Cut-elimination theorem: Difference between revisions
No edit summary |
|||
Line 46: | Line 46: | ||
Cut elimination is one of the most powerful tools for proving [[Craig interpolation|interpolation theorem]]s. The possibility of carrying out proof search based on [[First-order resolution|resolution]], the essential insight leading to the [[Prolog]] programming language, depends upon the admissibility of Cut in the appropriate system. |
Cut elimination is one of the most powerful tools for proving [[Craig interpolation|interpolation theorem]]s. The possibility of carrying out proof search based on [[First-order resolution|resolution]], the essential insight leading to the [[Prolog]] programming language, depends upon the admissibility of Cut in the appropriate system. |
||
For proof systems based on [[higher-order typed lambda calculus]] through a [[Curry–Howard isomorphism]], cut elimination algorithms correspond to the strong normalization property (every proof term reduces in a finite number of steps into a [[normal form (term rewriting)|normal form]]). |
For proof systems based on [[higher-order typed lambda calculus]] through a [[Curry–Howard isomorphism]], cut elimination algorithms correspond to the [[normalization property (abstract rewriting)|strong normalization property]] (every proof term reduces in a finite number of steps into a [[normal form (term rewriting)|normal form]]). |
||
== See also == |
== See also == |
Revision as of 19:58, 15 December 2018
The cut-elimination theorem (or Gentzen's Hauptsatz) is the central result establishing the significance of the sequent calculus. It was originally proved by Gerhard Gentzen in his landmark 1934 paper "Investigations in Logical Deduction" for the systems LJ and LK formalising intuitionistic and classical logic respectively. The cut-elimination theorem states that any judgement that possesses a proof in the sequent calculus making use of the cut rule also possesses a cut-free proof, that is, a proof that does not make use of the cut rule.[1][2]
The cut rule
A sequent is a logical expression relating multiple formulas, in the form "", which is to be read as " proves ", and (as glossed by Gentzen) should be understood as equivalent to the truth-function "If ( and and …) then ( or or …)."[3] Note that the left-hand side (LHS) is a conjunction (and) and the RHS is a disjunction (or).
The LHS may have arbitrarily many or few formulae; when the LHS is empty, the RHS is a tautology. In LK, the RHS may also have any number of formulae—if it has none, the LHS is a contradiction, whereas in LJ the RHS may only have one formula or none: here we see that allowing more than one formula in the RHS is equivalent, in the presence of the right contraction rule, to the admissibility of the law of the excluded middle. However, the sequent calculus is a fairly expressive framework, and there have been sequent calculi for intuitionistic logic proposed that allow many formulae in the RHS. From Jean-Yves Girard's logic LC it is easy to obtain a rather natural formalisation of classical logic where the RHS contains at most one formula; it is the interplay of the logical and structural rules that is the key here.
"Cut" is a rule in the normal statement of the sequent calculus, and equivalent to a variety of rules in other proof theories, which, given
and
allows one to infer
That is, it "cuts" the occurrences of the formula out of the inferential relation.
Cut elimination
The cut-elimination theorem states that (for a given system) any sequent provable using the rule Cut can be proved without use of this rule.
For sequent calculi that have only one formula in the RHS, the "Cut" rule reads, given
and
allows one to infer
If we think of as a theorem, then cut-elimination in this case simply says that a lemma used to prove this theorem can be inlined. Whenever the theorem's proof mentions lemma , we can substitute the occurrences for the proof of . Consequently, the cut rule is admissible.
Consequences of the theorem
For systems formulated in the sequent calculus, analytic proofs are those proofs that do not use Cut. Typically such a proof will be longer, of course, and not necessarily trivially so. In his essay "Don't Eliminate Cut!" George Boolos demonstrated that there was a derivation that could be completed in a page using cut, but whose analytic proof could not be completed in the lifespan of the universe.
The theorem has many, rich consequences:
- A system is inconsistent if it admits a proof of the absurd. If the system has a cut elimination theorem, then if it has a proof of the absurd, or of the empty sequent, it should also have a proof of the absurd (or the empty sequent), without cuts. It is typically very easy to check that there are no such proofs. Thus, once a system is shown to have a cut elimination theorem, it is normally immediate that the system is consistent.
- Normally also the system has, at least in first order logic, the subformula property, an important property in several approaches to proof-theoretic semantics.
Cut elimination is one of the most powerful tools for proving interpolation theorems. The possibility of carrying out proof search based on resolution, the essential insight leading to the Prolog programming language, depends upon the admissibility of Cut in the appropriate system.
For proof systems based on higher-order typed lambda calculus through a Curry–Howard isomorphism, cut elimination algorithms correspond to the strong normalization property (every proof term reduces in a finite number of steps into a normal form).
See also
Notes
- ^ Curry 1977, pp. 208–213, gives a 5-page proof of the elimination theorem. See also pages 188, 250.
- ^ Kleene 2009, pp. 453, gives a very brief proof of the cut-elimination theorem.
- ^ Wilfried Buchholz, Beweistheorie (university lecture notes about cut-elimination, German, 2002-2003)
References
- Gentzen, Gerhard (1934–1935). "Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen". Mathematische Zeitschrift. 39: 405–431. doi:10.1007/BF01201363.
- Gentzen, Gerhard (1964). "Investigations into logical deduction". American Philosophical Quarterly. 1 (4): 249–287.
- Gentzen, Gerhard (1965). "Investigations into logical deduction". American Philosophical Quarterly. 2 (3): 204–218.
- Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen I
- Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen II
- Curry, Haskell Brooks (1977) [1963]. Foundations of mathematical logic. New York: Dover Publications Inc. ISBN 978-0-486-63462-3.
{{cite book}}
: Invalid|ref=harv
(help) - Kleene, Stephen Cole (2009) [1952]. Introduction to metamathematics. Ishi Press International. ISBN 978-0-923891-57-2.
{{cite book}}
: Invalid|ref=harv
(help)
External links
- Alex Sakharov. "Cut Elimination Theorem". MathWorld.
- Dragalin, A.G. (2001) [1994], "Sequent calculus", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press