Scientific realism: Difference between revisions
m cit. sat. via Garrett; mce |
|||
Line 42: | Line 42: | ||
*The theory-ladenness of observation—see [[Norwood Russell Hanson|Hanson]] (1958) [[Thomas Samuel Kuhn|Kuhn]] (1970) and Quine (1960). |
*The theory-ladenness of observation—see [[Norwood Russell Hanson|Hanson]] (1958) [[Thomas Samuel Kuhn|Kuhn]] (1970) and Quine (1960). |
||
*Difficulties moving from the observationality of terms to observationality of sentences—see [[Hilary Putnam|Putnam]] (1962). |
*Difficulties moving from the observationality of terms to observationality of sentences—see [[Hilary Putnam|Putnam]] (1962). |
||
*The vagueness of the observational-theoretical distinction—see |
*The vagueness of the observational-theoretical distinction—see G. Maxwell (1962). |
||
These difficulties for logical positivism suggest, but do not entail, scientific realism, and led to the development of realism as a philosophy of science. |
These difficulties for logical positivism suggest, but do not entail, scientific realism, and led to the development of realism as a philosophy of science. |
||
Realism became the dominant philosophy of science after positivism. |
Realism became the dominant philosophy of science after positivism.<ref>Garrett, B., ''Empirical Nursing: The Art of Evidence-Based Care'' ([[Bingley]]: [[Emerald Group Publishing|Emerald Publishing]], 2018), [https://books.google.com/books?id=3ExyDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA70 p. 70].</ref>{{rp|70}} [[Bas van Fraassen]] in his book ''[[The Scientific Image]]'' (1980) developed [[constructive empiricism]] as an alternative to realism. Responses to van Fraassen have sharpened realist positions and lead to some revisions of scientific realism. |
||
==Arguments for and against scientific realism== |
==Arguments for and against scientific realism== |
||
Line 99: | Line 99: | ||
* Leplin, Jarrett. (1997). ''A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press. |
* Leplin, Jarrett. (1997). ''A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press. |
||
* Lipton, Peter. (2004). Inference to the best explanation, 2nd edition. London: Routledge. |
* Lipton, Peter. (2004). Inference to the best explanation, 2nd edition. London: Routledge. |
||
* |
* Maxwell, G. (1962). "The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities" in [[Herbert Feigl|H. Feigl]] and G. Maxwell ''Scientific Explanation, Space, and Time'' vol. 3, ''Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 3-15. |
||
* Okasha, Samir. (2002). Philosophy of science: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. See especially chapter 4, "Realism and Anti-Realism." |
* Okasha, Samir. (2002). Philosophy of science: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. See especially chapter 4, "Realism and Anti-Realism." |
||
* Putnam, Hilary. (1962). "What Theories are Not" in Ernst Nagel ''et al.'' (1962). ''Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science'' Stanford University Press. |
* Putnam, Hilary. (1962). "What Theories are Not" in Ernst Nagel ''et al.'' (1962). ''Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science'' Stanford University Press. |
Revision as of 11:38, 21 February 2020
This article includes a list of general references, but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations. (May 2017) |
Scientific realism is the view that the universe described by science is real regardless of how it may be interpreted.
Within philosophy of science, this view is often an answer to the question "how is the success of science to be explained?" The discussion on the success of science in this context centers primarily on the status of unobservable entities apparently talked about by scientific theories. Generally, those who are scientific realists assert that one can make valid claims about unobservables (viz., that they have the same ontological status) as observables, as opposed to instrumentalism.
Main features
Scientific realism involves the two basic positions. First, it is a set of claims about the features of an ideal scientific theory; an ideal theory is the sort of theory science aims to produce. Second, it is the commitment that science will eventually produce theories very much like an ideal theory and that science has done pretty well thus far in some domains. It is important to note that one might be a scientific realist regarding some sciences while not being a realist regarding others.[citation needed]
According to scientific realism, an ideal scientific theory has the following features:
- The claims the theory makes are either true or false, depending on whether the entities talked about by the theory exist and are correctly described by the theory. This is the semantic commitment of scientific realism.
- The entities described by the scientific theory exist objectively and mind-independently. This is the metaphysical commitment of scientific realism.
- There are reasons to believe some significant portion of what the theory says. This is the epistemological commitment.
Combining the first and the second claim entails that an ideal scientific theory says definite things about genuinely existing entities. The third claim says that we have reasons to believe that many scientific claims about these entities are true, but not all.
Scientific realism usually holds that science makes progress, i.e. scientific theories usually get successively better, or, rather, answer more and more questions. For this reason, many people[who?], scientific realists or otherwise, hold that realism should make sense of the progress of science in terms of theories being successively more like the ideal theory that scientific realists describe[who said this?].
Characteristic claims
The following claims are typical of those held by scientific realists. Due to the wide disagreements over the nature of science's success and the role of realism in its success, a scientific realist would agree with some but not all of the following positions.[1]
- The best scientific theories are at least partially true.
- The best theories do not employ central terms that are non referring expressions.
- To say that a theory is approximately true is sufficient explanation of the degree of its predictive success.
- The approximate truth of a theory is the only explanation of its predictive success.
- Even if a theory employs expressions that do not have a reference, a scientific theory may be approximately true.
- Scientific theories are in a historical process of progress towards a true account of the physical world.
- Scientific theories make genuine, existential claims.
- Theoretical claims of scientific theories should be read literally and are definitively either true or false.
- The degree of the predictive success of a theory is evidence of the referential success of its central terms.
- The goal of science is an account of the physical world that is literally true. Science has been successful because this is the goal that it has been making progress towards.
History
Scientific realism is related to much older philosophical positions including rationalism and metaphysical realism. However, it is a thesis about science developed in the twentieth century. Portraying scientific realism in terms of its ancient, medieval, and early modern cousins is at best misleading.
Scientific realism is developed largely as a reaction to logical positivism. Logical positivism was the first philosophy of science in the twentieth century and the forerunner of scientific realism, holding that a sharp distinction can be drawn between observational terms and theoretical terms, the latter capable of semantic analysis in observational and logical terms.
Logical positivism encountered difficulties with:
- The verificationist theory of meaning—see Hempel (1950).
- Troubles with the analytic-synthetic distinction—see Quine (1950).
- The theory-ladenness of observation—see Hanson (1958) Kuhn (1970) and Quine (1960).
- Difficulties moving from the observationality of terms to observationality of sentences—see Putnam (1962).
- The vagueness of the observational-theoretical distinction—see G. Maxwell (1962).
These difficulties for logical positivism suggest, but do not entail, scientific realism, and led to the development of realism as a philosophy of science.
Realism became the dominant philosophy of science after positivism.[2]: 70 Bas van Fraassen in his book The Scientific Image (1980) developed constructive empiricism as an alternative to realism. Responses to van Fraassen have sharpened realist positions and lead to some revisions of scientific realism.
Arguments for and against scientific realism
No miracles argument
One of the main arguments for scientific realism centers on the notion that scientific knowledge is progressive in nature, and that it is able to predict phenomena successfully.[3] Many scientific realists (e.g., Ernan McMullin, Richard Boyd) think the operational success of a theory lends credence to the idea that its more unobservable aspects exist, because they were how the theory reasoned its predictions. For example, a scientific realist would argue that science must derive some ontological support for atoms from the outstanding phenomenological success of all the theories using them.
Arguments for scientific realism often appeal to abductive reasoning or "inference to the best explanation" (Lipton, 2004). For instance, one argument commonly used—the "miracle argument" or "no miracles argument"—starts out by observing that scientific theories are highly successful in predicting and explaining a variety of phenomena, often with great accuracy. Thus, it is argued that the best explanation—the only explanation that renders the success of science to not be what Hilary Putnam calls "a miracle"—is the view that our scientific theories (or at least the best ones) provide true descriptions of the world, or approximately so.[4]
Bas van Fraassen replies with an evolutionary analogy: "I claim that the success of current scientific theories is no miracle. It is not even surprising to the scientific (Darwinist) mind. For any scientific theory is born into a life of fierce competition, a jungle red in tooth and claw. Only the successful theories survive—the ones which in fact latched on to actual regularities in nature." (The Scientific Image, 1980)
Some have argued that the no miracles argument commits the base rate fallacy.[5]
Pessimistic induction
Pessimistic induction, one of the main arguments against realism, argues that the history of science contains many theories once regarded as empirically successful but which are now believed to be false. Additionally, the history of science contains many empirically successful theories whose unobservable terms are not believed to genuinely refer. For example, the effluvium theory of static electricity (a theory of the 16th Century physicist William Gilbert) is an empirically successful theory whose central unobservable terms have been replaced by later theories.
Realists reply that replacement of particular realist theories with better ones is to be expected due to the progressive nature of scientific knowledge, and when such replacements occur only superfluous unobservables are dropped. For example, Albert Einstein's theory of special relativity showed that the concept of the luminiferous ether could be dropped because it had contributed nothing to the success of the theories of mechanics and electromagnetism. On the other hand, when theory replacement occurs, a well-supported concept, such as the concept of atoms, is not dropped but is incorporated into the new theory in some form. These replies can lead scientific realists to structural realism.
Constructivist epistemology
Social constructivists might argue that scientific realism is unable to account for the rapid change that occurs in scientific knowledge during periods of revolution. Constructivists may also argue that the success of theories is only a part of the construction. However, these arguments ignore the fact that many scientists are not realists. In fact, during what is perhaps the most notable example of revolution in science—the development of quantum mechanics in the 1920s—the dominant philosophy of science was logical positivism. The alternative realist Bohm interpretation and many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics do not make such a revolutionary break with the concepts of classical physics.
Underdetermination problem
Another argument against scientific realism, deriving from the underdetermination problem, is not so historically motivated as these others. It claims that observational data can in principle be explained by multiple theories that are mutually incompatible. Realists might counter by saying that there have been few actual cases of underdetermination in the history of science. Usually the requirement of explaining the data is so exacting that scientists are lucky to find even one theory that fulfills it. Furthermore, if we take the underdetermination argument seriously, it implies that we can know about only what we have directly observed. For example, we could not theorize that dinosaurs once lived based on the fossil evidence because other theories (e.g., that the fossils are clever hoaxes) can account for the same data.
See also
- Anti-realism
- Constructivist epistemology
- Critical realism
- Dialectical materialism
- Instrumentalism
- Musgrave's scientific realism
- Naïve realism
- Pessimistic induction
- Scientific materialism
- Social constructionism
Footnotes
- ^ Jarrett Leplin (1984), Scientific Realism, University of California Press, p. 1, ISBN 0-520-05155-6
- ^ Garrett, B., Empirical Nursing: The Art of Evidence-Based Care (Bingley: Emerald Publishing, 2018), p. 70.
- ^ Cappelen, H., Gendler, T. S., & Hawthorne, J., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), pp. 401–402.
- ^ Chakravartty, Anjan (10 July 2018). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Collin Howson, Hume's Problem: Induction and the Justification of Belief (2000), Chap. 3 : Realism and the No Miracles Argument
Further reading
- Boyd, R. N. (1988). "How to Be A Moral Realist", in G. Sayre-McCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism, Cornell University Press, pp. 181–228.
- Bunge, Mario. (2006). Chasing Reality: Strife over Realism. Toronto Studies in Philosophy: University of Toronto Press
- Bunge, Mario. (2001). Scientific Realism: Selected Essays of Mario Bunge. Mahner, M. (Ed.) New York: Prometheus Books
- Devitt, Michael, "Scientific realism". In: Oxford handbook of contemporary analytic philosophy (2005)
- Hempel, Carl. (1950). "Empiricist Criteria of Cognitive Significance" in Boyd, Richard et al. eds. (1990). The Philosophy of Science Cambridge: MIT Press..
- Hunt, Shelby D. (2003). "Controversy in Marketing Theory: For Reason, Realism, Truth, and Objectivity." Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, Inc.
- Hunt Shelby D. (2011). "Theory Status, Inductive Realism, And Approximate Truth: No Miracles, No Charades." International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 25(2), 159-178.
- Kukla, A. (2000). Social constructivism and the philosophy of science. London: Routledge.
- Kuhn, Thomas. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd Edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Laudan, Larry. (1981). "A Confutation of Convergent Realism" Philosophy of Science
- Leplin, Jarrett. (1984). Scientific Realism. California: University of California Press.
- Leplin, Jarrett. (1997). A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Lipton, Peter. (2004). Inference to the best explanation, 2nd edition. London: Routledge.
- Maxwell, G. (1962). "The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities" in H. Feigl and G. Maxwell Scientific Explanation, Space, and Time vol. 3, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 3-15.
- Okasha, Samir. (2002). Philosophy of science: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. See especially chapter 4, "Realism and Anti-Realism."
- Putnam, Hilary. (1962). "What Theories are Not" in Ernst Nagel et al. (1962). Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science Stanford University Press.
- Psillos, Stathis. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.
- Quine, W.V.O. (1951). "Two Dogmas of Empiricism" in his (1953)[1]. From a Logical Point of View Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Quine, W.V.O. (1960). Word and Object Cambridge: MIT Press.
- Sankey, H. (2001). "Scientific Realism: An Elaboration and a Defense" retrieved from http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu