Jump to content

Inalienable right: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
JW1805 (talk | contribs)
Criticism: This is finally starting to look like an encyclopedia entry. One assertion still needs to be cited. All citations need to be verified. Thanks for your work.
Line 13: Line 13:
== Criticism ==
== Criticism ==
{{cleanup-sect}}
{{cleanup-sect}}
The concept of inalienable rights has been criticized by [[Jeremy Bentham]] and [[Edmund Burke]] as groundless, since rights arise from the actions of government, or evolve from tradition, and neither of these can provide ''inalienable'' anything. ([http://www.ditext.com/bentham/bentham.html Jeremy Bentham ''Critique of the Doctrine of Inalienable, Natural Rights'']) <!--for Burke, ''Reflections on the Revolution in France'', ''passim''-->. The Declaration of Independence claims that all men are endowed with these rights by their "[[Creator God|Creator]]". If they are indeed based on [[theology|theological]] principles (as in "God-given rights"), one may ask which theological principles those are (since none of the major [[religion]]s of the world assert the existence of inalienable rights), or why those theological principles should be accepted by people who do not adhere to the religion from which they are derived.<!-- Citation needed -->
The concept of inalienable rights has been criticized by [[Jeremy Bentham]] and [[Edmund Burke]] as groundless. Bentham and Burke claim that rights arise from the actions of government, or evolve from tradition, and neither of these can provide ''inalienable'' anything. (See also Bentham's "[[Critique of the Doctrine of Inalienable, Natural Rights]]"[http://www.ditext.com/bentham/bentham.html], Burke's "[[Reflections on the Revolution in France]]").


The Declaration of Independence says that all men are "endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights." {{fact}} asserts that use of the word "Creator" signifies these rights are based on [[theology|theological]] principles, and asks which theological principles those are (since none of the major [[religion]]s of the world assert the existence of inalienable rights), or why those theological principles should be accepted by people who do not adhere to the religion from which they are derived.
If, on the other hand, inalienable rights are said to be based on [[Natural Law]], then this argument has been criticized as a ''[[Non sequitur (logic)|non sequitur]]'', deriving an "ought" statement from an "is". (the [[naturalistic fallacy]] of [[David Hume]] and [[G. E. Moore]]) <!--Principia Ethica-->. One version of this describes the phrase "We hold these truths to be self-evident" as simply a 'more elegant version of "Because we said so"'.<!--Jonathan Wallace, "Natural Rights Don't Exist"-->


[[David Hume]] and [[G. E. Moore]] criticize inalienable rights that are said to be based on [[Natural Law]] as a ''[[Non sequitur (logic)|non sequitur]]'', deriving an "ought" statement from an "is". (see also the [[naturalistic fallacy]] of [[David Hume]] and [[G. E. Moore]]) <!--Principia Ethica-->. [[Jonathan Wallace]] states in his book "Natural Rights Don't Exist," that the phrase "We hold these truths to be self-evident" is simply a "more elegant version of 'Because we said so.'"
The existence of inalienable rights is unnecessary for the existence of a [[constitution]] or a set of laws and rights. The idea of a [[social contract]] &ndash; that rights and responsibilities are derived from a consensual contract between the government and the people &ndash; is the most widely recognized alternative.<!--Jean-Jacques Rousseau, "The Social Contract"-->

[[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]] states in "[[The Social Contract]]" that the existence of inalienable rights is unnecessary for the existence of a [[constitution]] or a set of laws and rights. The idea of a [[social contract]] &ndash; that rights and responsibilities are derived from a consensual contract between the government and the people &ndash; is the most widely recognized alternative.


[[Samuel P. Huntington]], an American [[political scientist]], wrote that the "inalienable rights" argument from the Declaration of Independence was necessary because "The British were white, English, and Protestant, just as we were. They had to have some other basis on which to justify independence".
[[Samuel P. Huntington]], an American [[political scientist]], wrote that the "inalienable rights" argument from the Declaration of Independence was necessary because "The British were white, English, and Protestant, just as we were. They had to have some other basis on which to justify independence".

Revision as of 06:53, 24 January 2006

The term inalienable rights (or unalienable rights) refers to a set of human rights that are absolute, not awarded by human power, not transferable to another power, and incapable of repudiation. Several different sets of inalienable rights have been suggested by philosophers and politicians.

Origins

It has been argued that the idea of inalienable rights is derived from the freeborn rights claimed by the Englishman John Lilburne in his conflict with both the monarchy of King Charles I and the military dictatorship of the republic governed by Oliver Cromwell. Lilburne (known as Freeborn John) defined freeborn rights as being rights that every human being is born with, as opposed to rights bestowed by government or by human law.

The concept of inalienable rights is central to the ideology of liberalism. Inalienable rights played important roles in the justifications for both the French and American Revolutions. 17th-century philosopher John Locke discussed the idea of inalienable rights in his work, and identified them as being "life, liberty, and estate (or property)". The 1776 United States Declaration of Independence, written by Thomas Jefferson, famously asserts:

"We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness. That to secure these rights, Governments are instituted among Men."

Chief Justice Salmon P. Chase wrote in the case of John Van Zandt, who had been charged with violating the Fugitive Slave Act, that:

"The law of the Creator, which invests every human being with an inalienable title to freedom, cannot be repealed by any interior law which asserts that man is property."

Criticism

Template:Cleanup-sect The concept of inalienable rights has been criticized by Jeremy Bentham and Edmund Burke as groundless. Bentham and Burke claim that rights arise from the actions of government, or evolve from tradition, and neither of these can provide inalienable anything. (See also Bentham's "Critique of the Doctrine of Inalienable, Natural Rights"[1], Burke's "Reflections on the Revolution in France").

The Declaration of Independence says that all men are "endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights." [citation needed] asserts that use of the word "Creator" signifies these rights are based on theological principles, and asks which theological principles those are (since none of the major religions of the world assert the existence of inalienable rights), or why those theological principles should be accepted by people who do not adhere to the religion from which they are derived.

David Hume and G. E. Moore criticize inalienable rights that are said to be based on Natural Law as a non sequitur, deriving an "ought" statement from an "is". (see also the naturalistic fallacy of David Hume and G. E. Moore) . Jonathan Wallace states in his book "Natural Rights Don't Exist," that the phrase "We hold these truths to be self-evident" is simply a "more elegant version of 'Because we said so.'"

Jean-Jacques Rousseau states in "The Social Contract" that the existence of inalienable rights is unnecessary for the existence of a constitution or a set of laws and rights. The idea of a social contract – that rights and responsibilities are derived from a consensual contract between the government and the people – is the most widely recognized alternative.

Samuel P. Huntington, an American political scientist, wrote that the "inalienable rights" argument from the Declaration of Independence was necessary because "The British were white, English, and Protestant, just as we were. They had to have some other basis on which to justify independence".

See also

References

  • Locke, John. Two Treatises on Government. 1690 (primarily the second treatise)
  • Lloyd Thomas, D.A. Locke on Government. 1995, Routledge. ISBN 0-415-09533-6
  • Waldron, Jeremy [ed.] Theories of Rights 1984, Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-875063-3