Dysthanasia (animal)
Definition
Animal Dysthanasia (from the Greek ???θανασία meaning “difficult death”: ???, dys (bad; difficult) + θάνατος, thanatos (death)) refers to the practice of prolonging the life of animals that are seriously or even terminally ill and that are potentially experiencing suffering. Animal dysthanasia is a recent concept, emerging from changes in the social perception of animals and from advances in veterinary care.
Context
Animal dysthanasia is particularly relevant in the context of small animal practice. In eastern societies, domestic animals used to be mainly farm animals. With the industrialization process, humans become increasingly concentrated in urban areas, having preferential contact with companion animals, namely cats and dogs. While farm animals are widely seen as property, companion animals are perceived as family members with whom humans keep close bonds and develop strong emotional relationships. At the same time, scientific advances in veterinary medicine enable practitioners to reach accurate diagnosis faster and reliably than before, allowing life-threatening illness to be identified in the early stages of their development. Additionally, more advanced treatments are now available and used to prolong animal lives as much as possible regardless of its quality (Rollin, 2006).
Causes
Decision upon animal euthanasia often takes into account the relief of pain and suffering. Animal dysthanasia occurs because there is no agreement upon the acceptable and recognizable endpoints of the lives of companion animals. This is due to several reasons. The keeper (guardian; owner) may wish to extend the animal’s life because he rejects euthanasia as an acceptable solution. On the other hand, the veterinarian may have a scientific interest on studying the progress of a specific illness or even a financial interest in keeping the patient alive (Rollin, 2005). The keeper and the veterinarian may also want to make use of all possible treatment resources before making the decision of euthanasia. Genuine belief on the animal’s recovery and emotional attachment can also interfere on the decision-making process of euthanasia. Situations like these can be specially problematic in some veterinary specialities like small animal oncology.
Ethical considerations
In dysthanasia there is an intractable conflict between the value of the animal’s life and the termination of the suffering involved. In order to keep the animal alive we are necessarily impairing its welfare. Since it is no longer possible to provide some quality of life to the individual, the only way to prevent the animal from suffering is by putting an end to its life. When the keeper refuses euthanasia to be performed in his animal, three justifications can underlie it: 1) euthanasia can be seen as a violation to the animal’s integrity (Bovenkerk 2002); 2) the keeper might not believe in the severity of the clinical prognosis and 3) although he understands the situation as irreversible, he refuses to detach himself from a loved one. From the veterinary viewpoint he can accept dysthanasia if he believes to have a prima facie moral obligation to defend the lives of animals. But the relief of animal suffering and welfare considerations are also part of the ethical analysis. We can also take into consideration the veterinarian’s responsibilities towards the interests of the owner and those of the animal: a veterinary surgeon is expected to attend simultaneously to the animal’s needs and to the client’s expectations which results in an ethical dilemma. This is reinforced by the fact that the social role of veterinarians has been increasingly questioned from being not only “animal healers” but also “animal protectors”. And often veterinarians are reluctant to use their authority (what the philosopher Bernard Rollin calls the Aesculpapian Authority)in advising the use of euthanasia (Rollin 2002).
- ^ Bovenkerk B, Brom FWA, van der Berg B, “Brave New Birds . The Use of ‘Animal Integrity’ in Animal Ethics”, Hastings Center Report, 2002, p16-22
- ^ Rollin BE, “Ethics of Critical Care”, J.Vet. Emergency and Critical Care, 2005, 15(4): 233-239
- ^ Rollin BE, "Euthanasia and quality of life", Journal American Veterinary Medical Association, 2006, 228 (7): 1014-1016
- ^ Rollin BE, The use and abuse of Aesculapian authority in veterinary medicine, Journal American Veterinary Medical Association, 2002, 220 (8): 1144-1149