Jump to content

Truth condition: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Fleshed out meaning v. truth condition example
m Made notation consistent
Line 3: Line 3:
More formally, we can think of a truth condition as what makes for the truth of a sentence in an [[inductive definition]] of truth. (For details, see the [[semantic theory of truth]].) Understood this way, truth conditions are [[theoretical entities]]. To illustrate with an example: suppose that, in a particular truth theory, the word "Nixon" [[Reference|refers]] to [[Richard M. Nixon]], and "is alive" is associated with the [[set]] of currently living things. Then one way of representing the truth condition of "Nixon is alive" is as the [[ordered pair]] <Nixon, {x: x is alive}>. And we say that "Nixon is alive" is true if and only if the referent of "Nixon" belongs to the set associated with "is alive", that is, if and only if Nixon is alive.
More formally, we can think of a truth condition as what makes for the truth of a sentence in an [[inductive definition]] of truth. (For details, see the [[semantic theory of truth]].) Understood this way, truth conditions are [[theoretical entities]]. To illustrate with an example: suppose that, in a particular truth theory, the word "Nixon" [[Reference|refers]] to [[Richard M. Nixon]], and "is alive" is associated with the [[set]] of currently living things. Then one way of representing the truth condition of "Nixon is alive" is as the [[ordered pair]] <Nixon, {x: x is alive}>. And we say that "Nixon is alive" is true if and only if the referent of "Nixon" belongs to the set associated with "is alive", that is, if and only if Nixon is alive.


In [[semantics]], the truth condition of a sentence is almost universally considered to be distinct from its [[Meaning(linguistics)|meaning]]. One popular argument for this view is that some sentences are necessarily true--that is, they are true whatever happens to obtain. All such sentences have the same truth conditions, but arguably do not thereby have the same meaning. Likewise, the sets {x|x is alive} and {x|x is alive and x is not a rock} are identical--they have precisely the same members--but presumably the sentences "Nixon is alive" and "Nixon is alive and is not a rock" have different meanings.
In [[semantics]], the truth condition of a sentence is almost universally considered to be distinct from its [[Meaning(linguistics)|meaning]]. One popular argument for this view is that some sentences are necessarily true--that is, they are true whatever happens to obtain. All such sentences have the same truth conditions, but arguably do not thereby have the same meaning. Likewise, the sets {x: x is alive} and {x: x is alive and x is not a rock} are identical--they have precisely the same members--but presumably the sentences "Nixon is alive" and "Nixon is alive and is not a rock" have different meanings.


[[Category:Logic]]
[[Category:Logic]]

Revision as of 22:20, 1 March 2005

In semantics, truth conditions are what obtain precisely when a sentence is true. For example, "It is snowing in Nebraska" is true precisely when it is snowing in Nebraska.

More formally, we can think of a truth condition as what makes for the truth of a sentence in an inductive definition of truth. (For details, see the semantic theory of truth.) Understood this way, truth conditions are theoretical entities. To illustrate with an example: suppose that, in a particular truth theory, the word "Nixon" refers to Richard M. Nixon, and "is alive" is associated with the set of currently living things. Then one way of representing the truth condition of "Nixon is alive" is as the ordered pair <Nixon, {x: x is alive}>. And we say that "Nixon is alive" is true if and only if the referent of "Nixon" belongs to the set associated with "is alive", that is, if and only if Nixon is alive.

In semantics, the truth condition of a sentence is almost universally considered to be distinct from its meaning. One popular argument for this view is that some sentences are necessarily true--that is, they are true whatever happens to obtain. All such sentences have the same truth conditions, but arguably do not thereby have the same meaning. Likewise, the sets {x: x is alive} and {x: x is alive and x is not a rock} are identical--they have precisely the same members--but presumably the sentences "Nixon is alive" and "Nixon is alive and is not a rock" have different meanings.