Jump to content

Social equality: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Fixed link title
BunnysBot (talk | contribs)
Fix CW Errors with GenFixes (T1)
 
(157 intermediate revisions by 91 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Comparable status amongst peoples about certain respects}}
{{Duplicated citations|reason=[[User:Polygnotus/DuplicateReferences|DuplicateReferences]] detected:<br>
* https://academic.oup.com/book/1566 (refs: 5, 7)
|date=October 2024}}
{{Globalize|date=January 2022}}
[[File:Pro marriage equality rally - 3032706279.jpg|alt=A pro-marriage equality rally in San Francisco, USA|thumb|upright=1.35|A pro-[[Same-sex marriage|marriage equality]] rally in [[San Francisco]], [[US]]]]


[[File:Equality symbol.svg|thumb|Equality symbol]]
{{More footnotes|date=October 2014}}


'''Social equality''' is a state of affairs in which all individuals within society have equal rights, liberties, and status, possibly including [[civil rights]], [[freedom of expression]], [[autonomy]], and equal access to certain [[Public good (economics)|public goods]] and [[social services]].
'''Social equality''' is a state of affairs in which all people within a specific [[Society|society]] or isolated group have the same status in possibly all respects, possibly including [[civil rights]], [[freedom of speech]], [[property rights]] and equal access to certain [[social goods]] and [[social services]]. However, it may also include [[health equality]], [[economic equality]] and other social securities. Social equality requires the absence of legally enforced [[social class]] or [[caste]] boundaries and the absence of [[discrimination]] motivated by an inalienable part of a person's identity.<ref name="Blackford">{{cite journal|last1=Blackford|first1=Russell|date=July 20, 2006|title=Genetic enhancement and the point of social equality|url=http://ieet.org/index.php/IEET/more/689/%20Genetic%20enhancement%20and%20the%20point%20of%20social%20equality|journal=Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies|volume=|pages=|via=}}</ref> For example, sex, gender, ethnicity, age, sexual orientation, origin, caste or class, income or property, language, religion, convictions, opinions, health or disability must absolutely not result in [[equal justice under law|equal treatment under the law]] and should not reduce opportunities unjustifiably.


Social equality requires the absence of legally enforced [[social class]] or [[caste]] boundaries and the absence of [[discrimination]] motivated by an inalienable part of an individual's identity.<ref name="Blackford">{{Citation |last=Blackford |first=Russell |title=Genetic enhancement and the point of social equality |date=20 July 2006 |url=http://ieet.org/index.php/IEET/more/689/%20Genetic%20enhancement%20and%20the%20point%20of%20social%20equality |work=Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies}}</ref> For example, advocates of social equality believe in [[equality before the law]] for all individuals regardless of sex, gender, ethnicity, age, sexual orientation, origin, caste or class, income or property, language, religion, convictions, opinions, health, or disability.<ref>{{Citation |last=Gosepath |first=Stefan |title=Equality |date=2021 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/equality/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Summer 2021 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=6 July 2021}}</ref><ref>{{Citation |last=Gruen |first=Lori |title=The Moral Status of Animals |date=2021 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/moral-animal/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Summer 2021 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=6 July 2021}}</ref>
''[[Equal opportunity|Equal opportunities]]'' is interpreted as being judged by ability, which is compatible with a [[free market]] economy. Relevant problems are [[horizontal inequality]] − the inequality of two persons of ''same'' origin and ability and differing opportunities given to individuals − such as in (education) or by inherited capital.
There are different types of social equality:<ref name="EU">[https://doi.org/10.1177/1358229120927947 De Vos, M. (2020). The European Court of Justice and the march towards substantive equality in European Union anti-discrimination law. International Journal of Discrimination and the Law, 20(1), 62-87.]</ref>
* ''[[Equal opportunity|Formal equality]]'': equal opportunity for individuals based on merit.
* ''[[Substantive equality]]'': [[equality of outcome]]s for groups, also called [[social equity]].


==Ontological==
== Definition ==
Social equality is variously defined and measured by different schools of thought. These include equality of [[Power (social and political)|power]], rights, [[goods]], [[Equal opportunity|opportunities]], capabilities, or some combination of these things. It may also be defined in comparison to [[Distributive justice|distributive]] equality, power structures between individuals, or [[justice]] and [[political egalitarianism]]. Societies that promote social equality generally do not make distinctions of rank or [[social class]], and [[interpersonal relationship]]s under a system of social equality are generally based on the idea of mutual [[respect]] and equal [[Value (ethics and social sciences)|value]] rather than [[hierarchy]] or [[honour]]. Many different ideologies draw from ideas of social equality, including [[communism]], [[anarchism]], [[multiculturalism]], [[republicanism]], [[democracy]], [[socialism]], and [[social democracy]]. The advocacy of social equality is [[egalitarianism]].<ref>{{Cite book |last1=Fourie |first1=Carina |url=https://academic.oup.com/book/1566 |title=Social Equality: On What It Means to be Equals |last2=Schuppert |first2=Fabian |last3=Wallimann-Helmer |first3=Ivo |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2014 |isbn=9780190212865 |pages=1–17 |chapter=The Nature and Distinctiveness of Social Equality: An Introduction}}</ref> Social equality is distinct from alleviating suffering of the unfortunate in society. It is an expression of the ideal that any two individuals in society should be treated with equal respect and have an equal right to participate in society without regard for social status or hierarchy.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Fourie |first=Carina |date=1 May 2012 |title=What is Social Equality? An Analysis of Status Equality as a Strongly Egalitarian Ideal |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-011-9162-2 |journal=Res Publica |language=en |volume=18 |issue=2 |pages=107–126 |doi=10.1007/s11158-011-9162-2 |s2cid=146141385 |issn=1572-8692}}</ref>
The standard of equality that states everyone is created equal at birth is called '''ontological equality'''. This type of equality can be seen in many different places like the [[Declaration of Independence]]. This early document, which states many of the values of the [[United States of America]], has this idea of equality embedded in it. It clearly states that "all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights". The statement reflects the philosophy of [[John Locke]] and his idea that we are all equal in certain [[natural rights theory|natural rights]]. Although this standard of equality is seen in documents as important as the Declaration of Independence, it is "one not often invoked in policy debates these days".<ref name=YMAY>{{cite book|last1=Conley|first1=Dalton|title=You May Ask Yourself|date=2013|publisher=[[W. W. Norton & Company]]|location=New York|edition=3rd}}</ref> However this notion of equality is often used to justify inequalities such as material inequality. Dalton Conley claims that ontological equality is used to justify material inequality by putting a spotlight on the fact, legitimated by theology, that "the distribution of power and resources here on earth does not matter, because all of us are equally children of God and will have to face our maker upon dying". [[Dalton Conley]], the author of ''You May Ask Yourself'', claims that ontological equality can also be used to put forth the notion that poverty is virtue. [[Luciano Floridi]], author of a book about [[information]], wrote about what he calls the ontological equality principle. His work on information ethics raises the importance of equality when presenting information. Here is a short sample of his work:
:Information ethics is impartial and universal because it brings to ultimate completion the process of enlargement of the concept of what may count as a centre of a (no matter how minimal) [[morality|moral claim]], which now includes every instance of being understood informationally, no matter whether physically implemented or not. In this respect information ethics holds that every entity as an expression of being, has a dignity constituted by its mode of existence and essence (the collection of all the elementary properties that constitute it for what it is), which deserve to be respected (at least in a minimal and overridable sense), and hence place moral claims on the interacting agent and ought to contribute to the constraint and guidance of his ethical decisions and behaviour.<ref name="Oxford">{{cite book|last1=Floridi|first1=Luciano|title=Very Short Introductions : Information: A Very Short Introduction|date=2010|publisher=Oxford}}</ref>
Floridi goes onto claim that this "ontological equality principle means that any form of reality (any instance of information/being), simply for the fact of being what it is, enjoys a minimal, initial, overridable, equal right to exist and develop in a way which is appropriate to its nature."<ref name="Oxford"/>
Values in his claims correlate to those shown in the sociological textbook ''You May Ask Yourself'' by Dalton Conley. The notion of "ontological equality" describes equality by saying everything is equal by nature. Everyone is created equal at birth. Everything has equal right to exist and develop by its nature.<ref name=YMAY/>


Social equality often pertains to how individuals relate to one another within a society, though it can also be considered in interactions between societies. Social hierarchies may form between [[State (polity)|states]] or their citizens when power disparities exist between them, particularly in the context of [[globalization]]. These disparities are often distinct in type as well as scope, as citizens in different states do not share a common community or social environment.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Nath |first=Rekha |url=https://academic.oup.com/book/1566 |title=Social Equality: On What It Means to be Equals |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2014 |isbn=9780190212865 |editor-last=Fourie |editor-first=Carina |pages=186–208 |chapter=On the Scope and Grounds of Social Equality |editor-last2=Schuppert |editor-first2=Fabian |editor-last3=Wallimann-Helmer |editor-first3=Ivo}}</ref> As advances are made in social equality, both internationally and within a society, the scope of social equality expands as new forms of [[social inequality]] become apparent and new solutions become possible.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Barnard |first=Catherine |date=2001 |title=The Changing Scope of the Fundamental Principle of Equality? |journal=McGill Law Journal |volume=46 |issue=4}}</ref>
==Opportunity==

=== Historical examples ===
Illustrating the combat fought in favour of this application on many fronts are the following episodes:

* The [[French Revolution]] of 1789 in view of the abolition of [[Privilege (law)|privileges]]
* The [[Bandung Conference]] and other anticolonialist movements reclaimed a better sharing of the world than that realized between great powers at the [[Yalta Conference]]
* The [[United Nations]] which – by its specialized institutions – seeks to promote more stable and concrete dialogue and cooperation between its members
* In France, trade union movements (as in 1936) or charitable movements, such as in France that of [[Abbé Pierre]], of [[International Movement ATD Fourth World]]
* The appeal to the establishment of [[equal opportunities]] appeals to the idea that people must be in the same conditions to try in life (with concrete initiatives, such as that of [[Muhammad Yunus]] in favour of [[microcredit]])

== Philosophical history ==
Early conceptions of social equality appear in [[Ancient Greek philosophy]]. The [[Stoicism|Stoic]] philosophers believed that human [[reason]] is universal. [[Plato]] considered the natures of equality when building society in the [[Republic (Plato)|'' Republic'']], including both a [[Monasticism|monastic]] equality and equality in depravity.<ref name=":0" /> [[Aristotle]] also developed a conception of equality, particularly regarding [[citizenship]], though he rejected the concept of total social equality in favour of social hierarchy.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Schwartzberg |first=Melissa |date=1 July 2016 |title=Aristotle and the Judgment of the Many: Equality, Not Collective Quality |url=https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/abs/10.1086/685000 |journal=The Journal of Politics |volume=78 |issue=3 |pages=733–745 |doi=10.1086/685000 |s2cid=147808630 |issn=0022-3816}}</ref> Social equality developed as a practicable element of society in Europe during the [[Reformation]] in which traditional religious hierarchies were challenged. The development of post-Reformation [[political philosophy]] provided a [[Secularism|secular]] foundation for social equality and [[political science]] created empirical systems to analyze social equality in practice.<ref name=":0">{{Cite book |last=Lakoff |first=Sanford A. |url=https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.4159/harvard.9780674493407.c1/html |title=Equality in Political Philosophy |publisher=Harvard University Press |year=1964 |isbn=978-0-674-49340-7 |pages=1–11 |language=en |chapter=Three Concepts of Equality |doi=10.4159/harvard.9780674493407.c1}}</ref>

The contemporary notion of social equality was developed in the 20th century by political philosophers such as [[John Rawls]], [[Ronald Dworkin]], and [[Amartya Sen]]. Rawls defined equality through [[primary goods]] like liberty, opportunity, respect, and wealth. Dworkin incorporated a concept of responsibility into Rawls' approach, saying that individuals are personally responsible for voluntary decisions but not natural talents or pre-dispositions. Sen rejected Rawls' measurement of resources in favour of the capability to function. [[Robert Nozick]] is known for rejecting Rawls' conception of social equality, arguing that the individual who produced a resource is entitled to it, even if this produces unequal results.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Wolff |first=Jonathan |date=1 January 2007 |title=Equality: The Recent History of an Idea |url=https://brill.com/view/journals/jmp/4/1/article-p125_13.xml |journal=Journal of Moral Philosophy |language=en |volume=4 |issue=1 |pages=125–136 |doi=10.1177/1740468107077389 |issn=1745-5243}}</ref>

== Types ==
Social equality is a major element of equality for any group in society. [[Gender equality]] includes social equality between [[men]], [[women]], and [[Intersex|intersex people]], whether [[transgender]] or [[cisgender]]. Internationally, women are harmed significantly more by a lack of gender equality, resulting in a higher risk of [[poverty]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Camilletti |first=Elena |date=18 May 2021 |title=Social Protection and Its Effects on Gender Equality: A Literature Review |url=https://www.un-ilibrary.org/content/papers/10.18356/25206796-2020-16 |journal= |series=Innocenti Working Papers |language=en |publisher=UNICEF Innocenti Research Centre |doi=10.18356/25206796-2020-16|s2cid=242414658 }}</ref> [[Racial equality]] and ethnic equality include social equality between people of different races and ethnic origins. Social equality can also be applied to belief and ideology, including equal social status for people of all political or religious beliefs.

The rights of people with [[Disability|disabilities]] pertain to social equality. Both physical and mental disabilities can prevent individuals from participating in society at an equal level, due to environmental factors as well as stigmas associated with disability. Social equality includes both the treatment of disabilities and the accommodation of people with disabilities to facilitate equal participation in society.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Rieser |first=Richard |title=Education, Equality and Human Rights: Issues of Gender, 'Race', Sexuality, Disability and Social Class |publisher=Taylor & Francis |year=2011 |isbn=9781136580994 |editor-last=Cole |editor-first=Mike |edition=3rd |chapter=The struggle for disability equality}}</ref>

== Means ==
[[Economic development]] and [[industrialization]] are correlated with increased social equality. The industrialization process in which a [[developing country]] becomes a [[developed country]] corresponds to a significant increase in social equality, and further economic development and growth in developed countries corresponds with further increases in social equality.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Jackman |first=Robert W. |date=1974 |title=Political Democracy and Social Equality: A Comparative Analysis |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2094274 |journal=American Sociological Review |volume=39 |issue=1 |pages=29–45 |doi=10.2307/2094274 |jstor=2094274 |issn=0003-1224}}</ref> [[Education]] and social equality are also correlated, and increased access to education promotes social equality among individuals.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Gylfason |first1=Thorvaldur |last2=Zoega |first2=Gylfi |date=2003 |title=Education, Social Equality and Economic Growth: A View of the Landscape |url=https://academic.oup.com/cesifo/article-abstract/49/4/557/353221 |journal=CESifo Economic Studies |volume=49 |issue=4 |pages=557–579 |doi=10.1093/cesifo/49.4.557|hdl=10419/76425 |hdl-access=free }}</ref>

== Standards ==
{{Essay-like|date=August 2022|section}}

=== Ontological ===
The standard of equality that states everyone is created equal at birth is called ''[[ontological]] equality''. This type of equality can be seen in many places like the [[United States Declaration of Independence]]. This early document, which states many of the values of the United States of America, has this idea of equality embedded in it. It says "[[all men are created equal]], that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights". The statement reflects the philosophy of [[John Locke]] and his idea that all are equal in terms of certain [[natural rights theory|natural rights]]. Although this standard of equality is seen in documents as important as the Declaration of Independence, it is "one not often invoked in policy debates these days".<ref name="YMAY">{{Citation |last=Conley |first=Dalton |title=You May Ask Yourself |date=2013 |edition=3rd |place=New York |publisher=[[W. W. Norton & Company]]}}</ref>

=== Opportunity ===
{{Main article|Equality of opportunity}}
{{Main article|Equality of opportunity}}


Another standard of equality is equality of opportunity, "the idea that everyone has an equal chance to achieve wealth, social prestige, and power because the rules of the game, so to speak, are the same for everyone".<ref name=YMAY/> This concept can be applied to society by saying that no one has a head start. This means that, for any social equality issue dealing with wealth, social prestige, power, or any of that sort, the equality of opportunity standard can defend the idea that everyone had the same start. This views society almost as a [[game]] and any of the differences in equality are due to luck and playing the "game" to one's best ability. Conley gives an example of this standard of equality by using a game of [[Monopoly (game)|Monopoly]] to describe society. He claims that "Monopoly follows the rules of equality of opportunity" by explaining that everyone had an equal chance when starting the game and any differences were a result of the luck of the dice roll and the skill of the player to make choices to benefit their wealth. Comparing this example to society, the standard of equality of opportunity eliminates inequality because the rules of the games in society are still fair and the same for all; therefore making any existing inequalities in society fair. Lesley A. Jacobs, the author of ''Pursuing Equal Opportunities: The Theory and Practice of Egalitarian Justice'', talks about equality of opportunity and its importance relating to egalitarian [[justice]]. Jacobs states that
Another standard of equality is equality of opportunity, "the idea that everyone has an equal chance to achieve wealth, social prestige, and power because the rules of the game, so to speak, are the same for everyone".<ref name=YMAY/> This concept can be applied to society by saying that no one has a head start. This means that, for any social equality issue dealing with wealth, social prestige, power, or any of that sort, the equality of opportunity standard can defend the idea that everyone had the same start. This views society almost as a game and any of the differences in equality standards are due to luck and playing the "game" to one's best ability.{{citation needed|date=May 2022}} [[Equal opportunity|Formal equality]] refers to equal opportunity for individuals based on merit while [[substantive equality]] reforms to [[equality of outcome]]s for groups.
:at the core of equality of opportunity... is the concept that in competitive procedures designed for the allocation of scarce resources and the distribution of the benefits and burdens of social life, those procedures should be governed by criteria that are relevant to the particular goods at stake in the competition and not by irrelevant considerations such as race, religion, class, gender, disability, sexual orientation, ethnicity, or other factors that may hinder some of the competitors’ opportunities at success. (Jacobs, 10).
This concept points out factors like [[race (biology)|race]], [[gender]], [[social class|class]] etc. that should not be considered when talking about equality through this notion. Conley also mentions that this standard of equality is at the heart of a [[bourgeoisie|bourgeois society]], such as a modern capitalist society, or "a society of commerce in which the maximization of profit is the primary business incentive".<ref name=YMAY/> It was the equal opportunity ideology that civil rights activists adopted in the era of the [[Civil Rights Movement]] in the 1960s. This ideology was used by them to argue that [[Jim Crow laws]] were incompatible with the standard of equality of opportunity.


Lesley A. Jacobs, the author of ''Pursuing Equal Opportunities: The Theory and Practice of Egalitarian Justice'', talks about equality of opportunity and its importance relating to egalitarian [[justice]]. Jacobs states that: at the core of equality of opportunity... is the concept that in competitive procedures designed for the allocation of scarce resources and the distribution of the benefits and burdens of social life, those procedures should be governed by criteria that are relevant to the particular goods at stake in the competition and not by irrelevant considerations such as race, religion, class, gender, disability, sexual orientation, ethnicity, or other factors that may hinder some of the competitors' opportunities at success. (Jacobs, 10).
==Condition==
{{Main article|Leveling mechanism}}
Another notion of equality introduced by Conley is equality of condition. Through this framework is the idea that everyone should have an equal starting point. Conley goes back to his example of a game of Monopoly to explain this standard. If the game of four started off with two players both having an advantage of $5,000 dollars to start off with and both already owning hotels and other property while the other two players both did not own any property and both started off with a $5,000 dollar deficit, then from a perspective of the standard of equality of condition, one can argue that the rules of the game "need to be altered in order to compensate for inequalities in the relative starting positions".<ref name=YMAY/> From this we form policies in order to even equality which in result bring an efficient way to create fairer [[competition]] in society. Here is where [[social engineering (political science)|social engineering]] comes into play where we change society in order to give an equality of [[human condition|condition]] to everyone based on race, gender, class, religion etc. when it is made justifiable that the proponents of the society makes it unfair for them.


This concept points out factors like [[race (human categorization)|race]], [[gender]], class, etc. that should not be considered when talking about equality through this notion. Conley also mentions that this standard of equality is at the heart of a [[bourgeoisie|bourgeois society]], such as a modern capitalist society, or "a society of commerce in which the maximization of profit is the primary business incentive".<ref name=YMAY/> It was the equal opportunity ideology that civil rights activists adopted in the era of the [[civil rights movement]] in the 1960s. This ideology was used by them to argue that [[Jim Crow laws]] were incompatible with the standard of equality of opportunity.
Sharon E. Kahn, author of ''Academic Freedom and the Inclusive University'', talks about equality of condition in their work as well and how it correlates to [[freedom]] of individuals. They claim that in order to have individual freedom there needs to be equality of condition "which requires much more than the elimination of legal barriers: it requires the creation of a [[level playing field]] that eliminates structural barriers to opportunity".<ref name="CAN: UBC Press">{{cite book|last1=Kahn|first1=Sharon|title=Academic Freedom and the Inclusive University|date=2000|publisher=CAN: UBC Press|location=Vancouver|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KSlKx1Lxlz8C&printsec=frontcover#v=onepage&q=equality&f=false|isbn=9780774808088}}</ref> Her work talks about the academic structure and its problem with equalities and claims that to "ensure equity...we need to recognize that the [[university]] structure and its organizational culture have traditionally privileged some and marginalized other; we need to go beyond theoretical concepts of equality by eliminating systemic barriers that hinder the equal participation of members of all groups; we need to create and equality of condition, not merely an equality of opportunity".<ref name="CAN: UBC Press"/> "Notions of equity, diversity, and inclusiveness begin with a set of premises about [[individualism]], freedom and rights that take as given the existence of deeply rooted inequalities in social structure," therefore in order to have a culture of the inclusive university, it would have to "be based on values of equity; that is, equality of condition" eliminating all systemic barriers that go against equality.<ref name="CAN: UBC Press"/>


==Outcome==
=== Condition ===
Another notion of equality introduced by Conley is equality of condition. Through this framework is the idea that everyone should have an equal starting point. Conley goes back to his example of a game of ''Monopoly'' to explain this standard. If the game of four started with two players both having an advantage of $5,000 to start with and both already owning hotels and other property while the other two players both did not own any property and both started with a $5,000 deficit, then from a perspective of the standard of equality of condition, one can argue that the rules of the game "need to be altered to compensate for inequalities in the relative starting positions".<ref name=YMAY/> From this we{{who|date=October 2023}} form policies to even equality which in result bring an efficient way to create fairer competition in society. Here is where [[social engineering (political science)|social engineering]] comes into play where we{{who|date=October 2023}} change society to give an equality of [[human condition|condition]] to everyone based on race, gender, class, religion, etc. when it is made justifiable that the proponents of the society make it unfair for them. {{citation needed|date=October 2023}}

Sharon E. Kahn, the author of ''Academic Freedom and the Inclusive University'', talks about equality of condition in their work as well and how it correlates to [[freedom]] of individuals. Kahn claims that in order to have individual freedom there needs to be equality of condition "which requires much more than the elimination of legal barriers: it requires the creation of a [[level playing field]] that eliminates structural barriers to opportunity".<ref name="CAN: UBC Press">{{Citation |last=Kahn |first=Sharon |title=Academic Freedom and the Inclusive University |date=2000 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KSlKx1Lxlz8C |place=Vancouver |publisher=CAN: UBC Press |isbn=9780774808088}}</ref> Her work refers to academic structure and its problem with equalities and claims that to "ensure equity... we need to recognize that the university structure and its organizational culture have traditionally privileged some and marginalized other; we need to go beyond theoretical concepts of equality by eliminating systemic barriers that hinder the equal participation of members of all groups; we need to create and equality of condition, not merely an equality of opportunity".<ref name="CAN: UBC Press" /> "Notions of equity, diversity, and inclusiveness begin with a set of premises about [[individualism]], freedom and rights that take as given the existence of deeply rooted inequalities in social structure," therefore in order to have a culture of the inclusive university, it would have to "be based on values of equity; that is, equality of condition" eliminating all systemic barriers that go against equality.<ref name="CAN: UBC Press" />

=== Outcome ===
{{Main article|Equality of outcome}}
{{Main article|Equality of outcome}}
A fourth standard of equality is equality of outcome, which is "a position that argues each player must end up with the same amount regardless of the fairness".<ref name=YMAY/> This ideology is predominately a [[Marxist philosophy]] that is concerned with equal distribution of power and resources rather than the rules of society. In this standard of equality, the idea is that "everyone contributes to society and to the economy according to what they do best".<ref name=YMAY/> Under this notion of equality, Conley states that "nobody will earn more power, prestige, and wealth by working harder".
The fourth standard of equality is equality of outcome, which is "a position that argues each player must end up with the same amount regardless of the fairness".<ref name=YMAY/> In this standard of equality, the idea is that "everyone contributes to society and the economy according to what they do best".<ref name="YMAY" /> Under this notion of equality, Conley states that "nobody will earn more power, prestige, and wealth by working harder". Equality of outcome is often falsely conflated with [[communism]] or [[Marxist philosophy]] even though these ideologies promote the distribution of resources based on [[From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs|need]] or [[To each according to his contribution|contribution]] (depending on the level of development of a society's [[productive forces]]) rather than equality. [[Vladimir Lenin]] stated that the "abolition of classes means placing ''all'' citizens on an ''equal'' footing about the ''means of production'' belonging to society as a whole. It means giving all citizens ''equal'' opportunities of working on the publicly-owned means of production, on the publicly-owned land, at the publicly-owned factories, and so forth".<ref>{{Cite web |title=Lenin: A Liberal Professor on Equality |url=https://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1914/mar/11.htm |access-date=6 July 2022 |website=www.marxists.org}}</ref>


When defining equality of outcome in [[education]], "the goals should not be the liberal one of equality of access but equality of outcome for the median number of each identifiable non-educationally defined group, i.e. the average women, negro, or proletarian or rural dweller should have the same level of educational attainment as the average male, white, suburbanite".<ref name="Palgrave Macmillan">{{cite book|last1=Hewitt|first1=Martin|title=Welfare & Human Nature : The Human Subject in Twentieth-Century Social Politics|date=2000|publisher=Palgrave Macmillan|location=New York}}</ref> The outcome and the benefits from equality from education from this notion of equality promotes that all should have the same outcomes and benefits regardless of race, gender, religion etc. The equality of outcome in Hewitt's point of view is supposed to result in "a comparable range of achievements between a specific [[disadvantaged]] group – such as an ethnic [[minority group|minority]], women, lone parents and the disabled – and society as a whole".<ref name="Palgrave Macmillan"/>
When defining equality of outcome in education, "the goals should not be the liberal one of equality of access but equality of outcome for the median number of each identifiable non-educationally defined group, i.e. the average women, negro, or [[Proletariat|proletarian]] or rural dweller should have the same level of educational attainment as the average male, white, suburbanite".<ref name="Palgrave Macmillan">{{Cite book |last=Hewitt |first=Martin |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Rh6JDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA58 |title=Welfare and human nature: the human subject in twentieth-century social politics |date=2000 |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-312-23409-6 |location=Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire |oclc=43499436}}</ref> The outcome and the benefits from equality from education from this notion of equality promotes that all should have the same outcomes and benefits regardless of race, gender, religion etc. The equality of outcome in Hewitt's point of view is supposed to result in "a comparable range of achievements between a specific [[disadvantaged]] group – such as an ethnic [[minority group|minority]], women, lone parents and the disabled – and society as a whole".<ref name="Palgrave Macmillan" />

Information ethics is impartial and universal because it brings to ultimate completion the process of enlargement of the concept of what may count as a centre of a (no matter how minimal) [[morality|moral claim]], which now includes every instance of being understood informationally, no matter whether physically implemented or not. In this respect, information ethics holds that every entity as an expression of being has a dignity constituted by its mode of existence and essence (the collection of all the elementary properties that constitute it for what it is), which deserve to be respected (at least in a minimal and overridable sense), and hence place moral claims on the interacting agent and ought to contribute to the constraint and guidance of his ethical decisions and behaviour.<ref name="Oxford">{{Cite book |last=Floridi |first=Luciano |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/743804876 |title=Information: a very short introduction |date=2010 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-157298-2 |location=Oxford |oclc=743804876}}</ref> Floridi goes on to claim that this "ontological equality principle means that any form of reality (any instance of information/being), simply for the fact of being what it is, enjoys a minimal, initial, overridable, equal right to exist and develop in a way which is appropriate to its nature."<ref name="Oxford" /> Values in his claims correlate to those shown in the sociological textbook ''You May Ask Yourself'' by Dalton Conley. The notion of "ontological equality" describes equality by saying everything is equal by nature. Everyone is created equal at birth. Everything has an equal right to exist and develop by its nature.<ref name=YMAY/>


==References==
==References==
{{reflist|30em}}
{{reflist}}


==Further reading==
==Further reading==
{{Refbegin|30em}}
{{Refbegin|30em}}
* [[Matthew Arnold|Arnold, Matthew]] (18759). [https://archive.org/stream/mixedessays00arnorich#page/48/mode/2up "Equality."] In: ''Mixed Essays''. New York: Macmillan & Co., pp.&nbsp;48–97.
* [[Matthew Arnold|Arnold, Mathew]] (18759). "Equality." In: ''Mixed Essays''. New York: Macmillan & Co., pp.&nbsp;48–97.
* {{Citation |last=Bell |first=Daniel |title=On meritocracy and equality |url=https://www.nationalaffairs.com/storage/app/uploads/public/58e/1a4/b60/58e1a4b603517781616817.pdf |work=[[The Public Interest]] |volume=29 |pages=29–68 |year=1972 |author-link=Daniel Bell}}
* [[Daniel Bell|Bell, Daniel]] (1972). [http://www.nationalaffairs.com/doclib/20080527_197202902onmeritocracyandequalitydanielbell.pdf "On Meritocracy and Equality,"]{{dead link|date=March 2018 |bot=InternetArchiveBot |fix-attempted=yes }} ''The Public Interest'', No. 29, pp.&nbsp;29–68.
* [[James Bryce, 1st Viscount Bryce|Bryce, James]] (1898). [http://ebooks.library.cornell.edu/cgi/t/text/pageviewer-idx?c=cent;g=moagrp;xc=1;q1=Woman%20Suffrage;rgn=full%20text;view=image;cc=cent;seq=0469;idno=cent0056-3;node=cent0056-3%3A17 "Equality,"] ''The Century; A Popular Quarterly,'' Vol. 56, No. 3, pp.&nbsp;459–469.
* [[James Bryce, 1st Viscount Bryce|Bryce, James]] (1898). "Equality," ''The Century; A Popular Quarterly,'' Vol. 56, No. 3, pp.&nbsp;459–469.
* [[Rudolf Dreikurs|Dreikurs, Rudolf]] (1983). ''Social Equality; The Challenge of Today.'' Chicago, IL: Alfred Adler Institute of Chicago.
* [[Rudolf Dreikurs|Dreikurs, Rudolf]] (1983). ''Social Equality; The Challenge of Today.'' Chicago, IL: Alfred Adler Institute of Chicago.
* Gil, David G. (1976). ''The Challenge of Social Equality.'' Cambridge: Schenkman Pub. Co.
* Gil, David G. (1976). ''The Challenge of Social Equality.'' Cambridge: Schenkman Pub. Co.
* Hyneman, Charles S. (1980). [http://www.unz.org/Pub/ModernAge-1980q3-00226 "Equality: Elusive Ideal or Beguiling Delusion?,"] ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIV, No. 3, pp.&nbsp;226–237.
* Hyneman, Charles S. (1980). "Equality: Elusive Ideal or Beguiling Delusion?" ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIV, No. 3, pp.&nbsp;226–237.
* Jackman, Robert W. (1975). ''Politics and Social Equality.'' New York: Wiley.
* Jackman, Robert W. (1975). ''Politics and Social Equality.'' New York: Wiley.
* Lane, Robert E. (1959). "The Fear of Equality," ''The American Political Science Review,'' Vol. 53, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;35–51.
* Lane, Robert E. (1959). "The Fear of Equality," ''The American Political Science Review,'' Vol. 53, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;35–51.
* [[John Lucas (philosopher)|Lucas, J.R.]] (1965). [http://users.ox.ac.uk/~jrlucas/libeqsor/equality.html "Against Equality,"] ''Philosophy'', Vol. 40, pp.&nbsp;296–307.
* [[John Lucas (philosopher)|Lucas, J.R.]] (1965). "Against Equality," ''Philosophy'', Vol. 40, pp.&nbsp;296–307.
* [[John Lucas (philosopher)|Lucas, J.R.]] (1977). [https://web.archive.org/web/20121104232114/http://users.ox.ac.uk/~jrlucas/libeqsor/equag.html "Against Equality Again,"] ''Philosophy'', Vol. 52, pp.&nbsp;255–280.
* [[John Lucas (philosopher)|Lucas, J.R.]] (1977). "Against Equality Again," ''Philosophy'', Vol. 52, pp.&nbsp;255–280.
* [[William Hurrell Mallock|Mallock, William H.]] (1882). [https://archive.org/stream/socialequalitysh00mall#page/250/mode/2up ''Social Equality: A Short Study in a Missing Science.''] London: Richard Bentley and Son.
* [[William Hurrell Mallock|Mallock, William H.]] (1882). ''Social Equality: A Short Study in a Missing Science.'' London: Richard Bentley and Son.
* Merwin, Henry Childs (1897). [http://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=mdp.39015030108370;view=1up;seq=364 "The American Notion of Equality,"] ''The Atlantic Monthly,'' Vol. 80, pp.&nbsp;354–363.
* Merwin, Henry Childs (1897). "The American Notion of Equality," ''The Atlantic Monthly,'' Vol. 80, pp.&nbsp;354–363.
* [[Thomas Nagel|Nagel, Thomas]] (1978). "The Justification of Equality," ''Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía,'' Vol. 10, No. 28, pp.&nbsp;3–31.'''
* [[Thomas Nagel|Nagel, Thomas]] (1978). "The Justification of Equality," ''Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía,'' Vol. 10, No. 28, pp.&nbsp;3–31.
* {{Citation |last=Nisbet |first=Robert |title=The Pursuit of Equality |url=https://www.nationalaffairs.com/storage/app/uploads/public/58e/1a4/baa/58e1a4baacc8c820214073.pdf |work=The Public Interest |volume=35 |pages=103–120 |year=1974 |author-link=Robert Nisbet}}
* Nisbet, Richard (1974). [http://www.nationalaffairs.com/doclib/20080527_197403506thepursuitofequalityrobertnisbet.pdf "The Pursuit of Equality"]{{dead link|date=June 2019|bot=InternetArchiveBot |fix-attempted=yes }}, ''The Public Interest'', Vol. 35, pp.&nbsp;103–120.
* {{cite book |last=Piketty|first=Thomas |author-link=Thomas Piketty|date=2022 |title=[[A Brief History of Equality]]|location= |publisher=[[Harvard University Press]]|isbn=978-0674273559}}
* [[Murray Rothbard|Rothbard, Murray N.]] (1995). [http://www.lewrockwell.com/2014/09/murray-n-rothbard/why-the-power-elite-loves-equality/ "Egalitarianism and the Elites,"] ''The Review of Austrian Economics'', Vol. 8, No. 2, pp.&nbsp;39–57.
* [[Louis Rougier|Rougier, Louis]] (1974). [http://www.unz.org/Pub/ModernAge-1974q1-00029 "Philosophical Origins of the Idea of Natural Equality,"] ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XVIII, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;29–38.
* [[Murray Rothbard|Rothbard, Murray N.]] (1995). "Egalitarianism and the Elites," ''The Review of Austrian Economics'', Vol. 8, No. 2, pp.&nbsp;39–57.
* [[James Fitzjames Stephen|Stephen, James Fitzjames]] (1873). [https://archive.org/stream/libertyequality00stepgoog#page/n196/mode/2up "Equality."] In: ''Liberty, Equality, Fraternity.'' New York: Holt & Williams, pp.&nbsp;189–255.
* [[Louis Rougier|Rougier, Louis]] (1974). "Philosophical Origins of the Idea of Natural Equality," ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XVIII, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;29–38.
* [[Leslie Stephen|Stephen, Leslie]] (1891). [https://www.jstor.org/stable/2375306 "Social Equality,"] ''International Journal of Ethics,'' Vol. 1, No. 3, pp.&nbsp;261–288.
* [[James Fitzjames Stephen|Stephen, James Fitzjames]] (1873). "Equality." In: ''Liberty, Equality, Fraternity.'' New York: Holt & Williams, pp.&nbsp;189–255.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1979). [http://www.unz.org/Pub/ModernAge-1979q1-00002 "Liberty and Equality as Absolutes,"] ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIII, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;2–9.
* [[Leslie Stephen|Stephen, Leslie]] (1891). "Social Equality," ''International Journal of Ethics,'' Vol. 1, No. 3, pp.&nbsp;261–288.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). [http://www.unz.org/Pub/ModernAge-1980q2-00134 "Equality and Ancient Society,"] ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIV, No. 2, pp.&nbsp;134–141.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1979). "Liberty and Equality as Absolutes," ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIII, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;2–9.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). [http://www.unz.org/Pub/ModernAge-1980q3-00238 "The New Natural Law and the Problem of Equality,"] ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIV, No. 3, pp.&nbsp;238–247.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). "Equality and Ancient Society," ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIV, No. 2, pp.&nbsp;134–141.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). [http://www.unz.org/Pub/ModernAge-1980q4-00345 "Equality in the New Testament,"] ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIV, No. 4, pp.&nbsp;345–354.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). "Equality in the New Testament," ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIV, No. 4, pp.&nbsp;345–354.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1981). [http://www.unz.org/Pub/ModernAge-1981q1-00046 "Equality: The Greek Historical Experience,"] ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXV, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;46–55.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). "The New Natural Law and the Problem of Equality," ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXIV, No. 3, pp.&nbsp;238–247.
* Velasco, Gustavo R. (1974). [http://www.unz.org/Pub/ModernAge-1974q1-00021 "On Equality and Egalitarianism,"] ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XVIII, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;21–28.
* Tonsor, Stephen J. (1981). "Equality: The Greek Historical Experience," ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XXV, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;46–55.
* Velasco, Gustavo R. (1974). "On Equality and Egalitarianism," ''The Modern Age'', Vol. XVIII, No. 1, pp.&nbsp;21–28.
{{Refend}}'''
{{Refend}}

==External links==
* {{Commons category-inline}}

{{Authority control}}


[[Category:Social systems]]
[[Category:Social systems]]

Latest revision as of 14:36, 11 December 2024

A pro-marriage equality rally in San Francisco, USA
A pro-marriage equality rally in San Francisco, US
Equality symbol

Social equality is a state of affairs in which all individuals within society have equal rights, liberties, and status, possibly including civil rights, freedom of expression, autonomy, and equal access to certain public goods and social services.

Social equality requires the absence of legally enforced social class or caste boundaries and the absence of discrimination motivated by an inalienable part of an individual's identity.[1] For example, advocates of social equality believe in equality before the law for all individuals regardless of sex, gender, ethnicity, age, sexual orientation, origin, caste or class, income or property, language, religion, convictions, opinions, health, or disability.[2][3] There are different types of social equality:[4]

Definition

[edit]

Social equality is variously defined and measured by different schools of thought. These include equality of power, rights, goods, opportunities, capabilities, or some combination of these things. It may also be defined in comparison to distributive equality, power structures between individuals, or justice and political egalitarianism. Societies that promote social equality generally do not make distinctions of rank or social class, and interpersonal relationships under a system of social equality are generally based on the idea of mutual respect and equal value rather than hierarchy or honour. Many different ideologies draw from ideas of social equality, including communism, anarchism, multiculturalism, republicanism, democracy, socialism, and social democracy. The advocacy of social equality is egalitarianism.[5] Social equality is distinct from alleviating suffering of the unfortunate in society. It is an expression of the ideal that any two individuals in society should be treated with equal respect and have an equal right to participate in society without regard for social status or hierarchy.[6]

Social equality often pertains to how individuals relate to one another within a society, though it can also be considered in interactions between societies. Social hierarchies may form between states or their citizens when power disparities exist between them, particularly in the context of globalization. These disparities are often distinct in type as well as scope, as citizens in different states do not share a common community or social environment.[7] As advances are made in social equality, both internationally and within a society, the scope of social equality expands as new forms of social inequality become apparent and new solutions become possible.[8]

Historical examples

[edit]

Illustrating the combat fought in favour of this application on many fronts are the following episodes:

Philosophical history

[edit]

Early conceptions of social equality appear in Ancient Greek philosophy. The Stoic philosophers believed that human reason is universal. Plato considered the natures of equality when building society in the Republic, including both a monastic equality and equality in depravity.[9] Aristotle also developed a conception of equality, particularly regarding citizenship, though he rejected the concept of total social equality in favour of social hierarchy.[10] Social equality developed as a practicable element of society in Europe during the Reformation in which traditional religious hierarchies were challenged. The development of post-Reformation political philosophy provided a secular foundation for social equality and political science created empirical systems to analyze social equality in practice.[9]

The contemporary notion of social equality was developed in the 20th century by political philosophers such as John Rawls, Ronald Dworkin, and Amartya Sen. Rawls defined equality through primary goods like liberty, opportunity, respect, and wealth. Dworkin incorporated a concept of responsibility into Rawls' approach, saying that individuals are personally responsible for voluntary decisions but not natural talents or pre-dispositions. Sen rejected Rawls' measurement of resources in favour of the capability to function. Robert Nozick is known for rejecting Rawls' conception of social equality, arguing that the individual who produced a resource is entitled to it, even if this produces unequal results.[11]

Types

[edit]

Social equality is a major element of equality for any group in society. Gender equality includes social equality between men, women, and intersex people, whether transgender or cisgender. Internationally, women are harmed significantly more by a lack of gender equality, resulting in a higher risk of poverty.[12] Racial equality and ethnic equality include social equality between people of different races and ethnic origins. Social equality can also be applied to belief and ideology, including equal social status for people of all political or religious beliefs.

The rights of people with disabilities pertain to social equality. Both physical and mental disabilities can prevent individuals from participating in society at an equal level, due to environmental factors as well as stigmas associated with disability. Social equality includes both the treatment of disabilities and the accommodation of people with disabilities to facilitate equal participation in society.[13]

Means

[edit]

Economic development and industrialization are correlated with increased social equality. The industrialization process in which a developing country becomes a developed country corresponds to a significant increase in social equality, and further economic development and growth in developed countries corresponds with further increases in social equality.[14] Education and social equality are also correlated, and increased access to education promotes social equality among individuals.[15]

Standards

[edit]

Ontological

[edit]

The standard of equality that states everyone is created equal at birth is called ontological equality. This type of equality can be seen in many places like the United States Declaration of Independence. This early document, which states many of the values of the United States of America, has this idea of equality embedded in it. It says "all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights". The statement reflects the philosophy of John Locke and his idea that all are equal in terms of certain natural rights. Although this standard of equality is seen in documents as important as the Declaration of Independence, it is "one not often invoked in policy debates these days".[16]

Opportunity

[edit]

Another standard of equality is equality of opportunity, "the idea that everyone has an equal chance to achieve wealth, social prestige, and power because the rules of the game, so to speak, are the same for everyone".[16] This concept can be applied to society by saying that no one has a head start. This means that, for any social equality issue dealing with wealth, social prestige, power, or any of that sort, the equality of opportunity standard can defend the idea that everyone had the same start. This views society almost as a game and any of the differences in equality standards are due to luck and playing the "game" to one's best ability.[citation needed] Formal equality refers to equal opportunity for individuals based on merit while substantive equality reforms to equality of outcomes for groups.

Lesley A. Jacobs, the author of Pursuing Equal Opportunities: The Theory and Practice of Egalitarian Justice, talks about equality of opportunity and its importance relating to egalitarian justice. Jacobs states that: at the core of equality of opportunity... is the concept that in competitive procedures designed for the allocation of scarce resources and the distribution of the benefits and burdens of social life, those procedures should be governed by criteria that are relevant to the particular goods at stake in the competition and not by irrelevant considerations such as race, religion, class, gender, disability, sexual orientation, ethnicity, or other factors that may hinder some of the competitors' opportunities at success. (Jacobs, 10).

This concept points out factors like race, gender, class, etc. that should not be considered when talking about equality through this notion. Conley also mentions that this standard of equality is at the heart of a bourgeois society, such as a modern capitalist society, or "a society of commerce in which the maximization of profit is the primary business incentive".[16] It was the equal opportunity ideology that civil rights activists adopted in the era of the civil rights movement in the 1960s. This ideology was used by them to argue that Jim Crow laws were incompatible with the standard of equality of opportunity.

Condition

[edit]

Another notion of equality introduced by Conley is equality of condition. Through this framework is the idea that everyone should have an equal starting point. Conley goes back to his example of a game of Monopoly to explain this standard. If the game of four started with two players both having an advantage of $5,000 to start with and both already owning hotels and other property while the other two players both did not own any property and both started with a $5,000 deficit, then from a perspective of the standard of equality of condition, one can argue that the rules of the game "need to be altered to compensate for inequalities in the relative starting positions".[16] From this we[who?] form policies to even equality which in result bring an efficient way to create fairer competition in society. Here is where social engineering comes into play where we[who?] change society to give an equality of condition to everyone based on race, gender, class, religion, etc. when it is made justifiable that the proponents of the society make it unfair for them. [citation needed]

Sharon E. Kahn, the author of Academic Freedom and the Inclusive University, talks about equality of condition in their work as well and how it correlates to freedom of individuals. Kahn claims that in order to have individual freedom there needs to be equality of condition "which requires much more than the elimination of legal barriers: it requires the creation of a level playing field that eliminates structural barriers to opportunity".[17] Her work refers to academic structure and its problem with equalities and claims that to "ensure equity... we need to recognize that the university structure and its organizational culture have traditionally privileged some and marginalized other; we need to go beyond theoretical concepts of equality by eliminating systemic barriers that hinder the equal participation of members of all groups; we need to create and equality of condition, not merely an equality of opportunity".[17] "Notions of equity, diversity, and inclusiveness begin with a set of premises about individualism, freedom and rights that take as given the existence of deeply rooted inequalities in social structure," therefore in order to have a culture of the inclusive university, it would have to "be based on values of equity; that is, equality of condition" eliminating all systemic barriers that go against equality.[17]

Outcome

[edit]

The fourth standard of equality is equality of outcome, which is "a position that argues each player must end up with the same amount regardless of the fairness".[16] In this standard of equality, the idea is that "everyone contributes to society and the economy according to what they do best".[16] Under this notion of equality, Conley states that "nobody will earn more power, prestige, and wealth by working harder". Equality of outcome is often falsely conflated with communism or Marxist philosophy even though these ideologies promote the distribution of resources based on need or contribution (depending on the level of development of a society's productive forces) rather than equality. Vladimir Lenin stated that the "abolition of classes means placing all citizens on an equal footing about the means of production belonging to society as a whole. It means giving all citizens equal opportunities of working on the publicly-owned means of production, on the publicly-owned land, at the publicly-owned factories, and so forth".[18]

When defining equality of outcome in education, "the goals should not be the liberal one of equality of access but equality of outcome for the median number of each identifiable non-educationally defined group, i.e. the average women, negro, or proletarian or rural dweller should have the same level of educational attainment as the average male, white, suburbanite".[19] The outcome and the benefits from equality from education from this notion of equality promotes that all should have the same outcomes and benefits regardless of race, gender, religion etc. The equality of outcome in Hewitt's point of view is supposed to result in "a comparable range of achievements between a specific disadvantaged group – such as an ethnic minority, women, lone parents and the disabled – and society as a whole".[19]

Information ethics is impartial and universal because it brings to ultimate completion the process of enlargement of the concept of what may count as a centre of a (no matter how minimal) moral claim, which now includes every instance of being understood informationally, no matter whether physically implemented or not. In this respect, information ethics holds that every entity as an expression of being has a dignity constituted by its mode of existence and essence (the collection of all the elementary properties that constitute it for what it is), which deserve to be respected (at least in a minimal and overridable sense), and hence place moral claims on the interacting agent and ought to contribute to the constraint and guidance of his ethical decisions and behaviour.[20] Floridi goes on to claim that this "ontological equality principle means that any form of reality (any instance of information/being), simply for the fact of being what it is, enjoys a minimal, initial, overridable, equal right to exist and develop in a way which is appropriate to its nature."[20] Values in his claims correlate to those shown in the sociological textbook You May Ask Yourself by Dalton Conley. The notion of "ontological equality" describes equality by saying everything is equal by nature. Everyone is created equal at birth. Everything has an equal right to exist and develop by its nature.[16]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Blackford, Russell (20 July 2006), "Genetic enhancement and the point of social equality", Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies
  2. ^ Gosepath, Stefan (2021), "Equality", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2021 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 6 July 2021
  3. ^ Gruen, Lori (2021), "The Moral Status of Animals", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2021 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 6 July 2021
  4. ^ De Vos, M. (2020). The European Court of Justice and the march towards substantive equality in European Union anti-discrimination law. International Journal of Discrimination and the Law, 20(1), 62-87.
  5. ^ Fourie, Carina; Schuppert, Fabian; Wallimann-Helmer, Ivo (2014). "The Nature and Distinctiveness of Social Equality: An Introduction". Social Equality: On What It Means to be Equals. Oxford University Press. pp. 1–17. ISBN 9780190212865.
  6. ^ Fourie, Carina (1 May 2012). "What is Social Equality? An Analysis of Status Equality as a Strongly Egalitarian Ideal". Res Publica. 18 (2): 107–126. doi:10.1007/s11158-011-9162-2. ISSN 1572-8692. S2CID 146141385.
  7. ^ Nath, Rekha (2014). "On the Scope and Grounds of Social Equality". In Fourie, Carina; Schuppert, Fabian; Wallimann-Helmer, Ivo (eds.). Social Equality: On What It Means to be Equals. Oxford University Press. pp. 186–208. ISBN 9780190212865.
  8. ^ Barnard, Catherine (2001). "The Changing Scope of the Fundamental Principle of Equality?". McGill Law Journal. 46 (4).
  9. ^ a b Lakoff, Sanford A. (1964). "Three Concepts of Equality". Equality in Political Philosophy. Harvard University Press. pp. 1–11. doi:10.4159/harvard.9780674493407.c1. ISBN 978-0-674-49340-7.
  10. ^ Schwartzberg, Melissa (1 July 2016). "Aristotle and the Judgment of the Many: Equality, Not Collective Quality". The Journal of Politics. 78 (3): 733–745. doi:10.1086/685000. ISSN 0022-3816. S2CID 147808630.
  11. ^ Wolff, Jonathan (1 January 2007). "Equality: The Recent History of an Idea". Journal of Moral Philosophy. 4 (1): 125–136. doi:10.1177/1740468107077389. ISSN 1745-5243.
  12. ^ Camilletti, Elena (18 May 2021). "Social Protection and Its Effects on Gender Equality: A Literature Review". Innocenti Working Papers. UNICEF Innocenti Research Centre. doi:10.18356/25206796-2020-16. S2CID 242414658. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  13. ^ Rieser, Richard (2011). "The struggle for disability equality". In Cole, Mike (ed.). Education, Equality and Human Rights: Issues of Gender, 'Race', Sexuality, Disability and Social Class (3rd ed.). Taylor & Francis. ISBN 9781136580994.
  14. ^ Jackman, Robert W. (1974). "Political Democracy and Social Equality: A Comparative Analysis". American Sociological Review. 39 (1): 29–45. doi:10.2307/2094274. ISSN 0003-1224. JSTOR 2094274.
  15. ^ Gylfason, Thorvaldur; Zoega, Gylfi (2003). "Education, Social Equality and Economic Growth: A View of the Landscape". CESifo Economic Studies. 49 (4): 557–579. doi:10.1093/cesifo/49.4.557. hdl:10419/76425.
  16. ^ a b c d e f g Conley, Dalton (2013), You May Ask Yourself (3rd ed.), New York: W. W. Norton & Company
  17. ^ a b c Kahn, Sharon (2000), Academic Freedom and the Inclusive University, Vancouver: CAN: UBC Press, ISBN 9780774808088
  18. ^ "Lenin: A Liberal Professor on Equality". www.marxists.org. Retrieved 6 July 2022.
  19. ^ a b Hewitt, Martin (2000). Welfare and human nature: the human subject in twentieth-century social politics. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-312-23409-6. OCLC 43499436.
  20. ^ a b Floridi, Luciano (2010). Information: a very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-157298-2. OCLC 743804876.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Arnold, Mathew (18759). "Equality." In: Mixed Essays. New York: Macmillan & Co., pp. 48–97.
  • Bell, Daniel (1972), "On meritocracy and equality" (PDF), The Public Interest, vol. 29, pp. 29–68
  • Bryce, James (1898). "Equality," The Century; A Popular Quarterly, Vol. 56, No. 3, pp. 459–469.
  • Dreikurs, Rudolf (1983). Social Equality; The Challenge of Today. Chicago, IL: Alfred Adler Institute of Chicago.
  • Gil, David G. (1976). The Challenge of Social Equality. Cambridge: Schenkman Pub. Co.
  • Hyneman, Charles S. (1980). "Equality: Elusive Ideal or Beguiling Delusion?" The Modern Age, Vol. XXIV, No. 3, pp. 226–237.
  • Jackman, Robert W. (1975). Politics and Social Equality. New York: Wiley.
  • Lane, Robert E. (1959). "The Fear of Equality," The American Political Science Review, Vol. 53, No. 1, pp. 35–51.
  • Lucas, J.R. (1965). "Against Equality," Philosophy, Vol. 40, pp. 296–307.
  • Lucas, J.R. (1977). "Against Equality Again," Philosophy, Vol. 52, pp. 255–280.
  • Mallock, William H. (1882). Social Equality: A Short Study in a Missing Science. London: Richard Bentley and Son.
  • Merwin, Henry Childs (1897). "The American Notion of Equality," The Atlantic Monthly, Vol. 80, pp. 354–363.
  • Nagel, Thomas (1978). "The Justification of Equality," Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, Vol. 10, No. 28, pp. 3–31.
  • Nisbet, Robert (1974), "The Pursuit of Equality" (PDF), The Public Interest, vol. 35, pp. 103–120
  • Piketty, Thomas (2022). A Brief History of Equality. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674273559.
  • Rothbard, Murray N. (1995). "Egalitarianism and the Elites," The Review of Austrian Economics, Vol. 8, No. 2, pp. 39–57.
  • Rougier, Louis (1974). "Philosophical Origins of the Idea of Natural Equality," The Modern Age, Vol. XVIII, No. 1, pp. 29–38.
  • Stephen, James Fitzjames (1873). "Equality." In: Liberty, Equality, Fraternity. New York: Holt & Williams, pp. 189–255.
  • Stephen, Leslie (1891). "Social Equality," International Journal of Ethics, Vol. 1, No. 3, pp. 261–288.
  • Tonsor, Stephen J. (1979). "Liberty and Equality as Absolutes," The Modern Age, Vol. XXIII, No. 1, pp. 2–9.
  • Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). "Equality and Ancient Society," The Modern Age, Vol. XXIV, No. 2, pp. 134–141.
  • Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). "Equality in the New Testament," The Modern Age, Vol. XXIV, No. 4, pp. 345–354.
  • Tonsor, Stephen J. (1980). "The New Natural Law and the Problem of Equality," The Modern Age, Vol. XXIV, No. 3, pp. 238–247.
  • Tonsor, Stephen J. (1981). "Equality: The Greek Historical Experience," The Modern Age, Vol. XXV, No. 1, pp. 46–55.
  • Velasco, Gustavo R. (1974). "On Equality and Egalitarianism," The Modern Age, Vol. XVIII, No. 1, pp. 21–28.
[edit]