {{citation |last=Hanson |first= William H|year= 1997 |title=The concept of logical consequence| journal=The Philosophical Review| volume=106|issue= 3|pages= 365–409|jstor= 2998398|doi= 10.2307/2998398}} 365–409. |
|||
* {{citation |author-link=Vincent F. Hendricks|last=Hendricks |first=Vincent F. |year=2005 |title=Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression |location=New York |publisher=Automatic Press / VIP |isbn= 978-87-991013-7-5}} |
|||
* {{citation |last=Planchette |first=P. A. |year=2001 |title=Logical Consequence}} in Goble, Lou, ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell. |
|||
* {{citation|author-link=W.V. Quine|last=Quine|first=W.V.| year=1982| title=Methods of Logic|location=Cambridge, MA|publisher=Harvard University Press}} (1st ed. 1950), (2nd ed. 1959), (3rd ed. 1972), (4th edition, 1982). |
|||
*{{citation |author-link=Stewart Shapiro |last=Shapiro |first=Stewart |year=2002 |title=Necessity, meaning, and rationality: the notion of logical consequence}} in D. Jacquette, ed., ''A Companion to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell. |
|||
*{{citation |author-link=Alfred Tarski |last=Tarski |first=Alfred |year= 1936 |title=On the concept of logical consequence}} Reprinted in Tarski, A., 1983. ''Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics'', 2nd ed. [[Oxford University Press]]. Originally published in [[Polish language|Polish]] and [[German language|German]]. |
|||
* {{cite book|author=Ryszard Wójcicki|title=Theory of Logical Calculi: Basic Theory of Consequence Operations|year=1988|publisher=Springer|isbn=978-90-277-2785-5|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/theoryoflogicalc0000wojc}} |
|||
* A paper on 'implication' from math.niu.edu, [http://www.math.niu.edu/~richard/Math101/implies.pdf Implication] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141021082239/http://www.math.niu.edu/~richard/Math101/implies.pdf |date=2014-10-21 }} |
|||
* A definition of 'implicant' [http://www.allwords.com/word-implicant.html AllWords] |
|||
==External links== |
|||
{{Commons category}} |
|||
*{{cite SEP |url-id=logical-consequence |title=Logical Consequence|date=2013-11-19|edition=Winter 2016|last=Beall|first=Jc|last2=Restall|first2=Greg|author-link=Jc Beall|author2-link=Greg Restall}} |
|||
*{{cite IEP |url-id=logcon/ |title=Logical consequence}} |
|||
*{{InPho|taxonomy|2409}} |
|||
*{{PhilPapers|category|logical-consequence-and-entailment}} |
|||
*{{springer|title=Implication|id=p/i050280}} |
|||
{{Logic}} |
|||
== External links == |
|||
{{Mathematical logic}} |
|||
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logical-consequence/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy] |
|||
{{Logical connectives}} |
|||
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/l/logcon.htm Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] |
|||
{{Common logical symbols}} |
|||
{{Formal semantics}} |
|||
{{Authority control}} |
|||
[[Category:Logic]] |
|||
[[Category:Logical consequence| ]] |
|||
[[id:Konsekuensi logis]] |
|||
[[Category:Philosophical logic]] |
|||
[[Category:Metalogic]] |
|||
[[Category:Propositional calculus]] |
|||
[[Category:Semantic units]] |
|||
[[Category:Deductive reasoning]] |
|||
[[Category:Concepts in logic]] |
|||
[[Category:Syntax (logic)]] |
|||
[[Category:Binary operations]] |
Latest revision as of 02:18, 1 December 2024
Logical consequence (also entailment) is a fundamental concept in logic which describes the relationship between statements that hold true when one statement logically follows from one or more statements. A valid logical argument is one in which the conclusion is entailed by the premises, because the conclusion is the consequence of the premises. The philosophical analysis of logical consequence involves the questions: In what sense does a conclusion follow from its premises? and What does it mean for a conclusion to be a consequence of premises?[1] All of philosophical logic is meant to provide accounts of the nature of logical consequence and the nature of logical truth.[2]
Logical consequence is necessary and formal, by way of examples that explain with formal proof and models of interpretation.[1] A sentence is said to be a logical consequence of a set of sentences, for a given language, if and only if, using only logic (i.e., without regard to any personal interpretations of the sentences) the sentence must be true if every sentence in the set is true.[3]
Logicians make precise accounts of logical consequence regarding a given language , either by constructing a deductive system for or by formal intended semantics for language . The Polish logician Alfred Tarski identified three features of an adequate characterization of entailment: (1) The logical consequence relation relies on the logical form of the sentences: (2) The relation is a priori, i.e., it can be determined with or without regard to empirical evidence (sense experience); and (3) The logical consequence relation has a modal component.[3]
Formal accounts
[edit]The most widely prevailing view on how best to account for logical consequence is to appeal to formality. This is to say that whether statements follow from one another logically depends on the structure or logical form of the statements without regard to the contents of that form.
Syntactic accounts of logical consequence rely on schemes using inference rules. For instance, we can express the logical form of a valid argument as:
- All X are Y
- All Y are Z
- Therefore, all X are Z.
This argument is formally valid, because every instance of arguments constructed using this scheme is valid.
This is in contrast to an argument like "Fred is Mike's brother's son. Therefore Fred is Mike's nephew." Since this argument depends on the meanings of the words "brother", "son", and "nephew", the statement "Fred is Mike's nephew" is a so-called material consequence of "Fred is Mike's brother's son", not a formal consequence. A formal consequence must be true in all cases, however this is an incomplete definition of formal consequence, since even the argument "P is Q's brother's son, therefore P is Q's nephew" is valid in all cases, but is not a formal argument.[1]
A priori property of logical consequence
[edit]If it is known that follows logically from , then no information about the possible interpretations of or will affect that knowledge. Our knowledge that is a logical consequence of cannot be influenced by empirical knowledge.[1] Deductively valid arguments can be known to be so without recourse to experience, so they must be knowable a priori.[1] However, formality alone does not guarantee that logical consequence is not influenced by empirical knowledge. So the a priori property of logical consequence is considered to be independent of formality.[1]
Proofs and models
[edit]The two prevailing techniques for providing accounts of logical consequence involve expressing the concept in terms of proofs and via models. The study of the syntactic consequence (of a logic) is called (its) proof theory whereas the study of (its) semantic consequence is called (its) model theory.[4]
Syntactic consequence
[edit]A formula is a syntactic consequence[5][6][7][8][9] within some formal system of a set of formulas if there is a formal proof in of from the set . This is denoted . The turnstile symbol was originally introduced by Frege in 1879, but its current use only dates back to Rosser and Kleene (1934–1935). [9]
Syntactic consequence does not depend on any interpretation of the formal system.[10]
Semantic consequence
[edit]A formula is a semantic consequence within some formal system of a set of statements if and only if there is no model in which all members of are true and is false.[11] This is denoted . Or, in other words, the set of the interpretations that make all members of true is a subset of the set of the interpretations that make true.
Modal accounts
[edit]Modal accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea:
- is true if and only if it is necessary that if all of the elements of are true, then is true.
Alternatively (and, most would say, equivalently):
- is true if and only if it is impossible for all of the elements of to be true and false.
Such accounts are called "modal" because they appeal to the modal notions of logical necessity and logical possibility. 'It is necessary that' is often expressed as a universal quantifier over possible worlds, so that the accounts above translate as:
- is true if and only if there is no possible world at which all of the elements of are true and is false (untrue).
Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above:
- All frogs are green.
- Kermit is a frog.
- Therefore, Kermit is green.
The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can not imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green.
Modal-formal accounts
[edit]Modal-formal accounts of logical consequence combine the modal and formal accounts above, yielding variations on the following basic idea:
- if and only if it is impossible for an argument with the same logical form as / to have true premises and a false conclusion.
Warrant-based accounts
[edit]The accounts considered above are all "truth-preservational", in that they all assume that the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from true premises to an untrue conclusion. As an alternative, some have proposed "warrant-preservational" accounts, according to which the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from justifiably assertible premises to a conclusion that is not justifiably assertible. This is (roughly) the account favored by intuitionists such as Michael Dummett.
Non-monotonic logical consequence
[edit]The accounts discussed above all yield monotonic consequence relations, i.e. ones such that if is a consequence of , then is a consequence of any superset of . It is also possible to specify non-monotonic consequence relations to capture the idea that, e.g., 'Tweety can fly' is a logical consequence of
- {Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird}
but not of
- {Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird, Tweety is a penguin}.
See also
[edit]- Abstract algebraic logic
- Ampheck
- Boolean algebra (logic)
- Boolean domain
- Boolean function
- Boolean logic
- Causality
- Deductive reasoning
- Logic gate
- Logical graph
- Peirce's law
- Probabilistic logic
- Propositional calculus
- Sole sufficient operator
- Strawson entailment
- Strict conditional
- Tautology (logic)
- Tautological consequence
- Therefore sign
- Turnstile (symbol)
- Double turnstile
- Validity
Notes
[edit]- ^ a b c d e f Beall, JC and Restall, Greg, Logical Consequence The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
- ^ Quine, Willard Van Orman, Philosophy of Logic.
- ^ a b McKeon, Matthew, Logical Consequence Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Kosta Dosen (1996). "Logical consequence: a turn in style". In Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara; Kees Doets; Daniele Mundici; Johan van Benthem (eds.). Logic and Scientific Methods: Volume One of the Tenth International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Florence, August 1995. Springer. p. 292. ISBN 978-0-7923-4383-7.
- ^ Dummett, Michael (1993) philosophy of language Harvard University Press, p.82ff
- ^ Lear, Jonathan (1986) and Logical Theory Cambridge University Press, 136p.
- ^ Creath, Richard, and Friedman, Michael (2007) Cambridge companion to Carnap Cambridge University Press, 371p.
- ^ FOLDOC: "syntactic consequence" Archived 2013-04-03 at the Wayback Machine
- ^ a b S. C. Kleene, Introduction to Metamathematics (1952), Van Nostrand Publishing. p.88.
- ^ Hunter, Geoffrey (1996) [1971]. Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-Order Logic. University of California Press (published 1973). p. 101. ISBN 9780520023567. OCLC 36312727. (accessible to patrons with print disabilities)
- ^ Etchemendy, John, Logical consequence, The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy
Resources
[edit]- Anderson, A.R.; Belnap, N.D. Jr. (1975), Entailment, vol. 1, Princeton, NJ: Princeton.
- Augusto, Luis M. (2017), Logical consequences. Theory and applications: An introduction. London: College Publications. Series: Mathematical logic and foundations.
- Barwise, Jon; Etchemendy, John (2008), Language, Proof and Logic, Stanford: CSLI Publications.
- Brown, Frank Markham (2003), Boolean Reasoning: The Logic of Boolean Equations 1st edition, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Norwell, MA. 2nd edition, Dover Publications, Mineola, NY, 2003.
- Davis, Martin, ed. (1965), The Undecidable, Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions, Unsolvable Problems And Computable Functions, New York: Raven Press, ISBN 9780486432281. Papers include those by Gödel, Church, Rosser, Kleene, and Post.
- Dummett, Michael (1991), The Logical Basis of Metaphysics, Harvard University Press, ISBN 9780674537866.
- Edgington, Dorothy (2001), Conditionals, Blackwell in Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic.
- Edgington, Dorothy (2006), "Indicative Conditionals", Conditionals, Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Etchemendy, John (1990), The Concept of Logical Consequence, Harvard University Press.
- Goble, Lou, ed. (2001), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic, Blackwell.
- Hanson, William H (1997), "The concept of logical consequence", The Philosophical Review, 106 (3): 365–409, doi:10.2307/2998398, JSTOR 2998398 365–409.
- Hendricks, Vincent F. (2005), Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression, New York: Automatic Press / VIP, ISBN 978-87-991013-7-5
- Planchette, P. A. (2001), Logical Consequence in Goble, Lou, ed., The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Blackwell.
- Quine, W.V. (1982), Methods of Logic, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (1st ed. 1950), (2nd ed. 1959), (3rd ed. 1972), (4th edition, 1982).
- Shapiro, Stewart (2002), Necessity, meaning, and rationality: the notion of logical consequence in D. Jacquette, ed., A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Blackwell.
- Tarski, Alfred (1936), On the concept of logical consequence Reprinted in Tarski, A., 1983. Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, 2nd ed. Oxford University Press. Originally published in Polish and German.
- Ryszard Wójcicki (1988). Theory of Logical Calculi: Basic Theory of Consequence Operations. Springer. ISBN 978-90-277-2785-5.
- A paper on 'implication' from math.niu.edu, Implication Archived 2014-10-21 at the Wayback Machine
- A definition of 'implicant' AllWords
External links
[edit]- Beall, Jc; Restall, Greg (2013-11-19). "Logical Consequence". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.).
- "Logical consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Logical consequence at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- Logical consequence at PhilPapers
- "Implication", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]