Jump to content

Subjective theory of value: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
See also: Removed unrelated topics
External links: Removed bad external links
Line 35: Line 35:
*[[Power theory of value]]
*[[Power theory of value]]


==External links==
* [http://www.conciseguidetoeconomics.com/book/LTV/ ''28. Labor Theory of Value''. from ''The Concise Guide To Economics''] by Jim Cox, contrasting the Labor Theory with the Subjective Theory
* [http://www.mises.org/epofe/c5sec0.asp ''Remarks on the Fundamental Problem of the Subjective Theory of Value''] by [[Ludwig Von Mises]]
* [http://www.mises.org/story/2308 Artwork and the Subjective Theory of Value], an article by Kim Yumi.


{{DEFAULTSORT:Subjective Theory Of Value}}
{{DEFAULTSORT:Subjective Theory Of Value}}

Revision as of 16:55, 20 February 2013

The subjective theory of value, also known as the theory of subjective value, is an economic theory of value that identifies worth as being based on the wants and needs of the members of a society, as opposed to value being inherent to an object. It holds that to possess value an object must be useful, with the extent of that value dependent upon the ability of an object to satisfy the wants of any given individual.[citation needed]

"Value", in this context, is separate from exchange value or price, except insofar as the latter is intended to help identify the former; the value of any good or service simply being whatever someone would trade for it in the present. This creates problems as consumers tend to bid up prices if they are funding demand with credit. This tends to separate subjective values from stable values.

The theory recognizes that one thing may be more useful in satisfying the wants of one person than another, or of no use to one person and of use to another.[1] The theory contrasts with intrinsic theories of value that hold that there is an objectively correct value of an object that can be determined irrespective of individual value judgements, such as by analyzing the amount of labor incurred in producing the object (see labor theory of value).

Overview

The theory holds that things become valuable in the economic sense (have exchange value or price) under two conditions: 1) They are useful in satisfying human wants, and are therefore desired. 2) There are not enough of them, or just enough of them, to satisfy demand. Any goods that are in unlimited supply would have no value. In other words, those useful items that are of insufficient quantity to satisfy demand have a price, and those that exist in numbers superfluous to demand (or that satisfy no wants) are free. The subjective theory of value was built upon to develop marginalist economics.

The subjective theory contrasts with intrinsic theories of value, such as the labor theory of value[citation needed] which holds that the economic value of a thing is contingent upon how much labor was - necessarily - exerted in producing it - under the condition, however, that this "thing" has a use value. For example David Ricardo said, "The value of a commodity, or the quantity of any other commodity for which it will exchange, depends on the relative quantity of labour which is necessary for its production, and not as the greater or less compensation which is paid for that labour."

In the context of a free market, several major conclusions follow from the theory. The theory contrasts with normative versions of the labor theory of value that say the exchange value of a good should be proportional to how much socially necessary labor went into producing it. The subjective theory of value is a denial of intrinsic value. It leads to the conclusion that there is no proper price of a good or service other than the rate at which it trades in a free market. Whereas the labor theory of value has been used to condemn profit as exploitation, the subjective theory of value rebuts that condemnation: a buyer in a free market who offers to pay a price lower than that which is commensurate with the amount of labor used to produce the good merely communicates information to the seller about the value the good might create for the buyer. (The price offered is not a measure of subjective value; it is just a means of communication between the buyer and the seller.) The offer is in one sense an expression of the buyer's opinion, which the seller is free to reject.

The subjective theory of value supports the inference that all voluntary trade is mutually beneficial. An individual purchases a thing because he values it more than he values what he offers in trade; otherwise he wouldn't make the trade, but would keep the thing he values more highly. Likewise, the seller agrees to trade only if he values the good less than the price he receives. In a free market, both parties therefore enter the exchange in the belief that they will receive more value than they transfer to the other party.

In turn, this leads to a third important conclusion: the mere act of voluntary trade increases total wealth in society, where wealth is understood to refer to an individual's subjective valuation of all of his possessions. In contrast to intrinsic-value theories, which tend to support the conclusion either that wealth creation is impossible (zero-sum), or that wealth creation is possible only by the application of labor, the subjective-value theory holds that one can create value simply by transferring ownership of a thing to someone who values it more highly, without necessarily modifying that thing.

Criticisms

Economist Paul Mattick argued that the subjective theory of value leads to circular reasoning. Prices are supposed to measure the "marginal utility" of the commodity. However, prices are required by the consumer in order to make the evaluations on how best to maximise their satisfaction. Hence subjective value "obviously rested on circular reasoning. Although it tried to explain prices, prices were necessary to explain marginal utility".[2]

Trade unionist Allan Engler noted that prices exist before subjective evaluations can take place, so "prices are determined by marginal utility; marginal utility is measured by prices. Prices... are nothing more or less than prices. Marginalists, having begun their search in the field of subjectivity, proceeded to walk in a circle".[3]

Notes

  1. ^ Menger, Carl. Principles of Economics (p.132)
  2. ^ Mattick, Paul (1977). Economics, Politics and The Age of Inflation.
  3. ^ Engler, Allan (1995). Apostles of Greed: Capitalism and the Myth of the Individual in the Market. Pluto Press. p. 27. ISBN 9780745309491.

See also