Craig interpolation
In mathematical logic, Craig's interpolation theorem is a result about the relationship between different logical theories. Roughly stated, the theorem says that if a formula φ implies a formula ψ then there is a third formula ρ, called an interpolant, such that every nonlogical symbol in ρ occurs both in φ and ψ, φ implies ρ, and ρ implies ψ. The theorem was first proved for first-order logic by William Craig in 1957. Variants of the theorem hold for other logics, such as propositional logic. A stronger form of Craig's theorem for first-order logic was proved by Roger Lyndon in 1959; the overall result is sometimes called the Craig–Lyndon theorem.
Example
In propositional logic, let
- φ = ~(P ∧ Q) → (~R ∧ Q)
- ψ = (T → P) ∨ (T → ~R).
Then φ tautologically implies ψ. This can be verified by writing φ in conjunctive normal form:
- φ ≡ (P ∨ ~R) ∧ Q.
Thus, if φ holds, then (P ∨ ~R) holds. In turn, (P ∨ ~R) tautologically implies ψ. Because the two propositional variables occurring in (P ∨ ~R) occur in both φ and ψ, this means that (P ∨ ~R) is an interpolant for the implication φ → ψ.
Lyndon's interpolation theorem
Suppose that S and T are two first-order theories. As notation, let S ∪ T denote the smallest theory including both S and T; the signature of S ∪ T is the smallest one containing the signatures of S and T. Also let S ∩ T be the intersection of the two theories; the signature of S ∩ T is the intersection of the signatures of the two theories.
Lyndon's theorem says that if S ∪ T is unsatisfiable, then there is a interpolating sentence ρ in the language of S ∩ T that is true in all models of S and false in all models of T. Moreover, ρ has the stronger property that every relation symbol that has a positive occurrence in ρ has a positive occurrence in some formula of S and a negative occurrence in some formula of T, and every relation symbol with a negative occurrence in ρ has a negative occurrence in some formula of S and a positive occurrence in some formula of T.
Proof of Craig's Interpolation Theorem
We present here a constructive proof of the Craig interpolation theorem for propositional logic.[1] Formally, the theorem states:
If ⊨φ → ψ then there is a ρ (the interpolant) such that ⊨φ → ρ and ⊨ρ → ψ, where atoms(ρ) ⊆ atoms(φ) ∩ atoms(ψ). Here atoms(φ) here is the set of propositional variables occurring in φ, and ⊨ is the semantic entailment relation for propositional logic.
Proof. Assume ⊨φ → ψ. The proof proceeds by induction on the number of propositional variables occurring in φ that do not occur in ψ, denoted |atoms(φ) - atoms(ψ)|.
Base case |atoms(φ) - atoms(ψ)| = 0: In this case, φ is suitable. This is because since |atoms(φ) - atoms(ψ)| = 0, we know that atoms(φ) ⊆ atoms(φ) ∩ atoms(ψ). Moreover we have that ⊨φ → φ and ⊨φ → ψ. This suffices to show that φ is a suitable interpolant in this case.
Next assume for the inductive step that the result has been shown for all χ where |atoms(χ) - atoms(ψ)| = n. Now assume that |atoms(φ) - atoms(ψ)| = n+1. Pick a p ∈ atoms(φ) but p ∉ atoms(ψ). Now define:
φ' := φ[⊤/p] ∨ φ[⊥/p]
Here φ[⊤/p] is the same as φ with every occurrence of p replaced by ⊤ and φ[⊥/p] similarly replaces p with ⊥. We may observe three things from this definition:
(1) ⊨φ' → ψ
(2) |atoms(φ') - atoms(ψ)| = n
(3) ⊨φ → φ'
From (1), (2) and the inductive step we have that there is an interpolant ρ such that:
(4) ⊨φ' → ρ
(5) ⊨ρ → ψ
But from (3) and (4) we know that
(6) ⊨φ → ρ
Hence, ρ is a suitable interpolent for φ and ψ.
QED
Since the above proof is constructive, one may extract an algorithm for computing interpolants. Using this algorithm, if n = |atoms(φ') - atoms(ψ)|, then the interpolant ρ has O(EXP(n)) more logical connectives than φ (see Big O Notation for details regarding this assertion). Similar constructive proofs may be provided for the basic modal logic K, intuitionistic logic and μ-calculus, with similar complexity measures.
Craig interpolation can be proved by other methods as well. However, these proofs are generally non-constructive:
- model-theoretically, via Robinson's joint consistency theorem: in presence of compactness, negation and conjunction, Robinson's joint consistency theorem and Craig interpolation are equivalent.
- proof-theoretically, via a Sequent calculus. If cut elimination is possible and as a result the subformula property holds, then Craig interpolation is provable via induction over the derivations.
- algebraically, using amalgamation theorems for the variety of algebras representing the logic.
- via translation to other logics enjoying Craig interpolation.
Applications
Craig interpolation has many applications, among them consistency proofs, model checking, proofs in modular specifications, modular ontologies.
References
- ^ Harrison pgs. 426-427
- John Harrison (2009). Handbook of Practical Logic and Automated Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521899575.
- Hinman, P. (2005). Fundamentals of Mathematical Logic. A K Peters. ISBN 1-568-81262-0.
- Hinman, P. (2005). Fundamentals of Mathematical Logic. A K Peters. ISBN 1-568-81262-0.
- Dov M. Gabbay and Larisa Maksimova (2006). Interpolation and Definability: Modal and Intuitionistic Logics (Oxford Logic Guides). Oxford science publications, Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0198511748.
- Eva Hoogland, Definability and Interpolation. Model-theoretic investigations. PhD thesis, Amsterdam 2001.
- W. Craig, Three uses of the Herbrand-Gentzen theorem in relating model theory and proof theory, The Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (1957), no. 3, 269–285.