Theory of Colours: Difference between revisions
Removed not-really-related link |
mNo edit summary |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
'''''Theory of |
'''''Theory of Colours''''' (original [[German language|German]] title, '''''Zur Farbenlehre''''') is a book by [[Johann Wolfgang von Goethe]] in [[1810]]. It contains some of the earliest and most accurate descriptions of [[coloured shadow]]s, [[refraction]], [[dioptrical colour]]s, and [[achromatism]]/[[hyperchromatism]]. A number of philosophers and physicists, including [[Arthur Schopenhauer]], [[Kurt Gödel]], [[Werner Heisenberg]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], and [[Hermann von Helmholtz]] were fascinated by Goethe's theory. [[Mitchell Feigenbaum]] was convinced that 'Goethe had been right about colour!'. Its influence extended to the art world, most notably to [[J. M. W. Turner]]. Turner studied it comprehensively and made reference to it in the titles of several paintings (''Bockemuhl'', 1991). |
||
Goethe considered his own theory to be a more general explanation of colour, with [[Isaac Newton]]'s observations being special cases[http://www.physicstoday.org/vol-55/iss-7/p43.html#fig4]. Goethe's work was not well accepted by the physics community of his day and is not typically discussed in modern accounts of the history of science. Physicists have come to understand, however, the distinction between the [[optical spectrum]], as observed by Newton, and the phenomenon of human perception of colour. Developments in understanding how the brain interprets colours, for example [[color constancy|colour constancy]] and [[Edwin Land]]'s [[retinex]] theory, bear-striking similarities to Goethe's theory of colours—particularly his focus on brightness and contrast as the determining factors of colour perception. |
Goethe considered his own theory to be a more general explanation of colour, with [[Isaac Newton]]'s observations being special cases[http://www.physicstoday.org/vol-55/iss-7/p43.html#fig4]. Goethe's work was not well accepted by the physics community of his day and is not typically discussed in modern accounts of the history of science. Physicists have come to understand, however, the distinction between the [[optical spectrum]], as observed by Newton, and the phenomenon of human perception of colour. Developments in understanding how the brain interprets colours, for example [[color constancy|colour constancy]] and [[Edwin Land]]'s [[retinex]] theory, bear-striking similarities to Goethe's theory of colours—particularly his focus on brightness and contrast as the determining factors of colour perception. |
Revision as of 23:36, 20 April 2007
Theory of Colours (original German title, Zur Farbenlehre) is a book by Johann Wolfgang von Goethe in 1810. It contains some of the earliest and most accurate descriptions of coloured shadows, refraction, dioptrical colours, and achromatism/hyperchromatism. A number of philosophers and physicists, including Arthur Schopenhauer, Kurt Gödel, Werner Heisenberg, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Hermann von Helmholtz were fascinated by Goethe's theory. Mitchell Feigenbaum was convinced that 'Goethe had been right about colour!'. Its influence extended to the art world, most notably to J. M. W. Turner. Turner studied it comprehensively and made reference to it in the titles of several paintings (Bockemuhl, 1991).
Goethe considered his own theory to be a more general explanation of colour, with Isaac Newton's observations being special cases[1]. Goethe's work was not well accepted by the physics community of his day and is not typically discussed in modern accounts of the history of science. Physicists have come to understand, however, the distinction between the optical spectrum, as observed by Newton, and the phenomenon of human perception of colour. Developments in understanding how the brain interprets colours, for example colour constancy and Edwin Land's retinex theory, bear-striking similarities to Goethe's theory of colours—particularly his focus on brightness and contrast as the determining factors of colour perception.
- When the eye sees a colour it is immediately excited, and it is its nature, spontaneously and of necessity, at once to produce another, which with the original colour comprehends the whole chromatic scale. A single colour excites, by a specific sensation, the tendency to universality. In this resides the fundamental law of all harmony of colours...
- —Goethe, Theory of Colours, p. 317
Theory of Colours not only parted radically with the dominant Newtonian light and optical theories of his time, but also with the entire Enlightenment methodology of reductive science. Although the theory was not received well by scientists, Goethe – considered one of the most important intellectual figures in modern Europe – thought of his colour theory as his greatest accomplishment. Holistic theorists and scientists such as Rupert Sheldrake still refer to Goethe's Theory of Colours as an inspiring example of holistic science. The introduction to the book lays out Goethe's unique philosophy of science.
Goethe's theory
Background
In the 1780s, Goethe was asked to return a prism which had been on loan from the Privy Councillor Buettner in Jena. As he was returning it, he paused to take a look through — and what he saw led him to a comprehensive study of light phenomenon, culminating in The Theory of Colours.
- Along with the rest of the world I was convinced that all the colours
- are contained in the light; no one had ever told me anything different,
- and I had never found the least cause to doubt it, because I had
- no further interest in the subject. (Goethe)
At the time, it was already known that the prismatic phenomenon is a process of splitting up the colourless (white) light into colours. Newton's theory stated that colourless light already contains the seven colours within itself — and when we channel this light through a prism, the prism does no more than to fan out and separate what is already there in the light — the seven colours, into which it is thus analyzed.
Goethe's reasoning
Goethe reasoned: In such way the phenomena are interpreted, but this is not the primal or complete phenomenon. A look through the prism shows that we do not see white areas split evenly into seven colours. Rather, we see colours at some edge or border-line.
If we let a cylinder of colourless light impinge on the screen, it shows a colourless picture. Putting a prism in the way of the cylinder of light, we get the sequence of colours: red, orange, yellow, green, cyan, blue, violet.
If we let light pass through the space of the room, we get a white circle on a screen. Put a prism in the way, and the cylinder of light is diverted (Figure I), but what appears is not the series of seven colours at all, only a reddish colour fanning out from the upper edge, passing over into yellow, and on the lower edge a blue passing over into greenish shades. In the middle it stays white.
Goethe now said to himself: It is not that the light is split up or that anything is separated out of the light as such. In point of fact, I am projecting a picture—simply an image of this circular aperture. The aperture has edges, and where the colours occur the reason is not that they are drawn out of the light, as though the light had been split up into them. It is because this picture which I am projecting—the picture as such—has edges. Here too the fact is that where light adjoins dark, colours appear at the edges. It is none other than that. For there is darkness outside this circular patch of light, while it is relatively light within it.
The colours therefore, to begin with, make their appearance purely and simply as phenomena at the border between light and dark. This is the original, the primary phenomenon. We are no longer seeing the original phenomenon when by reducing the circle in size we get a continuous sequence of colours. The latter phenomenon only arises when we take so small a circle that the colours extend inward from the edges to the middle. They then overlap in the middle and form what we call a continuous spectrum, while with the larger circle the colours formed at the edges stay as they are. This is the primal phenomenon. Colours arise at the borders, where light and dark flow together. The prism serves only to shift light and dark over each other.
Light and dark spectra
The spectrum, therefore, is a compound phenomenon. In the familiar prismatic experiment, you get colour at the edges, and where the red-yellow and blue-violet edges meet, you get green.
Because the colour phenomenon relies on the adjacency of light and dark, there are therefore two ways to produce a spectrum: with a light beam surrounded by dark, and with a dark beam surrounded by light, as illustrated below.
Darkness and light
From the Newtonian standpoint, darkness is an absence of light. According to this view, the light which streams into a dark space has no resistance from the darkness to overcome.
Goethe pictures to himself that light and darkness relate to each other like the north and south poles of a magnet. The darkness can weaken the light in its working power. Conversely, the light can limit the energy of the darkness. In both cases colour arises.
He writes:
- Yellow is a light which has been dampened by darkness;
- Blue is a darkness weakened by the light.
Newton vs. Goethe and beyond
The physicist defines darkness as an absence of light. This definition of darkness was held by such seventeenth century physicists as Newton, with his particle theory of light, and Huygens, with his wave theory. All visible colours are contained within white light, and are split according to their wavelengths. Thus said Goethe's contemporaries Young and Fresnel who revived Huygens' wave theory and rejected Newton's particle theory. Young and Fresnel regarded colour as the visible manifestation of light's wavelength. (Twenty first century physicists attribute corpuscular as well as undulatory character to light, which is the content of the so-called wave-particle duality.)
Today, Goethe's Theory of Colours is still remarkably accurate in its phenomenological observations. In his book Goethe takes isssue with Newton's concept of light and argues that light and dark related as the north and south poles of a magnet, and colour arises from their interplay. This reification of darkness has caused almost all of modern physics to reject Goethe's theory as unscientific. Yet Goethe was consistently empirical in his approach.
- "As Feigenbaum understood them, Goethe's ideas had true science in them. They were hard and empirical. Over and over again, Goethe emphasized the repeatability of his experiments. It was the perception of colour, to Goethe, that was universal and objective. What scientific evidence was there for a definable real-world quality of redness independent of our perception?" (James Gleick, 'Chaos', William Heinemann, London, 1988, pp. 165-7)
Goethe's experiments on light also accurately depict the complexities of human colour perception. Goethe's emphasis on brightness and boundaries correlates with modern research on the perception of colour [2]; while Goethe's idea of colour constancy correlates with Edwin Land's Retinex theory.
Where Newton's studies were aimed more towards the development of a mathematical explanation for the behaviour of light, Goethe was focused on exploring how colour is perceived in a complex array of conditions.
Quotations
- Can you lend me the Theory of Colours for a few weeks?
- It is an important work. His last things are insipid.
- —Ludwig van Beethoven, Conversation-book, 1820
- Should your glance on mornings lovely
- Lift to drink the heaven's blue
- Or when sun, vieled by sirocco,
- Royal red sinks out of view -
- Give to Nature praise and honor.
- Blithe of heart and sound of eye,
- Knowing for the world of colour
- Where its broad foundations lie.
- —Goethe
- [Goethe] delivered in full measure what was promised by the title of his excellent work: data toward a theory of colour. They are important, complete, and significant data, rich material for a future theory of colour. He has not, however, undertaken to furnish the theory itself; hence, as he himself remarks and admits on page xxxix of the introduction, he has not furnished us with a real explanation of the essential nature of colour, but really postulates it as a phenomenon, and merely tells us how it originates, not what it is.
- — Schopenhauer, On Vision and Colours
- Goethe's theory of the origin of the spectrum isn't a theory of its origin that has proved unsatisfactory; it is really not a theory at all. Nothing can be predicted by means of it. It is, rather, a vague schematic outline, of the sort we find in James's psychology. There is no experimentum crucis for Goethe's theory of colour.
- — Wittgenstein, Remarks on Colour
References
Bockemuhl, M. 1991. Turner. Koln: Taschen. ISBN 3-8228-6325-4.
Bibliography
- Goethe, Theory of Colours, trans. Charles Lock Eastlake (Cambridge, Massachusetts: The M.I.T. Press, 1982)
- Schopenhauer, On Vision and Colors, Prividence: Berg, 1994 ISBN 0-85496-988-8
See also
External links
- Physics Today - Exploratory Experimentation: Goethe, Land, and Colour Theory
- Goethe's Prismatic Experiments; Fotos by Sakae Tajima
- Connections That Have a Quality of Necessity: Goethe's Way Of Science As a Phenomenology of Nature
- Colour Mixing and Goethe's Triangle (Java Applet)
- A list of links relating to Goethe's investigation of colour
- Essay discussing color psychology and Goethe's theory
- Google Scholar: Works citing "Theory of Colours"