Jump to content

Finitary: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m typo
m descramble again
Line 1: Line 1:
In [[mathematics]] or [[logic]], a '''finitary operation''' is one, like those of [[arithmetic]], that takes a finite number of input values to produce an output. An operation such as taking an [[integral]] of a [[function (mathematics)|function]], in [[calculus]], is defined in such a way as to depend on all the values of the function (infinitely many of them, in general), and so is not ''[[prima facie]]'' finitary. In the logic proposed for [[quantum mechanics]], depending on the use of subspaces of [[Hilbert space]] as [[Propositional calculus|proposition]]s, operations such as taking the [[intersection (set theory)|intersection]] of subspaces are used; this in general cannot be considered a finitary operation. What fails to be finitary can be called '''''infinitary'''''.
In [[mathematics]] or [[logic]], a '''finitary operation''' is one, like those of [[arithmetic]], that takes a finite number of input values to produce an output. An operation such as taking an [[integral]] of a [[function (mathematics)|function]], in [[calculus]], is defined in such a way as to depend on all the values of the function (infinitely many of them, in general), and so is ''[[prima facie]]'' not finitary. In the logic proposed for [[quantum mechanics]], depending on the use of subspaces of [[Hilbert space]] as [[Propositional calculus|proposition]]s, operations such as taking the [[intersection (set theory)|intersection]] of subspaces are used; this in general cannot be considered a finitary operation. What fails to be finitary can be called '''''infinitary'''''.


A '''finitary argument''' is one which can be translated into a [[finite set]] of symbolic propositions starting from a finite<ref>The number of axioms ''referenced'' in the argument will necessarily be finite since the proof is finite, but the number of axioms from which these are ''chosen'' is infinite when the system has [[axiom scheme]]s, as for example the axiom schemes of [[propositional calculus]].</ref> set of [[axiom]]s. In other words, it is a [[Mathematical proof|proof]] that can be written on a large enough sheet of paper (including all assumptions).
A '''finitary argument''' is one which can be translated into a [[finite set]] of symbolic propositions starting from a finite<ref>The number of axioms ''referenced'' in the argument will necessarily be finite since the proof is finite, but the number of axioms from which these are ''chosen'' is infinite when the system has [[axiom scheme]]s, as for example the axiom schemes of [[propositional calculus]].</ref> set of [[axiom]]s. In other words, it is a [[Mathematical proof|proof]] that can be written on a large enough sheet of paper (including all assumptions).

Revision as of 22:34, 2 December 2011

In mathematics or logic, a finitary operation is one, like those of arithmetic, that takes a finite number of input values to produce an output. An operation such as taking an integral of a function, in calculus, is defined in such a way as to depend on all the values of the function (infinitely many of them, in general), and so is prima facie not finitary. In the logic proposed for quantum mechanics, depending on the use of subspaces of Hilbert space as propositions, operations such as taking the intersection of subspaces are used; this in general cannot be considered a finitary operation. What fails to be finitary can be called infinitary.

A finitary argument is one which can be translated into a finite set of symbolic propositions starting from a finite[1] set of axioms. In other words, it is a proof that can be written on a large enough sheet of paper (including all assumptions).

The emphasis on finitary methods has historical roots. Infinitary logic studies logics that allow infinitely long statements and proofs. In such a logic, one can regard the existential quantifier, for instance, as derived from an infinitary disjunction.

In the early 20th century, logicians aimed to solve the problem of foundations; that is, answer the question: "What is the true base of mathematics?" The program was to be able to rewrite all mathematics starting using an entirely syntactical language without semantics. In the words of David Hilbert (referring to geometry), "it does not matter if we call the things chairs, tables and beer mugs or points, lines and planes."

The stress on finiteness came from the idea that human mathematical thought is based on a finite number of principles and all the reasonings follow essentially one rule: the modus ponens. The project was to fix a finite number of symbols (essentially the numerals 1,2,3,... the letters of alphabet and some special symbols like "+", "->", "(", ")", etc.), give a finite number of propositions expressed in those symbols, which were to be taken as "foundations" (the axioms), and some rules of inference which would model the way humans make conclusions. From these, regardless of the semantic interpretation of the symbols the remaining theorems should follow formally using only the stated rules (which make mathematics look like a game with symbols more than a science) without the need to rely on ingenuity. The hope was to prove that from these axioms and rules all the theorems of mathematics could be deduced.

The aim itself was proved impossible by Kurt Gödel in 1931, with his Incompleteness Theorem, but the general mathematical trend is to use a finitary approach, arguing that this avoids considering mathematical objects that cannot be fully defined.

Notes

  1. ^ The number of axioms referenced in the argument will necessarily be finite since the proof is finite, but the number of axioms from which these are chosen is infinite when the system has axiom schemes, as for example the axiom schemes of propositional calculus.