Jump to content

Talk:Conjunction fallacy: Difference between revisions

Page contents not supported in other languages.
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Line 19: Line 19:
I think the example given doesn't really demonstrate a fallacy so much as the way wording can confuse an issue. Clearly, from a probability standpoint, "Linda is a bank teller" must be more probable than "Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement". However, when presented with the two choices, people may assume that the first option, "Linda is a bank teller", is meant to be "Linda is ''just'' a bank teller" (i.e., Linda is a bank teller but is not involved with the feminist movement). In other words, the real fallacy may not be one of conjunction but one of reading too much into the way it's worded. - [[User:Furrykef|furrykef]] ([[User_talk:Furrykef|Talk at me]]) 01:40, 4 February 2006 (UTC)
I think the example given doesn't really demonstrate a fallacy so much as the way wording can confuse an issue. Clearly, from a probability standpoint, "Linda is a bank teller" must be more probable than "Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement". However, when presented with the two choices, people may assume that the first option, "Linda is a bank teller", is meant to be "Linda is ''just'' a bank teller" (i.e., Linda is a bank teller but is not involved with the feminist movement). In other words, the real fallacy may not be one of conjunction but one of reading too much into the way it's worded. - [[User:Furrykef|furrykef]] ([[User_talk:Furrykef|Talk at me]]) 01:40, 4 February 2006 (UTC)
: I read about this objection before, and I've seen that studies have been made to show that even eliminating the possibility of that error didn't prevent people from committing the fallacy. When I find the specific info I'll add it to the article, if it's appropriate. [[User:Rbarreira|Rbarreira]] 12:20, 1 August 2006 (UTC)
: I read about this objection before, and I've seen that studies have been made to show that even eliminating the possibility of that error didn't prevent people from committing the fallacy. When I find the specific info I'll add it to the article, if it's appropriate. [[User:Rbarreira|Rbarreira]] 12:20, 1 August 2006 (UTC)
: The example given in the article Re. the polish invasion already demonstrates that there is no ambiguity, in my opinion. [[User:Jimhsu77479|Jimhsu77479]] ([[User talk:Jimhsu77479|talk]]) 20:28, 25 January 2009 (UTC)
: The example given in the article Re. the soviet invasion of poland already demonstrates that there is no ambiguity, in my opinion. [[User:Jimhsu77479|Jimhsu77479]] ([[User talk:Jimhsu77479|talk]]) 20:28, 25 January 2009 (UTC)
In other words, 85% of people believe both in the "researchers don't ask stupid questions" fallacy (and so assume that option 1 implies that Linda doesn't actively participate in the feminist movement) and that Linda is more likely to be both a bank teller and a feminist than a bank teller and not a feminist.
In other words, 85% of people believe both in the "researchers don't ask stupid questions" fallacy (and so assume that option 1 implies that Linda doesn't actively participate in the feminist movement) and that Linda is more likely to be both a bank teller and a feminist than a bank teller and not a feminist.



Revision as of 20:28, 25 January 2009

WikiProject iconPhilosophy: Logic Unassessed Mid‑importance
WikiProject iconThis article is within the scope of WikiProject Philosophy, a collaborative effort to improve the coverage of content related to philosophy on Wikipedia. If you would like to support the project, please visit the project page, where you can get more details on how you can help, and where you can join the general discussion about philosophy content on Wikipedia.
???This article has not yet received a rating on Wikipedia's content assessment scale.
MidThis article has been rated as Mid-importance on the project's importance scale.
Associated task forces:
Taskforce icon
Logic

Currently, this is confused:

(a) I assume it should read 85% choose 2, or there is no point here (b) the later wording 'people get this problem' is ambiguous - could mean people do see the point.

Charles Matthews 18:01, 17 Jun 2004 (UTC)

Yes, yes I fixed these after re-reading. --Taak 18:28, 17 Jun 2004 (UTC)

Remove Assumption of Independence

I didn't post it properly merely because I don't know if this is the right place for it. If you all want it, there it is. "Pr(B|A)" is read "The probability of B given A". Mo Anabre 17:43, 2 May 2007 (UTC)[reply]

Where most people go wrong

I think the example given doesn't really demonstrate a fallacy so much as the way wording can confuse an issue. Clearly, from a probability standpoint, "Linda is a bank teller" must be more probable than "Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement". However, when presented with the two choices, people may assume that the first option, "Linda is a bank teller", is meant to be "Linda is just a bank teller" (i.e., Linda is a bank teller but is not involved with the feminist movement). In other words, the real fallacy may not be one of conjunction but one of reading too much into the way it's worded. - furrykef (Talk at me) 01:40, 4 February 2006 (UTC)[reply]

I read about this objection before, and I've seen that studies have been made to show that even eliminating the possibility of that error didn't prevent people from committing the fallacy. When I find the specific info I'll add it to the article, if it's appropriate. Rbarreira 12:20, 1 August 2006 (UTC)[reply]
The example given in the article Re. the soviet invasion of poland already demonstrates that there is no ambiguity, in my opinion. Jimhsu77479 (talk) 20:28, 25 January 2009 (UTC)[reply]

In other words, 85% of people believe both in the "researchers don't ask stupid questions" fallacy (and so assume that option 1 implies that Linda doesn't actively participate in the feminist movement) and that Linda is more likely to be both a bank teller and a feminist than a bank teller and not a feminist.

No Paradox here

There is no reason to call this a paradox, as the material requirements for a paradox do not occur. While it is true that people would not expect that each representative (but less than certain) conjunction would reduce the probability; the fact that the probability itself is diminished is not paradoxical, as demonstrated easily in the example given on this page. In the mathematical proof of the example, it is explicitly demonstrated that no such paradox occurs.

Just because something violates the expectations of the reader does not make it a paradox, but rather sets it up closer to irony, than a paradox. --Puellanivis 04:42, 30 July 2006 (UTC)[reply]

'...this inequality...'

Is it just me, or does the inequality 'Pr(A) > Pr(A^B) < Pr(B)' look un-mathematical, due to the conflicting directions of the inequalities? When you write 'A<B<C', this is valid because A<B, B<C, and A<C all hold simultaneously; but in a form like 'A>B<C', what implication does that make for A and C? I think the statement should be changed to read that the probability of the conjunction is less than or equal to the MINIMUM of the set {P(A), P(B)}.

Pr(Linda is just a bank teller and not involved in feminism|Linda was a philosophy major)

It seems as if this fallacy is wrong, and I wonder if this criticism has come up: people are assuming that they are asking what the probability is that Linda is just a bank teller given that she majored in philosophy and is concerned about issues. Also, that "and" or "or" misunderstanding is likely as well. I'd like to see some studies cited, because clearly there's a lot of room for criticism here. It's likely that if you looked at female philosophy majors, the probability that these women are involved in feminism is higher than the probability that they are not. OptimistBen | talk - contribs 19:24, 25 April 2008 (UTC)[reply]