Jump to content

Thomas Aquinas: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Pcjivs (talk | contribs)
Canonization: Added date of canonization within the text
Line 31: Line 31:
== Biography ==
== Biography ==
===Early years and desire to become a Dominican (1225–1240)===
===Early years and desire to become a Dominican (1225–1240)===
Thomas was born in [[Aquino]] c.January 28, 1225, according to some authors in his father's, the Count Landulf of Aquino, castle placed in [[Roccasecca]], in the same Contea di Aquino ([[Kingdom of Sicily]], in the present-day: [[Lazio]]). Through his mother, Theodora Countess of Theate, Thomas was related to the [[Hohenstaufen]] dynasty of [[Holy Roman emperor]]s.<ref name="schaff-422">Schaff, p. [http://www.ccel.org/ccel/schaff/encyc11/Page_422.html p. 422].</ref> Landulf's brother Sinibald was [[abbot]] of the original [[Benedictine]] [[abbey]] at [[Monte Cassino]]. While the rest of the family's sons pursued a military career,<ref>Hampden, ''The Life'', p. 14.</ref> the family intended for Thomas to follow his uncle into the abbacy;<ref name="stump3">Stump, ''Aquinas'', p. 3.</ref> this would have been a normal career path for a younger son of southern Italian nobility.<ref name="schaff-422"/>
Thomas was born in [[Aquino]] c.January 28, 1235, according to some authors in his father's, the Count Landulf of Aquino, castle placed in [[Roccasecca]], in the same Contea di Aquino ([[Kingdom of Sicily]], in the present-day: [[Lazio]]). Through his mother, Theodora Countess of Theate, Thomas was related to the [[Hohenstaufen]] dynasty of [[Holy Roman emperor]]s.<ref name="schaff-422">Schaff, p. [http://www.ccel.org/ccel/schaff/encyc11/Page_422.html p. 422].</ref> Landulf's brother Sinibald was [[abbot]] of the original [[Benedictine]] [[abbey]] at [[Monte Cassino]]. While the rest of the family's sons pursued a military career,<ref>Hampden, ''The Life'', p. 14.</ref> the family intended for Thomas to follow his uncle into the abbacy;<ref name="stump3">Stump, ''Aquinas'', p. 3.</ref> this would have been a normal career path for a younger son of southern Italian nobility.<ref name="schaff-422"/>


At the age of five, Thomas began his early education at Monte Cassino but after the military conflict that broke out between the [[Emperor Frederick II]] and [[Pope Gregory IX]] spilled into the abbey in early 1239, Landulf and Theodora had Thomas enrolled at the ''studium generale'' (university) recently established by Frederick in [[Naples]].<ref>Davies, ''Aquinas: An Introduction'', pp. 1–2</ref> It was here that Thomas was probably introduced to [[Aristotle]], [[Averroes]] and [[Maimonides]], all of whom would influence his theological philosophy.<ref name="davies2">Davies, ''Aquinas: An Introduction'', p. 2</ref> It was also during his study at Naples that Thomas came under the influence of John of St. Julian, a Dominican preacher in Naples, who was part of the active effort by the Dominican order to recruit devout followers.<ref>Hampden, ''The Life'', pp. 21–22.</ref> Here his teacher in arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and music was [[Petrus de Ibernia]].<ref>Grabmann, Martin. Virgil Michel, trans. ''Thomas Aquinas: His Personality and Thought.'' (Kessinger Publishing, 2006), pp. 2.</ref>
At the age of five, Thomas began his early education at Monte Cassino but after the military conflict that broke out between the [[Emperor Frederick II]] and [[Pope Gregory IX]] spilled into the abbey in early 1239, Landulf and Theodora had Thomas enrolled at the ''studium generale'' (university) recently established by Frederick in [[Naples]].<ref>Davies, ''Aquinas: An Introduction'', pp. 1–2</ref> It was here that Thomas was probably introduced to [[Aristotle]], [[Averroes]] and [[Maimonides]], all of whom would influence his theological philosophy.<ref name="davies2">Davies, ''Aquinas: An Introduction'', p. 2</ref> It was also during his study at Naples that Thomas came under the influence of John of St. Julian, a Dominican preacher in Naples, who was part of the active effort by the Dominican order to recruit devout followers.<ref>Hampden, ''The Life'', pp. 21–22.</ref> Here his teacher in arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and music was [[Petrus de Ibernia]].<ref>Grabmann, Martin. Virgil Michel, trans. ''Thomas Aquinas: His Personality and Thought.'' (Kessinger Publishing, 2006), pp. 2.</ref>

Revision as of 09:45, 1 August 2011

Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas depicted in stained glass
Thomas Aquinas depicted in stained glass
BornThomas Aquinas
1225
Aquino, Kingdom of Sicily
Died7 March 1274
Fossanova, Kingdom of Sicily
OccupationPriest, Philosopher, Theologian
GenreScholasticism, Thomism
SubjectMetaphysics, Logic, Theology, Mind, Epistemology, Ethics, Politics
Notable worksSumma Theologica, Summa Contra Gentiles

Thomas Aquinas, O.P. (/[invalid input: 'icon']əˈkwnəs/ ə-KWY-nəs; Aquino, 1225 – Fossanova, 7 March 1274), also Thomas of Aquin or Aquino, was an Italian Dominican priest of the Catholic Church, and an immensely influential philosopher and theologian in the tradition of scholasticism, known as Doctor Angelicus, Doctor Communis, or Doctor Universalis.[1] "Aquinas" is not a surname (hereditary surnames were not then in common use in Europe), but is a Latin adjective meaning "of Aquino", his place of birth. He was the foremost classical proponent of natural theology, and the father of Thomism. His influence on Western thought is considerable, and much of modern philosophy was conceived as a reaction against, or as an agreement with his ideas, particularly in the areas of ethics, natural law and political theory.

Thomas is held in the Catholic Church to be the model teacher for those studying for the priesthood.[2] The works for which he is best-known are the Summa Theologica and the Summa Contra Gentiles. As one of the 33 Doctors of the Church, he is considered the Church's greatest theologian and philosopher. Pope Benedict XV declared: "This (Dominican) Order ... acquired new luster when the Church declared the teaching of Thomas to be her own and that Doctor, honored with the special praises of the Pontiffs, the master and patron of Catholic schools."[3]

Biography

Early years and desire to become a Dominican (1225–1240)

Thomas was born in Aquino c.January 28, 1235, according to some authors in his father's, the Count Landulf of Aquino, castle placed in Roccasecca, in the same Contea di Aquino (Kingdom of Sicily, in the present-day: Lazio). Through his mother, Theodora Countess of Theate, Thomas was related to the Hohenstaufen dynasty of Holy Roman emperors.[4] Landulf's brother Sinibald was abbot of the original Benedictine abbey at Monte Cassino. While the rest of the family's sons pursued a military career,[5] the family intended for Thomas to follow his uncle into the abbacy;[6] this would have been a normal career path for a younger son of southern Italian nobility.[4]

At the age of five, Thomas began his early education at Monte Cassino but after the military conflict that broke out between the Emperor Frederick II and Pope Gregory IX spilled into the abbey in early 1239, Landulf and Theodora had Thomas enrolled at the studium generale (university) recently established by Frederick in Naples.[7] It was here that Thomas was probably introduced to Aristotle, Averroes and Maimonides, all of whom would influence his theological philosophy.[8] It was also during his study at Naples that Thomas came under the influence of John of St. Julian, a Dominican preacher in Naples, who was part of the active effort by the Dominican order to recruit devout followers.[9] Here his teacher in arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and music was Petrus de Ibernia.[10]

The Castle of Monte San Giovanni Campano

At age nineteen, Thomas resolved to join the Dominican Order. Thomas's change of heart did not please his family, who had expected him to become a Benedictine monk.[11] In an attempt to prevent Theodora's interference in Thomas's choice, the Dominicans arranged for Thomas to be removed to Rome, and from Rome, sent to Paris.[12] On his way to Rome, his brothers, per Theodora's instructions, seized him as he was drinking from a spring and took him back to his parents at the castle of Monte San Giovanni Campano.[12] He was held for two years in the family homes at Monte San Giovanni and Roccasecca in an attempt to prevent him from assuming the Dominican habit and to push him into renouncing his new aspiration.[8] Political concerns prevented the Pope from ordering Thomas's release, extending the detention,[13] a detention which Thomas spent tutoring his sisters and communicating with members of the Dominican Order.[8] Family members became desperate to dissuade Thomas, who remained determined to join the Dominicans. At one point, two of his brothers hired a prostitute to seduce him, but he drove her away, wielding a burning stick. According to legend, that night two angels appeared to him as he slept and strengthened his determination to remain celibate.[14] By 1244, seeing that all of her attempts to dissuade Thomas had failed, Theodora sought to save the family's dignity, arranging for Thomas to escape at night through his window. In her mind, a secret escape from detention was less damaging than an open surrender to the Dominicans. Thomas was sent first to Naples and then to Rome to meet Johannes von Wildeshausen, the Master General of the Dominican Order.[15]

Paris, Cologne, Albert Magnus, and first Paris regency (1245–1259)

In 1245, Thomas was sent to study at the University of Paris' Faculty of Arts where he most likely met Dominican scholar Albertus Magnus,[16] then the Chair of Theology at the College of St. James in Paris.[17] When Albertus was sent by his superiors to teach at the new studium generale at Cologne in 1248,[16] Thomas followed him, declining Pope Innocent IV's offer to appoint him abbot of Monte Cassino as a Dominican.[6] Albertus then appointed the reluctant Thomas magister studentium.[4] When Thomas failed his first theological disputation, Albertus prophetically exclaimed: "We call him the dumb ox, but in his teaching he will one day produce such a bellowing that it will be heard throughout the world."[6]

Thomas taught in Cologne as an apprentice professor (baccalaureus biblicus), instructing students on the books of the Old Testament and writing Expositio super Isaiam ad litteram (Literal Commentary on Isaiah), Postilla super Ieremiam (Commentary on Jeremiah) and Postilla super Threnos (Commentary on Lamentations).[18] Then in 1252 he returned to Paris to study for the master's degree in theology. He lectured on the Bible as an apprentice professor, and upon becoming a baccalaureus Sententiarum (bachelor of the Sentences)[19] devoted his final three years of study to commenting on Peter Lombard's Sentences. In the first of his four theological syntheses, Thomas composed a massive commentary on the Sentences entitled Scriptum super libros Sententiarium (Commentary on the Sentences). Aside from his masters writings, he wrote De ente et essentia (On Being and Essence) for his fellow Dominicans in Paris.[6]

In the spring of 1256, Thomas was appointed regent master in theology at Paris and one of his first works upon assuming this office was Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et religionem (Against Those Who Assail the Worship of God and Religion), defending the mendicant orders which had come under attack by William of Saint-Amour.[20] During his tenure from 1256 to 1259, Thomas wrote numerous works, including: Questiones disputatae de veritate (Disputed Questions on Truth), a collection of twenty-nine disputed questions on aspects of faith and the human condition[21] prepared for the public university debates he presided over on Lent and Advent;[22] Quaestiones quodlibetales (Quodlibetal Questions), a collection of his responses to questions posed to him by the academic audience;[21] and both Expositio super librum Boethii De trinitate (Commentary on Boethius's De trinitate) and Expositio super librum Boethii De hebdomadibus (Commentary on Boethius's De hebdomadibus), commentaries on the works of 6th century philosopher Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius.[23] By the end of his regency, Thomas was working on one of his most famous works, Summa contra Gentiles.[24]

Saint Thomas Aquinas
St. Thomas Aquinas, by Fra Angelico, O.P.
Doctor of the Church
Bornc. 1225
Aquino, Kingdom of Sicily
Died7 March 1274
Fossanova Abbey, Kingdom of Sicily
Venerated inRoman Catholic Church
Anglican Communion
Lutheranism
Canonized1323, Avignon, France by Pope John XXII
Major shrineChurch of the Jacobins, Toulouse, France
Feast28 January (new), 7 March (old)
AttributesThe Summa Theologica, a model church, the Sun
PatronageAll Catholic educational institutions

Naples, Orvieto, Rome, and Santa Sabina (1259–1269)

Around 1259, Thomas returned to Naples where he lived until he arrived in Orvieto around September 1261. In Orvieto, he was appointed conventual lector, in charge of the education of friars unable to attend a studium generale. During his stay in Orvieto, Thomas completed his Summa contra Gentiles, and wrote the Catena Aurea (The Golden Chain).[25] He also wrote the liturgy for the newly created feast of Corpus Christi and produced works for Pope Urban IV concerning Greek Orthodox theology, e.g. Contra errores graecorum (Against the Errors of the Greeks).[24] In 1265 he was ordered by the Dominican Chapter of Agnani to establish a studium for the Order in Rome at the priory of Santa Sabina: “Fr. Thome de Aquino iniungimus in remissionem peccatorum quod teneat studium Rome, et volumus quod fratribus qui stant secum ad studendum provideatur in necessariis vestimentis a conventibus de quorum predicatione traxerunt originem. Si autem illi studentes inventi fuerint negligentes in studio, damus potestatem fr. Thome quod ad conventus suos possit eos remittere” (Acta Capitulorum Provincialium, Provinciae Romanae Ordinis Praedicatorum, 1265, n. 12).[26] He remained there from 1265 until he was called back to Paris in 1268.[27] It was in Rome that Thomas began his most famous work, Summa Theologica,[25] and wrote a variety of other works like his unfinished Compendium Theologiae and Responsio ad fr. Ioannem Vercellensem de articulis 108 sumptis ex opere Petri de Tarentasia (Reply to Brother John of Vercelli Regarding 108 Articles Drawn from the Work of Peter of Tarentaise).[23] In his position as head of the studium, conducted a series of important disputations on the power of God, which he compiled into his De potentia.[27]

The quarrelsome second Paris regency (1269–1272)

In 1268 the Dominican Order assigned Thomas to be regent master at the University of Paris for a second time, a position he held until the spring of 1272. Part of the reason for this sudden reassignment appears to have arisen from the rise of "Averroism" or "radical Aristotelianism" in the universities. In response to these perceived evils, Thomas wrote two works, one of them being De unitate intellectus, contra Averroistas (On the Unity of Intellect, against the Averroists) in which he blasts Averroism as incompatible with Christian doctrine.[28] During his second regency, he finished the second part of the Summa and wrote De virtutibus and De aeternitate mundi,[27] the latter of which dealt with controversial Averroist and Aristotelian beginninglessness of the world.[29] Disputes with some important Franciscans such as Bonaventure and John Peckham conspired to make his second regency much more difficult and troubled than the first. A year before Thomas re-assumed the regency at the 1266–67 Paris disputations, Franciscan master William of Baglione accused Thomas of encouraging Averroists, calling him the "blind leader of the blind". Thomas called these individuals the murmurantes (Grumblers).[29] In reality, Thomas was deeply disturbed by the spread of Averroism and was angered when he discovered Siger of Brabant teaching Averroistic interpretations of Aristotle to Parisian students.[30] On 10 December 1270, the bishop of Paris, Etienne Tempier, issued an edict condemning thirteen Aristotlelian and Averroistic propositions as heretical and excommunicating anyone who continued to support them.[31] Many in the ecclesiastical community, the so-called Augustinians, were fearful that this introduction of Aristotelianism and the more extreme Averroism might somehow contaminate the purity of the Christian faith. In what appears to be an attempt to counteract the growing fear of Aristotelian thought, Thomas conducted a series of disputations between 1270 and 1272: De virtutibus in communi (On Virtues in General), De virtutibus cardinalibus (On Cardinal Virtues), De spe (On Hope).[32]

Final days and "Straw" (1272–1274)

In 1272 Thomas took leave from the University of Paris when the Dominicans from his home province called upon him to establish a studium generale wherever he liked and staff it as he pleased. He chose to establish the institution in Naples, and moved there to take his post as regent master.[27] He took his time at Naples to work on the third part of the Summa while giving lectures on various religious topics. On 6 December 1273 Thomas was celebrating the Mass of St. Nicholas when, according to some, he heard Christ speak to him. Christ asked him what he desired, being pleased with his meritorious life. Thomas replied "Only you Lord. Only you."[33] After this exchange something happened, but Thomas never spoke of it or wrote it down. Because of what he saw, he abandoned his routine and refused to dictate to his socius Reginald of Piperno. When Reginald begged him to get back to work, Thomas replied: "Reginald, I cannot, because all that I have written seems like straw to me."[34] (mihi videtur ut palea).[35] What exactly triggered Thomas's change in behavior is believed to be some kind of supernatural experience of God.[36] After taking to his bed, he did recover some strength.[37]

Looking to find a way to reunite the Eastern Orthodox churches with the Catholic Church (the Eastern Orthodox had parted ways with the Catholic Church in A.D. 1054 over doctrinal disputes) Pope Gregory X convened the Second Council of Lyon to be held on 1 May 1274 and summoned Thomas to attend.[38] At the meeting, Thomas's work for Pope Urban IV concerning the Greeks, Contra errores graecorum, was to be presented.[39] On his way to the Council, riding on a donkey along the Appian Way,[38] he struck his head on the branch of a fallen tree and became seriously ill again. He was then quickly escorted to Monte Cassino to convalesce.[37] After resting for a while, he set out again, but stopped at the Cistercian Fossanova Abbey after again falling ill.[40] The monks nursed him for several days, and as he received his last rites he prayed: "I receive Thee, ransom of my soul. For love of Thee have I studied and kept vigil, toiled, preached and taught..."[41] He died on 7 March 1274[40] while giving commentary on the Song of Songs.[42]

Condemnation of 1277

In 1277, the same bishop of France, Etienne Tempier, who had issued the condemnation of 1270 issued another, more extensive condemnation. One aim of this condemnation was to clarify that God's absolute power transcended any principles of logic that Aristotle or Averroes might place on it.[43] More specifically, it contained a list of 219 propositions that the bishop had determined to violate the omnipotence of God, and included in this list were twenty Thomistic propositions. Their inclusion badly damaged Thomas's reputation for many years.[44]

In The Divine Comedy, Dante sees the glorified spirit of Thomas in the Heaven of the Sun with the other great exemplars of religious wisdom.[45] Dante asserts that Thomas died by poisoning, on the order of Charles of Anjou;[46] Villani (ix. 218) cites this belief, and the Anonimo Fiorentino describes the crime and its motive. But the historian Ludovico Antonio Muratori reproduces the account made by one of Thomas's friends, and this version of the story gives no hint of foul play.[47]

Thomas's theology had begun its rise to prestige. Two centuries later, in 1567, Pope Pius V proclaimed St. Thomas Aquinas a Doctor of the Church and ranked his feast with those of the four great Latin fathers: Ambrose, Augustine of Hippo, Jerome, and Gregory. However, in the same period the Council of Trent would still turn to Duns Scotus before Thomas as a source of arguments in defence of the Church. Even though Duns Scotus was more consulted at the Council of Trent, Thomas had the honor of having his Summa Theologica placed on the altar alongside the Bible and the Decretals.[44][48]

In his encyclical of 4 August 1879, Pope Leo XIII stated that Thomas's theology was a definitive exposition of Catholic doctrine. Thus, he directed the clergy to take the teachings of Thomas as the basis of their theological positions. Leo XIII also decreed that all Catholic seminaries and universities must teach Thomas's doctrines, and where Thomas did not speak on a topic, the teachers were "urged to teach conclusions that were reconcilable with his thinking." In 1880, Saint Thomas Aquinas was declared patron of all Catholic educational establishments.

Canonization

When the devil's advocate at his canonization process objected that there were no miracles, one of the cardinals answered, "Tot miraculis, quot articulis"—"there are as many miracles (in his life) as articles (in his Summa)," viz., thousands.[48] Fifty years after the death of Thomas, on July 18, 1323, Pope John XXII, seated in Avignon, pronounced Thomas a saint.[49]

In a monastery at Naples, near the cathedral of St. Januarius, a cell in which he supposedly lived is still shown to visitors. His remains were placed in the Church of the Jacobins in Toulouse in 1369. Between 1789 and 1974, they were held in Basilique de Saint-Sernin, Toulouse. In 1974, they were returned to the Church of the Jacobins, where they have remained ever since.

In the General Roman Calendar of 1962, in the Roman Catholic Church, Thomas was commemorated on 7 March, the day of death. However, in the General Roman Calendar of 1969, even though the norm in the Roman Catholic Church is to remember saints on the day of their death, Thomas's memorial was transferred to 28 January, the date of the translation of his relics to Toulouse.[50]

Saint Thomas Aquinas is honored with a feast day on the liturgical of the Episcopal Church in the United States of America on January 28.

Philosophy

Thomas was a theologian and a Scholastic philosopher.[51] However, he never considered himself a philosopher, and criticized philosophers, who he saw as pagans, for always "falling short of the true and proper wisdom to be found in Christian revelation".[52] With this in mind, Thomas did have respect for Aristotle, so much so that in the Summa, he often cites Aristotle simply as "the Philosopher." Much of his work bears upon philosophical topics, and in this sense may be characterized as philosophical. Thomas's philosophical thought has exerted enormous influence on subsequent Christian theology, especially that of the Roman Catholic Church, extending to Western philosophy in general. Thomas stands as a vehicle and modifier of Aristotelianism and Neoplatonism.

Commentaries on Aristotle

Thomas wrote several important commentaries on Aristotle, including On the Soul, Nicomachean Ethics and Metaphysics. His work is associated with William of Moerbeke's translations of Aristotle from Greek into Latin.

Epistemology

Thomas believed "that for the knowledge of any truth whatsoever man needs divine help, that the intellect may be moved by God to its act."[53] However, he believed that human beings have the natural capacity to know many things without special divine revelation, even though such revelation occurs from time to time, "especially in regard to such (truths) as pertain to faith."[54]

Revelation

Thomas believed that truth is known through reason (natural revelation) and faith (supernatural revelation). Supernatural revelation has its origin in the inspiration of the Holy Spirit and is made available through the teaching of the prophets, summed up in Holy Scripture, and transmitted by the Magisterium, the sum of which is called "Tradition". Natural revelation is the truth available to all people through their human nature; certain truths all men can attain from correct human reasoning. For example, he felt this applied to rational ways to know the existence of God.

Though one may deduce the existence of God and his Attributes (One, Truth, Good, Power, Knowledge) through reason, certain specifics may be known only through special revelation (such as the Trinity). In Thomas's view, special revelation is equivalent to the revelation of God in Jesus Christ. The major theological components of Christianity, such as the Trinity and the Incarnation, are revealed in the teachings of the Church and the Scriptures and may not otherwise be deduced.

Supernatural revelation (faith) and natural revelation (reason) are complementary rather than contradictory in nature, for they pertain to the same unity: truth.

Creation

As a Catholic, Thomas believed that God is the "maker of heaven and earth, of all that is visible and invisible." Like Aristotle, Thomas posited that life could form from non-living material or plant life, a theory of ongoing abiogenesis known as spontaneous generation:

Since the generation of one thing is the corruption of another, it was not incompatible with the first formation of things, that from the corruption of the less perfect the more perfect should be generated. Hence animals generated from the corruption of inanimate things, or of plants, may have been generated then.[55]

Additionally, Thomas considered Empedocles' theory that various mutated species emerged at the dawn of Creation. Thomas reasoned that these species were generated through mutations in animal sperm, and argued that they were not unintended by nature; rather, such species were simply not intended for perpetual existence. This discussion is found in his commentary on Aristotle's Physics:

The same thing is true of those substances which Empedocles said were produced at the beginning of the world, such as the ‘ox-progeny’, i.e., half ox and half man. For if such things were not able to arrive at some end and final state of nature so that they would be preserved in existence, this was not because nature did not intend this [a final state], but because they were not capable of being preserved. For they were not generated according to nature, but by the corruption of some natural principle, as it now also happens that some monstrous offspring are generated because of the corruption of seed.[56]

Ethics

Thomas's ethics are based on the concept of "first principles of action."[57] In his Summa Theologica, he wrote:

Virtue denotes a certain perfection of a power. Now a thing's perfection is considered chiefly in regard to its end. But the end of power is act. Wherefore power is said to be perfect, according as it is determinate to its act.[58]

Thomas defined the four cardinal virtues as prudence, temperance, justice, and fortitude. The cardinal virtues are natural and revealed in nature, and they are binding on everyone. There are, however, three theological virtues: faith, hope, and charity. These are supernatural and are distinct from other virtues in their object, namely, God:

Now the object of the theological virtues is God Himself, Who is the last end of all, as surpassing the knowledge of our reason. On the other hand, the object of the intellectual and moral virtues is something comprehensible to human reason. Wherefore the theological virtues are specifically distinct from the moral and intellectual virtues.[59]

Furthermore, Thomas distinguished four kinds of law: eternal, natural, human, and divine. Divine law is the decree of God that governs all creation. Natural law is the human "participation" in the eternal law and is discovered by reason.[60] Natural law, of course, is based on "first principles":

. . . this is the first precept of the law, that good is to be done and promoted, and evil is to be avoided. All other precepts of the natural law are based on this . . .[61]

The desires to live and to procreate are counted by Thomas among those basic (natural) human values on which all human values are based. However, Thomas condemned non-procreative sexual activity. This lead him to view masturbation, oral sex, and even coitus interruptus, as being worse than incest and rape when the act itself is considered (apart from the abuse suffered by the violated party). He also objected to sexual positions other than the missionary position, on the assumption that they made conception more difficult.[62][63][64]

Human law is positive law: the natural law applied by governments to societies. Divine law is the specially revealed law in the scriptures.

Thomas also greatly influenced Catholic understandings of mortal and venial sins.

Thomas denied that human beings have any duty of charity to animals because they are not persons. Otherwise, it would be unlawful to use them for food. But this does not give us license to be cruel to them, for "cruel habits might carry over into our treatment of human beings."[65]

Thomas contributed to economic thought as an aspect of ethics and justice. He dealt with the concept of a just price, normally its market price or a regulated price sufficient to cover seller costs of production. He argued it was immoral for sellers to raise their prices simply because buyers were in pressing need for a product.[66][67]

Intentionality

The pioneer of neurodynamics, cognitive neuroscientist Walter Freeman, considers the work of Thomas important in remodeling intentionality, the directedness of the mind toward what it is aware of. {{citation}}: Empty citation (help)

Psychology

Aquinas maintains that a human is a single material substance. He understands the soul as the form of the body, which makes a human being the composite of the two. Thus, only living, form-matter composites can truly be called human; dead bodies are “human” only analogously. One actually existing substance comes from body and soul. A human is a single material substance, but still should be understood as having an immaterial soul, which continues after bodily death.

Ultimately, humans are animals; the animal genus is body; body is material substance. When embodied, a human person is an “individual substance in the category rational animal.”[68] The body belongs to the essence of a human being. In his Summa Theologica, Aquinas clearly states his position on the nature of the soul; defining it as “the first principle of life.”[69] The soul is not corporeal, or a body; it is the act of a body. Because the intellect is incorporeal, it does not use the bodily organs, as “the operation of anything follows the mode of its being.”[70]

The human soul is perfected in the body, but does not depend on the body, because part of its nature is spiritual. The body-soul composite has matter and spirit. In this way, the soul differs from other forms, which are only found in matter, and thus depend on matter. Typically, matter exists only through form (by being organized by it), but the soul, as form of the body, does not depend on matter in this way. This is all thanks to the dual nature of humanity, which bridges the spiritual and material worlds.

The soul is not matter, not even incorporeal or spiritual matter. If it were, it would not be able to understand universals, which are immaterial. A receiver receives things according to the receiver’s own nature, so in order for soul (receiver) to understand (receive) universals, it must have the same nature as universals. Yet, any substance that understands universals may not be a matter-form composite. So, humans have intellectual souls which are abstract forms of the body and a human is one existing, single material substance (which comes from body and soul). This conclusion entails that the soul is the body’s form; that is, “something one in nature can be formed from an intellectual substance and a body,” and “a thing one in nature does not result from two permanent entities unless one has the character of substantial form and the other of matter.”[71]

The soul as form can be understood when one compares Aquinas’ definition of matter (that which of itself exists incompletely), with his definition of form (that which gives existence to matter). An item is matter if it is changeable and can become different than it is; matter is always potentially something else. For example, bronze matter is potentially a statue, or also potentially a cymbal. When Aquinas says the body is of matter, it means the material body is only potentially a human being (without the intellectual soul). Matter must be understood as the matter of something. The form of something is that whose presence in some matter is that matter’s being that thing. For matter to be the thing, some form of the thing must be present in it. Consequently, a human’s matter’s being live human tissue consists in a human soul’s being wholly present in each part of the human. The soul is a substantial form; it is a part of a substance, but it is not a substance itself. The soul exists separately from the body, and continues, after death, in many of the capacities we think of as human. Substantial form is what makes a thing a member of the species to which it belongs, and substantial form is also the structure or configuration that provides the object with the abilities that make the object what it is. For humans, those abilities are those of the rational animal.

Theology

17th century sculpture of Thomas Aquinas

Thomas viewed theology, or the sacred doctrine, as a science,[36] the raw material data of which consists of written scripture and the tradition of the Catholic Church. These sources of data were produced by the self-revelation of God to individuals and groups of people throughout history. Faith and reason, while distinct but related, are the two primary tools for processing the data of theology. Thomas believed both were necessary — or, rather, that the confluence of both was necessary — for one to obtain true knowledge of God. Thomas blended Greek philosophy and Christian doctrine by suggesting that rational thinking and the study of nature, like revelation, were valid ways to understand truths pertaining to God. According to Thomas, God reveals himself through nature, so to study nature is to study God. The ultimate goals of theology, in Thomas's mind, are to use reason to grasp the truth about God and to experience salvation through that truth.

Nature of God

Thomas believed that the existence of God is neither obvious nor improvable. In the Summa Theologica, he considered in great detail five reasons for the existence of God. These are widely known as the quinque viae, or the "Five Ways."

Concerning the nature of God, Thomas felt the best approach, commonly called the via negativa, is to consider what God is not. This led him to propose five statements about the divine qualities:

  1. God is simple, without composition of parts, such as body and soul, or matter and form.[72]
  2. God is perfect, lacking nothing. That is, God is distinguished from other beings on account of God's complete actuality.[73] Thomas defined God as the ‘Ipse Actus Essendi subsistens,’ subsisting act of being.[74]
  3. God is infinite. That is, God is not finite in the ways that created beings are physically, intellectually, and emotionally limited. This infinity is to be distinguished from infinity of size and infinity of number.[75]
  4. God is immutable, incapable of change on the levels of God's essence and character.[76]
  5. God is one, without diversification within God's self. The unity of God is such that God's essence is the same as God's existence. In Thomas's words, "in itself the proposition 'God exists' is necessarily true, for in it subject and predicate are the same."[77]

In this approach, he is following, among others, the Jewish philosopher Maimonides.[78]

Following St. Augustine of Hippo, Thomas defines sin as "a word, deed, or desire, contrary to the eternal law."[79] It is important to note the analogous nature of law in Thomas's legal philosophy. Natural law is an instance or instantiation of eternal law. Because natural law is that which human beings determine according to their own nature (as rational beings), disobeying reason is disobeying natural law and eternal law. Thus eternal law is logically prior to reception of either "natural law" (that determined by reason) or "divine law" (that found in the Old and New Testaments). In other words, God's will extends to both reason and revelation. Sin is abrogating either one's own reason, on the one hand, or revelation on the other, and is synonymous with "evil" (privation of good, or privatio boni[80]). Thomas, like all Scholastics, generally argued that the findings of reason and data of revelation cannot conflict, so both are a guide to God's will for human beings.

Nature of the Trinity

Thomas argued that God, while perfectly united, also is perfectly described by Three Interrelated Persons. These three persons (Father, Son, and Holy Spirit) are constituted by their relations within the essence of God. The Father generates the Son (or the Word) by the relation of self-awareness. This eternal generation then produces an eternal Spirit "who enjoys the divine nature as the Love of God, the Love of the Father for the Word."

This Trinity exists independently from the world. It transcends the created world, but the Trinity also decided to communicate God's self and God's goodness to human beings. This takes place through the Incarnation of the Word in the person of Jesus Christ and through the indwelling of the Holy Spirit (indeed, the very essence of the Trinity itself) within those who have experienced salvation by God.[81]

Prima causa – first cause

Thomas's five proofs for the existence of God take some of Aristotle's assertions concerning principles of being. For Thomas, God as prima causa (first cause) comes from Aristotle's concept of the unmoved mover and asserts that God is the ultimate cause of all things.[82]

Nature of Jesus Christ

In the Summa Theologica, Thomas begins his discussion of Jesus Christ by recounting the biblical story of Adam and Eve and by describing the negative effects of original sin. The purpose of Christ's Incarnation was to restore human nature by removing "the contamination of sin", which humans cannot do by themselves. "Divine Wisdom judged it fitting that God should become man, so that thus one and the same person would be able both to restore man and to offer satisfaction."[83] Thomas argued in favor of the satisfaction view of atonement; that is, that Jesus Christ died "to satisfy for the whole human race, which was sentenced to die on account of sin."[84]

Thomas argued against several specific contemporary and historical theologians who held differing views about Christ. In response to Photinus, Thomas stated that Jesus was truly divine and not simply a human being. Against Nestorius, who suggested that Son of God was merely conjoined to the man Christ, Thomas argued that the fullness of God was an integral part of Christ's existence. However, countering Apollinaris' views, Thomas held that Christ had a truly human (rational) soul, as well. This produced a duality of natures in Christ. Thomas argued against Eutyches that this duality persisted after the Incarnation. Thomas stated that these two natures existed simultaneously yet distinguishably in one real human body, unlike the teachings of Manichaeus and Valentinus.[85]

In short, "Christ had a real body of the same nature of ours, a true rational soul, and, together with these, perfect Deity." Thus, there is both unity (in his one hypostasis) and diversity (in his two natures, human and Divine) in Christ.[86]

Echoing Athanasius of Alexandria, he said that "The only begotten Son of God...assumed our nature, so that he, made man, might make men gods."[87]

Goal of human life

In Thomas's thought, the goal of human existence is union and eternal fellowship with God. Specifically, this goal is achieved through the beatific vision, an event in which a person experiences perfect, unending happiness by seeing the very essence of God. This vision, which occurs after death, is a gift from God given to those who have experienced salvation and redemption through Christ while living on earth.

This ultimate goal carries implications for one's present life on earth. Thomas stated that an individual's will must be ordered toward right things, such as charity, peace, and holiness. He sees this as the way to happiness. Thomas orders his treatment of the moral life around the idea of happiness. The relationship between will and goal is antecedent in nature "because rectitude of the will consists in being duly ordered to the last end [that is, the beatific vision]." Those who truly seek to understand and see God will necessarily love what God loves. Such love requires morality and bears fruit in everyday human choices.[88]

Treatment of heretics

Thomas Aquinas belonged to the Dominican Order (formally Ordo Praedicatorum, the Order of Preachers) who attempted the peaceful conversion of the Albigensian heretics. In the Summa Theologica, he wrote:

With regard to heretics two points must be observed: one, on their own side; the other, on the side of the Church. On their own side there is the sin, whereby they deserve not only to be separated from the Church by excommunication, but also to be severed from the world by death. For it is a much graver matter to corrupt the faith which quickens the soul, than to forge money, which supports temporal life. Wherefore if forgers of money and other evil-doers are forthwith condemned to death by the secular authority, much more reason is there for heretics, as soon as they are convicted of heresy, to be not only excommunicated but even put to death. On the part of the Church, however, there is mercy which looks to the conversion of the wanderer, wherefore she condemns not at once, but "after the first and second admonition," as the Apostle directs: after that, if he is yet stubborn, the Church no longer hoping for his conversion, looks to the salvation of others, by excommunicating him and separating him from the Church, and furthermore delivers him to the secular tribunal to be exterminated thereby from the world by death.(Summa, II–II, Q.11, art.3.)

Heresy was a capital offense against the secular law of most European countries of the 13th century. Thomas's suggestion specifically demands that heretics be handed to a "secular tribunal" rather than magisterial authority. That Thomas specifically says that heretics "deserve... death" is concerning his theology, where all sinners do not deserve life ("For the wages of sin is death; but the free gift of God is eternal life in Christ Jesus our Lord"[89]). He elaborates on his opinion regarding heresy in the next article, when he says:

In God's tribunal, those who return are always received, because God is a searcher of hearts, and knows those who return in sincerity. But the Church cannot imitate God in this, for she presumes that those who relapse after being once received, are not sincere in their return; hence she does not debar them from the way of salvation, but neither does she protect them from the sentence of death. (Summa, op. cit., art.4.)

The afterlife and resurrection

A grasp of Aquinas's psychology is essential for understanding his beliefs around the afterlife and resurrection. Thomas, following Church doctrine, accepts that the soul continues to exist after the death of the body. Because he accepts that the soul is the form of the body, then he also must believe that the human being, like all material things, is form-matter composite. Substantial form (the human soul) configures prime matter (the physical body) and is the form by which a material composite belongs to that species it does; in the case of human beings, that species is rational animal.[90] So, a human being is a matter-form composite that is organized to be a rational animal. Matter cannot exist without being configured by form, but form can exist without matter—which allows for the separation of soul from body. Aquinas says that the soul shares in the material and spiritual worlds, and so has some features of matter and other, immaterial, features (such as access to universals). The human soul is different from other material and spiritual things; it is created by God, but also only comes into existence in the material body.

Human beings are material, but the human person can survive the death of the body through continued existence of the soul, which persists. The human soul straddles the spiritual and material worlds, and is both a configured subsistent form as well as a configurer of matter into that of a living, bodily human.[91] Because it is spiritual, the human soul does not depend on matter and may exist separately. Because the human being is a soul-matter composite, the body has a part in what it is to be human. Perfected human nature consists in the human dual nature, embodied and intellecting.

Resurrection appears to require dualism, which Thomas rejects. Yet, Aquinas believes the soul persists after the death and corruption of the body, and is capable of existence, separated from the body between the time of death and the resurrection. Aquinas believes in a different sort of dualism, one guided by Christian scripture. Aquinas knows that human beings are essentially physical, but that that physicality has a spirit capable of returning to God after life.[92] For Aquinas, the rewards and punishment of the afterlife are not only spiritual. Because of this, resurrection is an important part of his philosophy on the soul. The human is fulfilled and complete in the body, so the hereafter must take place with souls enmattered in resurrected bodies. In addition to spiritual reward, humans can expect to enjoy material and physical blessings. Because Aquinas’s soul requires a body for its actions, during the afterlife, the soul will also be punished or rewarded in corporeal existence.

Aquinas states clearly his stance on resurrection, and uses it to back up his philosophy of justice; that is, the promise of resurrection compensates Christians who suffered in this world through a heavenly union with the divine. He says, “If there is no resurrection of the dead, it follows that there is no good for human beings other than in this life.”[93] Resurrection provides the impetus for people on earth to give up pleasures in this life. Thomas believes the human who has prepared for the afterlife both morally and intellectually will be rewarded more greatly; however, all reward is through the grace of God. Aquinas insists beatitude will be conferred according to merit, and will render the person better able to conceive the divine. Aquinas accordingly believes punishment is directly related to earthly, living preparation and activity as well. Aquinas’s account of the soul focuses on epistemology and metaphysics, and because of this he believes it gives a clear account of the immaterial nature of the soul. Aquinas conservatively guards Christian doctrine, and thus maintains physical and spiritual reward and punishment after death. By accepting the essentiality of both body and soul, he allows for a heaven and hell described in scripture and church dogma.

Modern influence

Many modern ethicists both within and outside the Catholic Church (notably Philippa Foot and Alasdair MacIntyre) have recently commented on the possible use of Thomas's virtue ethics as a way of avoiding utilitarianism or Kantian "sense of duty" (called deontology). Through the work of twentieth century philosophers such as Elizabeth Anscombe (especially in her book Intention), Thomas's principle of double effect specifically and his theory of intentional activity generally have been influential.

In recent years, the cognitive neuroscientist Walter Freeman proposes that Thomism is the philosophical system explaining cognition that is most compatible with neurodynamics, in a 2008 article in the journal Mind and Matter entitled "Nonlinear Brain Dynamics and Intention According to Aquinas."

Thomas's aesthetic theories, especially the concept of claritas, deeply influenced the literary practice of modernist writer James Joyce, who used to extol Thomas as being second only to Aristotle among Western philosophers. The influence of Thomas's aesthetics also can be found in the works of the Italian semiotician Umberto Eco, who wrote an essay on aesthetic ideas in Thomas (published in 1956 and republished in 1988 in a revised edition).

Claims of levitation

For centuries, there have been recurring claims that Thomas had the ability to levitate. For example, G. K. Chesterton wrote that, "His experiences included well-attested cases of levitation in ecstasy; and the Blessed Virgin appeared to him, comforting him with the welcome news that he would never be a Bishop."[94]

See also

Sources

Footnotes

  1. ^ See Pius XI, Studiorum Ducem 11 (29 June 1923), AAS, XV ("non modo Angelicum, sed etiam Communem seu Universalem Ecclesiae Doctorem"). The title Doctor Communis dates to the fourteenth century; the title Doctor Angelicus dates to the fifteenth century, see Walz, Xenia Thomistica, III, p. 164 n. 4. Tolomeo of Lucca writes in Historia Ecclesiastica (1317): “This man is supreme among modern teachers of philosophy and theology, and indeed in every subject. And such is the common view and opinion, so that nowadays in the University of Paris they call him the Doctor Communis because of the outstanding clarity of his teaching.” Historia Eccles. xxiii, c. 9.
  2. ^ Code of Canon Law, Can. 252, §3 [1]
  3. ^ Benedict XV Encyclical Fausto appetente die June 29, 1921, AAS 13 (1921), 332; Pius XI Encyclical Studiorum Ducem §11, June 29, 1923, AAS 15 (1923), cf. AAS 17 (1925) 574; Paul VI, March 7, 1964 AAS 56 (1964), 302 (Bouscaren, vol. VI, pp. 786–88).
  4. ^ a b c Schaff, p. p. 422.
  5. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 14.
  6. ^ a b c d Stump, Aquinas, p. 3.
  7. ^ Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, pp. 1–2
  8. ^ a b c Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, p. 2
  9. ^ Hampden, The Life, pp. 21–22.
  10. ^ Grabmann, Martin. Virgil Michel, trans. Thomas Aquinas: His Personality and Thought. (Kessinger Publishing, 2006), pp. 2.
  11. ^ Collison, Diane, and Kathryn Plant. Fifty Major Philosophers. 2nd ed. New York: Routledge, 2006.
  12. ^ a b Hampden, The Life, p. 23.
  13. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 24.
  14. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 25.
  15. ^ Hampden, The Life, pp. 27–28.
  16. ^ a b Healy, Theologian, p. 2.
  17. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 33.
  18. ^ Stump, Aquinas, p. xvi.
  19. ^ Davies, The Thought, p. 5.
  20. ^ Aquinas, Thomas (2003). On Evil. Oxford University Press US. p. 5. ISBN 0-1950-9183-3. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  21. ^ a b Stump, Aquinas, p. 4.
  22. ^ Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, pp. 3–4.
  23. ^ a b Stump, Aquinas, p. xvii.
  24. ^ a b Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, p. 4.
  25. ^ a b Healy, Theologian, p. 4.
  26. ^ http://www.corpusthomisticum.org/a65.html
  27. ^ a b c d Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, p. 5.
  28. ^ Stump, Aquinas, pp. 10–11.
  29. ^ a b Stump, Aquinas, p. 11.
  30. ^ Aquinas, Reader, pp. 9–11.
  31. ^ McInerney, Against the Averroists, p. 10.
  32. ^ Aquinas, Reader, p. 11.
  33. ^ Catholic Encyclopedia
  34. ^ Davies, The Thought, p. 9.
  35. ^ McBride, William Leon (1997). The Development and Meaning of Twentieth-century Existentialism. Taylor and Francis. p. 131. ISBN 0-8153-2491-X.
  36. ^ a b McInerny, Ralph and John O'Callaghan, "Saint Thomas Aquinas", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
  37. ^ a b Healy, Theologian, p. 7.
  38. ^ a b Nichols, Discovering Aquinas, p. 18.
  39. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 46.
  40. ^ a b Healy, Theologian, p. 8.
  41. ^ Aquinas, Reader, p. 12.
  42. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 47.
  43. ^ Grant, Edward (1996). The Foundations of Modern Science in the Middle Ages: Their Religious, Institutional, and Intellectual Contexts. Cambridge University Press. pp. 81–82. ISBN 0-5215-6762-9.
  44. ^ a b Kung, Christian Thinkers [2], pp. 112–114.
  45. ^ "Parad. x. 99". Divinecomedy.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  46. ^ "Purg. xx. 69". Divinecomedy.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  47. ^ "Aquinas, Thomas", Encyclopædia Britannica (1911), pg. 250.
  48. ^ a b Brian Mullady, O.P. (2006). "The Angelic Doctor – Thomas Aquinas". Retrieved 2011-06-11. {{cite web}}: External link in |author= (help)
  49. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 54.
  50. ^ Liturgy of the Hours Volume III, Proper of Saints, 28 January.
  51. ^ Some would not describe Thomas as a philosopher. See, e.g., Mark D. Jordan, "Philosophy in a Summa of Theology", in Rewritten Theology: Aquinas after his Readers (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006) pp. 154–170. [3]
  52. ^ Davies, Brian (2004). Aquinas. Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 14.
  53. ^ "Blog Archive " Saint Thomas Aquinas". Saints.SQPN.com. 1974-10-22. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  54. ^ "Summa, Q109a1". Ccel.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  55. ^ Saint Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, On the Work of the Sixth Day, Reply to Objection 5, Fathers of the English Dominican Province
  56. ^ Saint Thomas Aquinas, Physica, Book 2, Lecture 14, Fathers of the English Dominican Province
  57. ^ Geisler, p. 727.
  58. ^ "Summa, Q55a1". Ccel.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  59. ^ "Summa, Q62a2". Ccel.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  60. ^ Pojman, Louis (1995). Ethics: Discovering Right and Wrong. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company. ISBN 0-5345-6138-1.
  61. ^ "Summa, Q94a2". Ccel.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  62. ^ Alan Soble, Sex from Plato to Paglia
  63. ^ Vern L. Bullough, Bonnie Bullough, Human Sexuality: An Encyclopedia
  64. ^ Daphne Hampson, After Christianity
  65. ^ Honderich, Ted, ed. (1995). "Animals: Peter Singer". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford. pp. 35–36. {{cite book}}: External link in |contribution= (help)CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  66. ^ Summa Theologica, Questions 77 and 78
  67. ^ Barry Gordon (1987). "Aquinas, St Thomas (1225–1274)," v. 1, p. 100
  68. ^ Stump, Eleanore (2006). "Resurrection, Reassembly, and Reconstitution: Aquinas on the Soul". Die menschliche Seele: Brauchen wir den Dualismus? The Human Soul: Do We Need Dualism?. Frankfurt-London: Ontos Verlag. {{cite book}}: |access-date= requires |url= (help); Unknown parameter |editors= ignored (|editor= suggested) (help)
  69. ^ Aquinas, Thomas (1920). "Question 75, Article 1". Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas Aquinas. Vol. Second and Revised Edition. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |editors= ignored (|editor= suggested) (help)
  70. ^ Aquinas, Thomas (1920). "Question 75, Article 3". Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas Aquinas. Vol. Second and Revised Edition. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |editors= ignored (|editor= suggested) (help)
  71. ^ Aquinas, Thomas (1975). "5 volumes.". Summa Contra Gentiles. Notre Dame, Ind.: U. of Notre Dame Press. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |editors= ignored (|editor= suggested) (help)
  72. ^ Kreeft, pp. 74–77.
  73. ^ Kreeft, pp. 86–87.
  74. ^ See Actus Essendi.
  75. ^ Kreeft, pp. 97–99.
  76. ^ Kreeft, p. 105.
  77. ^ Kreeft, pp. 111–112.
  78. ^ Jewish Encyclopedia, Aquinas, Thomas
  79. ^ "Summa, II–I, Q.71, art.6". Newadvent.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  80. ^ Summa, II–I, Q.75, art.1. "For evil is the absence of the good, which is natural and due to a thing."
  81. ^ Nichols, Aidan (2002). Discovering Aquinas. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans Publishing Company. pp. 173–174.
  82. ^ Nichols, Aidan (2002). Discovering Aquinas. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans Publishing Company. pp. 80–82.
  83. ^ Aquinas, pp. 228–229.
  84. ^ "Summa, III, Q.50, art.1". Newadvent.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  85. ^ Aquinas, pp. 231–239.
  86. ^ Aquinas, pp. 241, 245–249. Emphasis is the author's.
  87. ^ Weigel, George (2001). The Truth of Catholicism. New York City: Harper Collins. p. 9. ISBN 0-06-621330-4. {{cite book}}: Cite has empty unknown parameter: |coauthors= (help)
  88. ^ Kreeft, p. 383.
  89. ^ "Romans 6:23, ASV". Biblegateway.com. Retrieved 2010-01-17.
  90. ^ Stump, Eleanore (2003). Aquinas, (in the series The Arguments of the Philosophers). London and New York: Routledge. p. 194.
  91. ^ Stump, Eleanore (2003). Aquinas, (in the series The Arguments of the Philosophers). London and New York: Routledge. p. 200.
  92. ^ Stump, Eleanore (2003). Aquinas, (in the series The Arguments of the Philosophers). London and New York: Routledge. p. 192.
  93. ^ Stump, Eleanore (2003). Aquinas, (in the series The Arguments of the Philosophers). London and New York: Routledge. pp. 461, 473.
  94. ^ G. K. Chesterton wrote an Essay on St. Thomas Aquinas which appeared in The Spectator Feb. 27, 1932.

References

Further reading

  • Copleston, Frederick (1991). Aquinas: An Introduction to the Life and Work of the Great Medieval Thinker. Penguin Books. ISBN 0-1401-3674-6.
  • Faitanin, Paulo (2008). A Sabedoria do Amor: iniciação à filosofia de Santo Tomás de Aquino. Instituto Aquinate. ISSN 1982-8845.
  • Faitanin, Paulo (2008). O Ofício do Sábio: o modo de estudar e ensinar segundo Santo Tomás de Aquino. Instituto Aquinate. ISSN 1982-8845.
  • Paterson, Craig & Matthew S. Pugh (eds.), Analytical Thomism: Traditions in Dialogue. Ashgate, 2006. Introduction to Thomism
  • Wallace, William A. (1970). "Thomas Aquinas, Saint" (PDF). In Gillispie, Charles (ed.). Dictionary of Scientific Biography. Vol. 1. New York: Scribner & American Council of Learned Societies. pp. 196–200. ISBN 9780684101149.
  • Weisheipl, James (1974). Friar Thomas D'Aquino: his life, thought, and work ([1st ed.] ed.). Garden City N.Y.: Doubleday. ISBN 9780385012997.

Biographies

On his thought

By Thomas

Template:Persondata

Template:Link GA Template:Link GA Template:Link GA Template:Link FA Template:Link FA Template:Link FA