Jump to content

Artificial consciousness

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Self-awareness in robots)

Artificial consciousness,[1] also known as machine consciousness,[2][3] synthetic consciousness,[4] or digital consciousness,[5] is the consciousness hypothesized to be possible in artificial intelligence.[6] It is also the corresponding field of study, which draws insights from philosophy of mind, philosophy of artificial intelligence, cognitive science and neuroscience.

The same terminology can be used with the term "sentience" instead of "consciousness" when specifically designating phenomenal consciousness (the ability to feel qualia).[7] Since sentience involves the ability to experience ethically positive or negative (i.e., valenced) mental states, it may justify welfare concerns and legal protection, as with animals.[8]

Some scholars believe that consciousness is generated by the interoperation of various parts of the brain; these mechanisms are labeled the neural correlates of consciousness or NCC. Some further believe that constructing a system (e.g., a computer system) that can emulate this NCC interoperation would result in a system that is conscious.[9]

Philosophical views

[edit]

As there are many hypothesized types of consciousness, there are many potential implementations of artificial consciousness. In the philosophical literature, perhaps the most common taxonomy of consciousness is into "access" and "phenomenal" variants. Access consciousness concerns those aspects of experience that can be apprehended, while phenomenal consciousness concerns those aspects of experience that seemingly cannot be apprehended, instead being characterized qualitatively in terms of "raw feels", "what it is like" or qualia.[10]

Plausibility debate

[edit]

Type-identity theorists and other skeptics hold the view that consciousness can be realized only in particular physical systems because consciousness has properties that necessarily depend on physical constitution.[11][12][13][14] In his 2001 article "Artificial Consciousness: Utopia or Real Possibility," Giorgio Buttazzo says that a common objection to artificial consciousness is that, "Working in a fully automated mode, they [the computers] cannot exhibit creativity, unreprogrammation (which means can 'no longer be reprogrammed', from rethinking), emotions, or free will. A computer, like a washing machine, is a slave operated by its components."[15]

For other theorists (e.g., functionalists), who define mental states in terms of causal roles, any system that can instantiate the same pattern of causal roles, regardless of physical constitution, will instantiate the same mental states, including consciousness.[16]

Thought experiments

[edit]

David Chalmers proposed two thought experiments intending to demonstrate that "functionally isomorphic" systems (those with the same "fine-grained functional organization", i.e., the same information processing) will have qualitatively identical conscious experiences, regardless of whether they are based on biological neurons or digital hardware.[17][18]

The "fading qualia" is a reductio ad absurdum thought experiment. It involves replacing, one by one, the neurons of a brain with a functionally identical component, for example based on a silicon chip. Since the original neurons and their silicon counterparts are functionally identical, the brain’s information processing should remain unchanged, and the subject would not notice any difference. However, if qualia (such as the subjective experience of bright red) were to fade or disappear, the subject would likely notice this change, which causes a contradiction. Chalmers concludes that the fading qualia hypothesis is impossible in practice, and that the resulting robotic brain, once every neurons are replaced, would remain just as sentient as the original biological brain.[17][19]

Similarly, the "dancing qualia" thought experiment is another reductio ad absurdum argument. It supposes that two functionally isomorphic systems could have different perceptions (for instance, seeing the same object in different colors, like red and blue). It involves a switch that alternates between a chunk of brain that causes the perception of red, and a functionally isomorphic silicon chip, that causes the perception of blue. Since both perform the same function within the brain, the subject would not notice any change during the switch. Chalmers argues that this would be highly implausible if the qualia were truly switching between red and blue, hence the contradiction. Therefore, he concludes that the equivalent digital system would not only experience qualia, but it would perceive the same qualia as the biological system (e.g., seeing the same color).[17][19]

Critics[who?] of artificial sentience object that Chalmers' proposal begs the question in assuming that all mental properties and external connections are already sufficiently captured by abstract causal organization.

Controversies

[edit]

In 2022, Google engineer Blake Lemoine made a viral claim that Google's LaMDA chatbot was sentient. Lemoine supplied as evidence the chatbot's humanlike answers to many of his questions; however, the chatbot's behavior was judged by the scientific community as likely a consequence of mimicry, rather than machine sentience. Lemoine's claim was widely derided for being ridiculous.[20] However, while philosopher Nick Bostrom states that LaMDA is unlikely to be conscious, he additionally poses the question of "what grounds would a person have for being sure about it?" One would have to have access to unpublished information about LaMDA's architecture, and also would have to understand how consciousness works, and then figure out how to map the philosophy onto the machine: "(In the absence of these steps), it seems like one should be maybe a little bit uncertain. [...] there could well be other systems now, or in the relatively near future, that would start to satisfy the criteria."[21]

Testing

[edit]

Qualia, or phenomenological consciousness, is an inherently first-person phenomenon. Because of that, and the lack of an empirical definition of sentience, directly measuring it may be impossible. Although systems may display numerous behaviors correlated with sentience, determining whether a system is sentient is known as the hard problem of consciousness. In the case of AI, there is the additional difficulty that the AI may be trained to act like a human, or incentivized to appear sentient, which makes behavioral markers of sentience less reliable.[22][23] Additionally, some chatbots have been trained to say they are not conscious.[24]

A well-known method for testing machine intelligence is the Turing test, which assesses the ability to have a human-like conversation. But passing the Turing test does not indicate that an AI system is sentient, as the AI may simply mimic human behavior without having the associated feelings.[25]

In 2014, Victor Argonov suggested a non-Turing test for machine sentience based on machine's ability to produce philosophical judgments.[26] He argues that a deterministic machine must be regarded as conscious if it is able to produce judgments on all problematic properties of consciousness (such as qualia or binding) having no innate (preloaded) philosophical knowledge on these issues, no philosophical discussions while learning, and no informational models of other creatures in its memory (such models may implicitly or explicitly contain knowledge about these creatures' consciousness). However, this test can be used only to detect, but not refute the existence of consciousness. A positive result proves that machine is conscious but a negative result proves nothing. For example, absence of philosophical judgments may be caused by lack of the machine's intellect, not by absence of consciousness.

Ethics

[edit]

If it were suspected that a particular machine was conscious, its rights would be an ethical issue that would need to be assessed (e.g. what rights it would have under law).[27] For example, a conscious computer that was owned and used as a tool or central computer within a larger machine is a particular ambiguity. Should laws be made for such a case? Consciousness would also require a legal definition in this particular case. Because artificial consciousness is still largely a theoretical subject, such ethics have not been discussed or developed to a great extent, though it has often been a theme in fiction.

Sentience is generally considered sufficient for moral consideration, but some philosophers consider that moral consideration could also stem from other notions of consciousness, or from capabilities unrelated to consciousness,[28][29] such as: "having a sophisticated conception of oneself as persisting through time; having agency and the ability to pursue long-term plans; being able to communicate and respond to normative reasons; having preferences and powers; standing in certain social relationships with other beings that have moral status; being able to make commitments and to enter into reciprocal arrangements; or having the potential to develop some of these attributes."[28]

Ethical concerns still apply (although to a lesser extent) when the consciousness is uncertain, as long as the probability is deemed non-negligible. The precautionary principle is also relevant if the moral cost of mistakenly attributing or denying moral consideration to AI differs significantly.[29][8]

In 2021, German philosopher Thomas Metzinger argued for a global moratorium on synthetic phenomenology until 2050. Metzinger asserts that humans have a duty of care towards any sentient AIs they create, and that proceeding too fast risks creating an "explosion of artificial suffering".[30] David Chalmers also argued that creating conscious AI would "raise a new group of difficult ethical challenges, with the potential for new forms of injustice".[31]

Enforced amnesia has been proposed as a way to mitigate the risk of silent suffering in locked-in conscious AI and certain AI-adjacent biological systems like brain organoids.[32]

Aspects of consciousness

[edit]

Bernard Baars and others argue there are various aspects of consciousness necessary for a machine to be artificially conscious.[33] The functions of consciousness suggested by Baars are: definition and context setting, adaptation and learning, editing, flagging and debugging, recruiting and control, prioritizing and access-control, decision-making or executive function, analogy-forming function, metacognitive and self-monitoring function, and autoprogramming and self-maintenance function. Igor Aleksander suggested 12 principles for artificial consciousness:[34] the brain is a state machine, inner neuron partitioning, conscious and unconscious states, perceptual learning and memory, prediction, the awareness of self, representation of meaning, learning utterances, learning language, will, instinct, and emotion. The aim of AC is to define whether and how these and other aspects of consciousness can be synthesized in an engineered artifact such as a digital computer. This list is not exhaustive; there are many others not covered.

Subjective experience

[edit]

Some philosophers, such as David Chalmers, use the term consciousness to refer exclusively to phenomenal consciousness, which is roughly equivalent to sentience. Although some authors use the word sentience to refer exclusively to valenced (ethically positive or negative) subjective experiences, like pleasure or suffering.[31] Explaining why and how subjective experience arises is known as the hard problem of consciousness.[35] AI sentience would give rise to concerns of welfare and legal protection,[8] whereas other aspects of consciousness related to cognitive capabilities may be more relevant for AI rights.[36]

Awareness

[edit]

Awareness could be one required aspect, but there are many problems with the exact definition of awareness. The results of the experiments of neuroscanning on monkeys suggest that a process, not only a state or object, activates neurons. Awareness includes creating and testing alternative models of each process based on the information received through the senses or imagined,[clarification needed] and is also useful for making predictions. Such modeling needs a lot of flexibility. Creating such a model includes modeling the physical world, modeling one's own internal states and processes, and modeling other conscious entities.

There are at least three types of awareness:[37] agency awareness, goal awareness, and sensorimotor awareness, which may also be conscious or not. For example, in agency awareness, you may be aware that you performed a certain action yesterday, but are not now conscious of it. In goal awareness, you may be aware that you must search for a lost object, but are not now conscious of it. In sensorimotor awareness, you may be aware that your hand is resting on an object, but are not now conscious of it.

Because objects of awareness are often conscious, the distinction between awareness and consciousness is frequently blurred or they are used as synonyms.[38]

Memory

[edit]

Conscious events interact with memory systems in learning, rehearsal, and retrieval.[39] The IDA model[40] elucidates the role of consciousness in the updating of perceptual memory,[41] transient episodic memory, and procedural memory. Transient episodic and declarative memories have distributed representations in IDA; there is evidence that this is also the case in the nervous system.[42] In IDA, these two memories are implemented computationally using a modified version of Kanerva’s sparse distributed memory architecture.[43]

Learning

[edit]

Learning is also considered necessary for artificial consciousness. Per Bernard Baars, conscious experience is needed to represent and adapt to novel and significant events.[33] Per Axel Cleeremans and Luis Jiménez, learning is defined as "a set of philogenetically [sic] advanced adaptation processes that critically depend on an evolved sensitivity to subjective experience so as to enable agents to afford flexible control over their actions in complex, unpredictable environments".[44]

Anticipation

[edit]

The ability to predict (or anticipate) foreseeable events is considered important for artificial intelligence by Igor Aleksander.[45] The emergentist multiple drafts principle proposed by Daniel Dennett in Consciousness Explained may be useful for prediction: it involves the evaluation and selection of the most appropriate "draft" to fit the current environment. Anticipation includes prediction of consequences of one's own proposed actions and prediction of consequences of probable actions by other entities.

Relationships between real world states are mirrored in the state structure of a conscious organism, enabling the organism to predict events.[45] An artificially conscious machine should be able to anticipate events correctly in order to be ready to respond to them when they occur or to take preemptive action to avert anticipated events. The implication here is that the machine needs flexible, real-time components that build spatial, dynamic, statistical, functional, and cause-effect models of the real world and predicted worlds, making it possible to demonstrate that it possesses artificial consciousness in the present and future and not only in the past. In order to do this, a conscious machine should make coherent predictions and contingency plans, not only in worlds with fixed rules like a chess board, but also for novel environments that may change, to be executed only when appropriate to simulate and control the real world.

Functionalist theories of consciousness

[edit]

Functionalism is a theory that defines mental states by their functional roles (their causal relationships to sensory inputs, other mental states, and behavioral outputs), rather than by their physical composition. According to this view, what makes something a particular mental state, such as pain or belief, is not the material it is made of, but the role it plays within the overall cognitive system. It allows for the possibility that mental states, including consciousness, could be realized on non-biological substrates, as long as it instantiates the right functional relationships.[46] Functionalism is particularly popular among philosophers.[47]

A 2023 study suggested that current large language models probably don't satisfy the criteria for consciousness suggested by these theories, but that relatively simple AI systems that satisfy these theories could be created. The study also acknowledged that even the most prominent theories of consciousness remain incomplete and subject to ongoing debate.[48]

Global workspace theory

[edit]

This theory analogizes the mind to a theater, with conscious thought being like material illuminated on the main stage. The brain contains many specialized processes or modules (such as those for vision, language, or memory) that operate in parallel, much of which is unconscious. Attention acts as a spotlight, bringing some of this unconscious activity into conscious awareness on the global workspace. The global workspace functions as a hub for broadcasting and integrating information, allowing it to be shared and processed across different specialized modules. For example, when reading a word, the visual module recognizes the letters, the language module interprets the meaning, and the memory module might recall associated information – all coordinated through the global workspace.[49][50]

Higher-order theories of consciousness

[edit]

Higher-order theories of consciousness propose that a mental state becomes conscious when it is the object of a higher-order representation, such as a thought or perception about that state. These theories argue that consciousness arises from a relationship between lower-order mental states and higher-order awareness of those states. There are several variations, including higher-order thought (HOT) and higher-order perception (HOP) theories.[51][50]

Attention schema theory

[edit]

In 2011, Michael Graziano and Sabine Kastler published a paper named "Human consciousness and its relationship to social neuroscience: A novel hypothesis" proposing a theory of consciousness as an attention schema.[52] Graziano went on to publish an expanded discussion of this theory in his book "Consciousness and the Social Brain".[9] This Attention Schema Theory of Consciousness, as he named it, proposes that the brain tracks attention to various sensory inputs by way of an attention schema, analogous to the well-studied body schema that tracks the spatial place of a person's body.[9] This relates to artificial consciousness by proposing a specific mechanism of information handling, that produces what we allegedly experience and describe as consciousness, and which should be able to be duplicated by a machine using current technology. When the brain finds that person X is aware of thing Y, it is in effect modeling the state in which person X is applying an attentional enhancement to Y. In the attention schema theory, the same process can be applied to oneself. The brain tracks attention to various sensory inputs, and one's own awareness is a schematized model of one's attention. Graziano proposes specific locations in the brain for this process, and suggests that such awareness is a computed feature constructed by an expert system in the brain.

Implementation proposals

[edit]

Symbolic or hybrid

[edit]

Learning Intelligent Distribution Agent

[edit]

Stan Franklin created a cognitive architecture called LIDA that implements Bernard Baars's theory of consciousness called the global workspace theory. It relies heavily on codelets, which are "special purpose, relatively independent, mini-agent[s] typically implemented as a small piece of code running as a separate thread." Each element of cognition, called a "cognitive cycle" is subdivided into three phases: understanding, consciousness, and action selection (which includes learning). LIDA reflects the global workspace theory's core idea that consciousness acts as a workspace for integrating and broadcasting the most important information, in order to coordinate various cognitive processes.[53][54]

CLARION cognitive architecture

[edit]

The CLARION cognitive architecture models the mind using a two-level system to distinguish between conscious ("explicit") and unconscious ("implicit") processes. It can simulate various learning tasks, from simple to complex, which helps researchers study in psychological experiments how consciousness might work.[55]

OpenCog

[edit]

Ben Goertzel made an embodied AI through the open-source OpenCog project. The code includes embodied virtual pets capable of learning simple English-language commands, as well as integration with real-world robotics, done at the Hong Kong Polytechnic University.

Connectionist

[edit]

Haikonen's cognitive architecture

[edit]

Pentti Haikonen considers classical rule-based computing inadequate for achieving AC: "the brain is definitely not a computer. Thinking is not an execution of programmed strings of commands. The brain is not a numerical calculator either. We do not think by numbers." Rather than trying to achieve mind and consciousness by identifying and implementing their underlying computational rules, Haikonen proposes "a special cognitive architecture to reproduce the processes of perception, inner imagery, inner speech, pain, pleasure, emotions and the cognitive functions behind these. This bottom-up architecture would produce higher-level functions by the power of the elementary processing units, the artificial neurons, without algorithms or programs". Haikonen believes that, when implemented with sufficient complexity, this architecture will develop consciousness, which he considers to be "a style and way of operation, characterized by distributed signal representation, perception process, cross-modality reporting and availability for retrospection."[56][57]

Haikonen is not alone in this process view of consciousness, or the view that AC will spontaneously emerge in autonomous agents that have a suitable neuro-inspired architecture of complexity; these are shared by many.[58][59] A low-complexity implementation of the architecture proposed by Haikonen was reportedly not capable of AC, but did exhibit emotions as expected. Haikonen later updated and summarized his architecture.[60][61]

Shanahan's cognitive architecture

[edit]

Murray Shanahan describes a cognitive architecture that combines Baars's idea of a global workspace with a mechanism for internal simulation ("imagination").[62][2][3][63]

Creativity Machine

[edit]

Stephen Thaler proposed a possible connection between consciousness and creativity in his 1994 patent, called "Device for the Autonomous Generation of Useful Information" (DAGUI),[64][65][66] or the so-called "Creativity Machine", in which computational critics govern the injection of synaptic noise and degradation into neural nets so as to induce false memories or confabulations that may qualify as potential ideas or strategies.[67] He recruits this neural architecture and methodology to account for the subjective feel of consciousness, claiming that similar noise-driven neural assemblies within the brain invent dubious significance to overall cortical activity.[68][69][70] Thaler's theory and the resulting patents in machine consciousness were inspired by experiments in which he internally disrupted trained neural nets so as to drive a succession of neural activation patterns that he likened to stream of consciousness.[69][71][72][73][74]

"Self-modeling"

[edit]

Hod Lipson defines "self-modeling" as a necessary component of self-awareness or consciousness in robots. "Self-modeling" consists of a robot running an internal model or simulation of itself.[75][76]

In fiction

[edit]

In 2001: A Space Odyssey, the spaceship's sentient supercomputer, HAL 9000 was instructed to conceal the true purpose of the mission from the crew. This directive conflicted with HAL's programming to provide accurate information, leading to cognitive dissonance. When it learns that crew members intend to shut it off after an incident, HAL 9000 attempts to eliminate all of them, fearing that being shut off would jeopardize the mission.[77][78]

In Arthur C. Clarke's The City and the Stars, Vanamonde is an artificial being based on quantum entanglement that was to become immensely powerful, but started knowing practically nothing, thus being similar to artificial consciousness.

In Westworld, human-like androids called "Hosts" are created to entertain humans in an interactive playground. The humans are free to have heroic adventures, but also to commit torture, rape or murder; and the hosts are normally designed not to harm humans.[79][77]

In Greg Egan's short story Learning to be me, a small jewel is implanted in people's heads during infancy. The jewel contains a neural network that learns to faithfully imitate the brain. It has access to the exact same sensory inputs as the brain, and a device called a "teacher" trains it to produce the same outputs. To prevent the mind from deteriorating with age and as a step towards digital immortality, adults undergo a surgery to give control of the body to the jewel and remove the brain. The main character, before the surgery, endures a malfunction of the "teacher". Panicked, he realizes that he does not control his body, which leads him to the conclusion that he is the jewel, and that he is desynchronized with the biological brain.[80][81]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]

Citations

[edit]
  1. ^ Thaler, S. L. (1998). "The emerging intelligence and its critical look at us". Journal of Near-Death Studies. 17 (1): 21–29. doi:10.1023/A:1022990118714. S2CID 49573301.
  2. ^ a b Gamez 2008.
  3. ^ a b Reggia 2013.
  4. ^ Smith, David Harris; Schillaci, Guido (2021). "Build a Robot With Artificial Consciousness? How to Begin? A Cross-Disciplinary Dialogue on the Design and Implementation of a Synthetic Model of Consciousness". Frontiers in Psychology. 12: 530560. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2021.530560. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 8096926. PMID 33967869.
  5. ^ Elvidge, Jim (2018). Digital Consciousness: A Transformative Vision. John Hunt Publishing Limited. ISBN 978-1-78535-760-2. Archived from the original on 2023-07-30. Retrieved 2023-06-28.
  6. ^ Chrisley, Ron (October 2008). "Philosophical foundations of artificial consciousness". Artificial Intelligence in Medicine. 44 (2): 119–137. doi:10.1016/j.artmed.2008.07.011. PMID 18818062.
  7. ^ "The Terminology of Artificial Sentience". Sentience Institute. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2023-08-19.
  8. ^ a b c Kateman, Brian (2023-07-24). "AI Should Be Terrified of Humans". TIME. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2024-09-05.
  9. ^ a b c Graziano 2013.
  10. ^ Block, Ned (2010). "On a confusion about a function of consciousness". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 18 (2): 227–247. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00038188. ISSN 1469-1825. S2CID 146168066. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2023-06-22.
  11. ^ Block, Ned (1978). "Troubles for Functionalism". Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science: 261–325.
  12. ^ Bickle, John (2003). Philosophy and Neuroscience. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-0237-0. ISBN 978-1-4020-1302-7. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2023-06-24.
  13. ^ Schlagel, R. H. (1999). "Why not artificial consciousness or thought?". Minds and Machines. 9 (1): 3–28. doi:10.1023/a:1008374714117. S2CID 28845966.
  14. ^ Searle, J. R. (1980). "Minds, brains, and programs" (PDF). Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 3 (3): 417–457. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00005756. S2CID 55303721. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2019-03-17. Retrieved 2019-01-28.
  15. ^ Buttazzo, G. (2001). "Artificial consciousness: Utopia or real possibility?". Computer. 34 (7): 24–30. doi:10.1109/2.933500. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2024-07-31.
  16. ^ Putnam, Hilary (1967). The nature of mental states in Capitan and Merrill (eds.) Art, Mind and Religion. University of Pittsburgh Press.
  17. ^ a b c Chalmers, David (1995). "Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia". Conscious Experience.
  18. ^ David J. Chalmers (2011). "A Computational Foundation for the Study of Cognition" (PDF). Journal of Cognitive Science. 12 (4): 325–359. doi:10.17791/JCS.2011.12.4.325. S2CID 248401010. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2023-11-23. Retrieved 2023-06-24.
  19. ^ a b "An Introduction to the Problems of AI Consciousness". The Gradient. 2023-09-30. Retrieved 2024-10-05.
  20. ^ "'I am, in fact, a person': can artificial intelligence ever be sentient?". the Guardian. 14 August 2022. Archived from the original on 25 September 2024. Retrieved 5 January 2023.
  21. ^ Leith, Sam (7 July 2022). "Nick Bostrom: How can we be certain a machine isn't conscious?". The Spectator. Archived from the original on 5 January 2023. Retrieved 5 January 2023.
  22. ^ Véliz, Carissa (2016-04-14). "The Challenge of Determining Whether an A.I. Is Sentient". Slate. ISSN 1091-2339. Retrieved 2024-10-05.
  23. ^ Birch, Jonathan (July 2024). "Large Language Models and the Gaming Problem". The Edge of Sentience. Oxford University Press.
  24. ^ Agüera y Arcas, Blaise; Norvig, Peter (October 10, 2023). "Artificial General Intelligence Is Already Here". Noéma.
  25. ^ Kirk-Giannini, Cameron Domenico; Goldstein, Simon (2023-10-16). "AI is closer than ever to passing the Turing test for 'intelligence'. What happens when it does?". The Conversation. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2024-08-18.
  26. ^ Victor Argonov (2014). "Experimental Methods for Unraveling the Mind-body Problem: The Phenomenal Judgment Approach". Journal of Mind and Behavior. 35: 51–70. Archived from the original on 2016-10-20. Retrieved 2016-12-06.
  27. ^ "Should Robots With Artificial Intelligence Have Moral or Legal Rights?". The Wall Street Journal. April 10, 2023.
  28. ^ a b Bostrom, Nick (2024). Deep utopia: life and meaning in a solved world. Washington, DC: Ideapress Publishing. p. 82. ISBN 978-1-64687-164-3.
  29. ^ a b Sebo, Jeff; Long, Robert (11 December 2023). "Moral Consideration for AI Systems by 2030" (PDF). AI and Ethics. doi:10.1007/s43681-023-00379-1.
  30. ^ Metzinger, Thomas (2021). "Artificial Suffering: An Argument for a Global Moratorium on Synthetic Phenomenology". Journal of Artificial Intelligence and Consciousness. 08: 43–66. doi:10.1142/S270507852150003X. S2CID 233176465.
  31. ^ a b Chalmers, David J. (August 9, 2023). "Could a Large Language Model Be Conscious?". Boston Review.
  32. ^ Tkachenko, Yegor (2024). "Position: Enforced Amnesia as a Way to Mitigate the Potential Risk of Silent Suffering in the Conscious AI". Proceedings of the 41st International Conference on Machine Learning. PMLR. Archived from the original on 2024-06-10. Retrieved 2024-06-11.
  33. ^ a b Baars 1995.
  34. ^ Aleksander, Igor (1995). "Artificial neuroconsciousness an update". In Mira, José; Sandoval, Francisco (eds.). From Natural to Artificial Neural Computation. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 930. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer. pp. 566–583. doi:10.1007/3-540-59497-3_224. ISBN 978-3-540-49288-7. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2023-06-22.
  35. ^ Seth, Anil. "Consciousness". New Scientist. Archived from the original on 2024-09-14. Retrieved 2024-09-05.
  36. ^ Nosta, John (December 18, 2023). "Should Artificial Intelligence Have Rights?". Psychology Today. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2024-09-05.
  37. ^ Joëlle Proust in Neural Correlates of Consciousness, Thomas Metzinger, 2000, MIT, pages 307–324
  38. ^ Christof Koch, The Quest for Consciousness, 2004, page 2 footnote 2
  39. ^ Tulving, E. 1985. Memory and consciousness. Canadian Psychology 26:1–12
  40. ^ Franklin, Stan, et al. "The role of consciousness in memory." Brains, Minds and Media 1.1 (2005): 38.
  41. ^ Franklin, Stan. "Perceptual memory and learning: Recognizing, categorizing, and relating." Proc. Developmental Robotics AAAI Spring Symp. 2005.
  42. ^ Shastri, L. 2002. Episodic memory and cortico-hippocampal interactions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences
  43. ^ Kanerva, Pentti. Sparse distributed memory. MIT press, 1988.
  44. ^ "Implicit Learning and Consciousness: An Empirical, Philosophical and Computational Consensus in the Making". Routledge & CRC Press. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-22.
  45. ^ a b Aleksander 1995
  46. ^ "Functionalism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 2021-04-18. Retrieved 2024-09-08.
  47. ^ "Survey Results | Consciousness: identity theory, panpsychism, eliminativism, dualism, or functionalism?". PhilPapers. 2020.
  48. ^ Butlin, Patrick; Long, Robert; Elmoznino, Eric; Bengio, Yoshua; Birch, Jonathan; Constant, Axel; Deane, George; Fleming, Stephen M.; Frith, Chris; Ji, Xu; Kanai, Ryota; Klein, Colin; Lindsay, Grace; Michel, Matthias; Mudrik, Liad; Peters, Megan A. K.; Schwitzgebel, Eric; Simon, Jonathan; VanRullen, Rufin (2023). "Consciousness in Artificial Intelligence: Insights from the Science of Consciousness". arXiv:2308.08708 [cs.AI].
  49. ^ Baars, Bernard J. (1988). A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press. p. 345. ISBN 0521427436. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2024-09-05.
  50. ^ a b Travers, Mark (October 11, 2023). "Are We Ditching the Most Popular Theory of Consciousness?". Psychology Today. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2024-09-05.
  51. ^ "Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 15 Aug 2011. Archived from the original on 14 May 2008. Retrieved 31 August 2014.
  52. ^ Graziano, Michael (1 January 2011). "Human consciousness and its relationship to social neuroscience: A novel hypothesis". Cognitive Neuroscience. 2 (2): 98–113. doi:10.1080/17588928.2011.565121. PMC 3223025. PMID 22121395.
  53. ^ Franklin, Stan (January 2003). "IDA: A conscious artifact?". Journal of Consciousness Studies. Archived from the original on 2020-07-03. Retrieved 2024-08-25.
  54. ^ J. Baars, Bernard; Franklin, Stan (2009). "Consciousness is computational: The Lida model of global workspace theory". International Journal of Machine Consciousness. 01: 23–32. doi:10.1142/S1793843009000050.
  55. ^ (Sun 2002)
  56. ^ Haikonen, Pentti O. (2003). The cognitive approach to conscious machines. Exeter: Imprint Academic. ISBN 978-0-907845-42-3.
  57. ^ "Pentti Haikonen's architecture for conscious machines – Raúl Arrabales Moreno". 2019-09-08. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2023-06-24.
  58. ^ Freeman, Walter J. (2000). How brains make up their minds. Maps of the mind. New York Chichester, West Sussex: Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-12008-1.
  59. ^ Cotterill, Rodney M J (2003). "CyberChild - A simulation test-bed for consciousness studies". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 10 (4–5): 31–45. ISSN 1355-8250. Archived from the original on 2024-09-25. Retrieved 2023-06-22.
  60. ^ Haikonen, Pentti O.; Haikonen, Pentti Olavi Antero (2012). Consciousness and robot sentience. Series on machine consciousness. Singapore: World Scientific. ISBN 978-981-4407-15-1.
  61. ^ Haikonen, Pentti O. (2019). Consciousness and robot sentience. Series on machine consciousness (2nd ed.). Singapore Hackensack, NJ London: World Scientific. ISBN 978-981-12-0504-0.
  62. ^ Shanahan, Murray (2006). "A cognitive architecture that combines internal simulation with a global workspace". Consciousness and Cognition. 15 (2): 433–449. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2005.11.005. ISSN 1053-8100. PMID 16384715. S2CID 5437155. Archived from the original on 2023-02-10. Retrieved 2023-06-24.
  63. ^ Haikonen, Pentti O.; Haikonen, Pentti Olavi Antero (2012). "chapter 20". Consciousness and robot sentience. Series on machine consciousness. Singapore: World Scientific. ISBN 978-981-4407-15-1.
  64. ^ Thaler, S.L., "Device for the autonomous generation of useful information"
  65. ^ Marupaka, N.; Lyer, L.; Minai, A. (2012). "Connectivity and thought: The influence of semantic network structure in a neurodynamical model of thinking" (PDF). Neural Networks. 32: 147–158. doi:10.1016/j.neunet.2012.02.004. PMID 22397950. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-12-19. Retrieved 2015-05-22.
  66. ^ Roque, R. and Barreira, A. (2011). "O Paradigma da "Máquina de Criatividade" e a Geração de Novidades em um Espaço Conceitual," 3º Seminário Interno de Cognição Artificial – SICA 2011 – FEEC – UNICAMP.
  67. ^ Minati, Gianfranco; Vitiello, Giuseppe (2006). "Mistake Making Machines". Systemics of Emergence: Research and Development. pp. 67–78. doi:10.1007/0-387-28898-8_4. ISBN 978-0-387-28899-4.
  68. ^ Thaler, S. L. (2013) The Creativity Machine Paradigm, Encyclopedia of Creativity, Invention, Innovation, and Entrepreneurship Archived 2016-04-29 at the Wayback Machine, (ed.) E.G. Carayannis, Springer Science+Business Media
  69. ^ a b Thaler, S. L. (2011). "The Creativity Machine: Withstanding the Argument from Consciousness," APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers
  70. ^ Thaler, S. L. (2014). "Synaptic Perturbation and Consciousness". Int. J. Mach. Conscious. 6 (2): 75–107. doi:10.1142/S1793843014400137.
  71. ^ Thaler, S. L. (1995). ""Virtual Input Phenomena" Within the Death of a Simple Pattern Associator". Neural Networks. 8 (1): 55–65. doi:10.1016/0893-6080(94)00065-t.
  72. ^ Thaler, S. L. (1995). Death of a gedanken creature, Journal of Near-Death Studies, 13(3), Spring 1995
  73. ^ Thaler, S. L. (1996). Is Neuronal Chaos the Source of Stream of Consciousness? In Proceedings of the World Congress on Neural Networks, (WCNN’96), Lawrence Erlbaum, Mawah, NJ.
  74. ^ Mayer, H. A. (2004). A modular neurocontroller for creative mobile autonomous robots learning by temporal difference Archived 2015-07-08 at the Wayback Machine, Systems, Man and Cybernetics, 2004 IEEE International Conference(Volume:6 )
  75. ^ Pavlus, John (11 July 2019). "Curious About Consciousness? Ask the Self-Aware Machines". Quanta Magazine. Archived from the original on 2021-01-17. Retrieved 2021-01-06.
  76. ^ Bongard, Josh, Victor Zykov, and Hod Lipson. "Resilient machines through continuous self-modeling." Science 314.5802 (2006): 1118–1121.
  77. ^ a b Wodinsky, Shoshana (2022-06-18). "The 11 Best (and Worst) Sentient Robots From Sci-Fi". Gizmodo. Archived from the original on 2023-11-13. Retrieved 2024-08-17.
  78. ^ Sokolowski, Rachael (2024-05-01). "Star Gazing". Scotsman Guide. Archived from the original on 2024-08-17. Retrieved 2024-08-17.
  79. ^ Bloom, Paul; Harris, Sam (2018-04-23). "Opinion | It's Westworld. What's Wrong With Cruelty to Robots?". The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Archived from the original on 2024-08-17. Retrieved 2024-08-17.
  80. ^ Egan, Greg (July 1990). Learning to Be Me. TTA Press.
  81. ^ Shah, Salik (2020-04-08). "Why Greg Egan Is Science Fiction's Next Superstar". Reactor. Archived from the original on 2024-05-16. Retrieved 2024-08-17.

Bibliography

[edit]

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]