Examine individual changes
Appearance
This page allows you to examine the variables generated by the Edit Filter for an individual change.
Variables generated for this change
Variable | Value |
---|---|
Edit count of the user (user_editcount ) | null |
Name of the user account (user_name ) | '50.233.176.2' |
Age of the user account (user_age ) | 0 |
Groups (including implicit) the user is in (user_groups ) | [
0 => '*'
] |
Rights that the user has (user_rights ) | [
0 => 'createaccount',
1 => 'read',
2 => 'edit',
3 => 'createtalk',
4 => 'writeapi',
5 => 'viewmywatchlist',
6 => 'editmywatchlist',
7 => 'viewmyprivateinfo',
8 => 'editmyprivateinfo',
9 => 'editmyoptions',
10 => 'abusefilter-log-detail',
11 => 'urlshortener-create-url',
12 => 'centralauth-merge',
13 => 'abusefilter-view',
14 => 'abusefilter-log',
15 => 'vipsscaler-test'
] |
Whether the user is editing from mobile app (user_app ) | false |
Whether or not a user is editing through the mobile interface (user_mobile ) | false |
Page ID (page_id ) | 48990 |
Page namespace (page_namespace ) | 0 |
Page title without namespace (page_title ) | 'Social justice' |
Full page title (page_prefixedtitle ) | 'Social justice' |
Edit protection level of the page (page_restrictions_edit ) | [] |
Last ten users to contribute to the page (page_recent_contributors ) | [
0 => 'Citation bot',
1 => 'Kliker Ghost',
2 => 'SierraTangoCharlie1',
3 => '208.105.198.226',
4 => 'Beauty School Dropout',
5 => '2603:8001:2601:F351:318D:6E8B:1539:3CAD',
6 => 'Gouncbeatduke',
7 => '72.10.136.22',
8 => 'Davide King',
9 => 'Trakking'
] |
Page age in seconds (page_age ) | 631658101 |
Action (action ) | 'edit' |
Edit summary/reason (summary ) | '/* History */ ' |
Old content model (old_content_model ) | 'wikitext' |
New content model (new_content_model ) | 'wikitext' |
Old page wikitext, before the edit (old_wikitext ) | '{{short description|Concept of fair and just relations between the individual and society}}
{{pp-pc1}}
{{for multi|the early-20th-century periodical|Social Justice (periodical)|the academic journal established in 1974|Social Justice (journal)}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=November 2020}}
{{use American English|date=November 2017}}
'''Social justice''' is justice in terms of the distribution of [[wealth]], [[Equal opportunity|opportunities]], and [[Social privilege|privilege]]s within a society.<ref name="Oxford">{{cite web |title=social justice |url=https://languages.oup.com/google-dictionary-en/ |website=Oxford languages |access-date=26 August 2021}}</ref> In [[Western Civilization|Western]] as well as in older [[Culture of Asia|Asian cultures]], the concept of social justice has often referred to the process of ensuring that individuals fulfill their [[Role theory|societal roles]] and receive what was their due from society.<ref>[[Aristotle]], ''[[The Politics]]'' (ca 350 BC)</ref><ref name="Augustine">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8djVCRFoyQTZYS0k |title = "Augustine on Justice," a Chapter in Augustine and Social Justice |publisher = Lexington Books |author = Clark, Mary T. |year = 2015 |pages = 3–10 |isbn = 978-1-4985-0918-3 }}</ref><ref name="Global Dynamics">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8eXZMWHU3ckpQVUk |title = Social Justice, Global Dynamics : Theoretical and Empirical Perspectives |publisher = Taylor and Francis |author1 = Banai, Ayelet |author2 = Ronzoni, Miriam |author3 = Schemmel, Christian |year = 2011 |location = Florence |isbn = 978-0-203-81929-6 }}</ref> In the current movements for social justice, the emphasis has been on the breaking of barriers for [[social mobility]], the creation of [[Social safety net|safety nets]], and [[economic justice]].<ref>{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8V3hpa0V1ekFQZms |title = Seeking Social Justice Through Globalization Escaping a Nationalist Perspective |publisher = Pennsylvania State University Press |author = Kitching, G. N. |year = 2001 |location = University Park, Pa |pages = 3–10 |isbn = 978-0-271-02377-9 }}</ref><ref name="Globalization and Social Justice">{{cite journal |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8R2tWbXFmelhzVDA |title = Globalization and Social Justice |author = Hillman, Arye L. |journal = The Singapore Economic Review |year = 2008 |volume = 53 |issue = 2 |pages = 173–189 |doi=10.1142/s0217590808002896}}</ref><ref name="Movements in Time">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MWpSSGRWUllXTEE |title = Movements in Time Revolution, Social Justice, and Times of Change |publisher = Cambridge Scholars Pub |author1 = Lawrence, Cecile |author2 = Natalie Churn |name-list-style = amp |year = 2012 |location = Newcastle upon Tyne, UK |pages = xi–xv |isbn = 978-1-4438-4552-6 }}</ref><ref name="The Question of Social Justice">{{cite journal |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8Qm8zcHRRQ0xFN2c |title = Globalization and the Question of Social Justice |author = Agartan, Kaan |journal = Sociology Compass |year = 2014 |volume = 8 |issue = 6 |pages = 903–915 |doi = 10.1111/soc4.12162 }}</ref><ref name="A propositional political approach">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MTk1Qkp2b0ZaNDg |title = Globalization Development and Social Justice : A propositional political approach |publisher = Taylor and Francis |author = El Khoury, Ann |year = 2015 |location = Florence |pages = 1–20 |isbn = 978-1-317-50480-1 }}</ref>{{Excessive citations inline|date=October 2021}} Social justice assigns rights and duties in the [[institution]]s of society, which enables people to receive the basic benefits and burdens of cooperation. The relevant institutions often include [[taxation]], [[social insurance]], [[public health]], [[State school|public school]], [[public services]], [[labor law]] and [[regulation]] of [[Market (economics)|markets]], to ensure [[distribution of wealth]], and [[equal opportunity]].<ref>John Rawls, ''A Theory of Justice'' (1971) 4, "the principles of social justice: they provide a way of assigning rights and duties in the basic institutions of society and they define the appropriate distribution of benefits and burdens of social co-operation."</ref>
Interpretations that relate justice to a [[Reciprocity (social and political philosophy)|reciprocal relationship]] to society are mediated by differences in cultural traditions, some of which emphasize the individual responsibility toward society and others the equilibrium between access to power and its responsible use.<ref>{{cite journal |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8cTlPd2dzZ3d3TG8 |title = The Antecedents of Help Giving in Chinese Culture: Attribution, Judgment of Responsibility, Expectation Change and the Reaction of Affect |author1 = Aiqing Zhang |author2 = Feifei Xia |author3 = Chengwei Li |journal = Social Behavior and Personality |year = 2007 |volume = 35 |issue = 1 |pages = 135–142 |doi=10.2224/sbp.2007.35.1.135}}</ref> Hence, social justice is invoked today while reinterpreting historical figures such as [[Bartolomé de las Casas]], in philosophical debates about differences among human beings, in efforts for gender, ethnic, and [[social equality]], for advocating justice for [[Emigration|migrants]], prisoners, the [[environmental justice|environment]], and the physically and developmentally [[Disability|disabled]].<ref name="Human Nature">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MWRYV0xVUzNlRlU |title = Nature, Human Nature, and Human Difference : Race in Early Modern Philosophy |publisher = Princeton University Press |author = Smith, Justin E. H. |year = 2015 |page = 17 |isbn = 978-1-4008-6631-1 }}</ref><ref name="Migration, Gender and Social Justice">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8RGJGb0RiZEc0NzA |title = Migration, Gender and Social Justice: Perspectives on Human Insecurity |publisher = Springer |author = Trương, Thanh-Đạm |year = 2013 |pages = 3–26 |isbn = 978-3-642-28012-2 }}</ref><ref name="We Cannot Clap">{{cite journal |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8bERZaWVUVGRPLTA |title = We Cannot Clap with One Hand: Global Socio–Political Differences in Social Support for People with Visual Impairment |author = Teklu, Abebe Abay |journal = International Journal of Ethiopian Studies |year = 2010 |volume = 5 |issue = 1 |pages = 93–105 }}</ref>
While concepts of social justice can be found in classical and Christian philosophical sources, from Plato and Aristotle to Augustine of Hippo and Thomas Aquinas, the term ''social justice'' finds its earliest uses in the late 18th century, albeit with unclear theoretical or practical meanings.<ref>J. Zajda, S. Majhanovich, V. Rust, ''Education and Social Justice'', 2006, [[ISBN (identifier)|ISBN]] [[Special:BookSources/1-4020-4721-5|1-4020-4721-5]]</ref><ref>Clark, Mary T. (2015). ''"Augustine on Justice," a Chapter in Augustine and Social Justice''. Lexington Books. pp. 3–10. [[ISBN (identifier)|ISBN]] [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4985-0918-3|<bdi>978-1-4985-0918-3</bdi>]].</ref><ref>Paine, Thomas. ''Agrarian Justice''. Printed by R. Folwell, for Benjamin Franklin Bache.</ref> The use of the term was early on subject to accusations of redundancy and of rhetorical flourish, perhaps but not necessarily related to amplifying one view of distributive justice.<ref name=":1">Behr, Thomas. ''Social Justice and Subsidiarity: Luigi Taparelli and the Origins of Modern Catholic Social Thought'' (Washington DC: Catholic University of American Press, December 2019).</ref> In the coining and definition of the term in the natural law social scientific treatise of Luigi Taparelli, SJ, in the early 1840s,<ref>Luigi Taparelli, SJ, ''Saggio teoretico di dritto naturale appogiato sul fatto'' (Palermo: Antonio Muratori, 1840-43), Sections 341-364.</ref> Taparelli established the natural law principle that corresponded to the evangelical principle of brotherly love—i.e. social justice reflects the duty one has to one’s other self in the interdependent abstract unity of the human person in society.<ref>Behr, Thomas. ''Social Justice and Subsidiarity: Luigi Taparelli and the Origins of Modern Catholic Social Thought''(Washington DC: Catholic University of American Press, December 2019), pp. 149-154.</ref> After the Revolutions of 1848 the term was popularized generically through the writings of Antonio Rosmini-Serbati.<ref>Rosmini-Serbati, ''The Constitution under Social Justice.'' trans. A. Mingardi (Lanham: Lexington Books, 2007).</ref><ref>Pérez-Garzón, Carlos Andrés (14 January 2018). "Unveiling the Meaning of Social Justice in Colombia". ''Mexican Law Review''. '''10''' (2): 27–66. [[ISSN (identifier)|ISSN]] 2448-5306. Archived from the original on 29 March 2018. Retrieved 28 March 2018.</ref>
In the late industrial revolution, [[Progressive Era]] American legal scholars began to use the term more, particularly [[Louis Brandeis]] and [[Roscoe Pound]]. From the early 20th century it was also embedded in [[international law]] and institutions; the preamble to establish the [[International Labour Organization]] recalled that "universal and lasting peace can be established only if it is based upon social justice." In the later 20th century, social justice was made central to the philosophy of the [[social contract]], primarily by [[John Rawls]] in ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'' (1971). In 1993, the [[Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action]] treats social justice as a purpose of [[human rights education]].<ref>[[s:Constitution of the International Labour Organization|The Preamble of ILO Constitution]]</ref><ref>Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, Part II, D.</ref>
== History ==
{{Main|Social contract|Justice|Corrective justice|Distributive justice}}
[[File:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|upright|An artist's rendering of what Plato might have looked like. From Raphael's early 16th century painting "''Scuola di Atene"''.]]
The different concepts of [[justice]], as discussed in ancient [[Western philosophy]], were typically centered upon the community.
[[File:Aristotle Altemps Inv8575.jpg|thumb|upright|Roman copy in marble of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by Lysippos, c. 330 BC. The alabaster mantle is modern.]]
* [[Plato]] wrote in ''[[The Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]'' that it would be an ideal state that "every member of the community must be assigned to the class for which he finds himself best fitted."<ref>[[Plato]], ''[[The Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]'' (ca 380BC)</ref> In an article for J.N.V University, author D.R. Bhandari says, "Justice is, for Plato, at once a part of human virtue and the bond, which joins man together in society. It is the identical quality that makes good and social. Justice is an order and duty of the parts of the soul, it is to the soul as health is to the body. Plato says that justice is not mere strength, but it is a harmonious strength. Justice is not the right of the stronger but the effective harmony of the whole. All moral conceptions revolve about the good of the whole-individual as well as social".<ref name="bu.edu">{{cite web |url=https://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciBhan.htm |title = 20th WCP: Plato's Concept of Justice: An Analysis |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20161005111127/http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciBhan.htm |archive-date = 5 October 2016}}</ref>
* Plato believed rights existed only between free people, and the law should take "account in the first instance of relations of inequality in which individuals are treated in proportion to their worth and only secondarily of relations of equality." Reflecting this time when [[slavery]] and subjugation of women was typical, ancient views of justice tended to reflect the rigid class systems that still prevailed. On the other hand, for the privileged groups, strong concepts of fairness and the community existed. [[Distributive justice]] was said by [[Aristotle]] to require that people were distributed goods and assets according to their merit.<ref>''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' V.3</ref>
[[File:Head of Socrates in Palazzo Massimo alle Terme (Rome).JPG|thumb|upright|Bust of Socrates]]
* [[Socrates]] (through Plato's dialogue ''[[Crito]]'') is credited with developing the idea of a [[social contract]], whereby people ought to follow the rules of a society, and accept its burdens because they have accepted its benefits.<ref>[[Plato]], ''[[Crito]]'' (ca 380 BC)</ref> During the Middle Ages, religious scholars particularly, such as [[Thomas Aquinas]] continued discussion of justice in various ways, but ultimately connected being a good citizen to the purpose of serving God.
After the [[Renaissance]] and [[Reformation]], the modern concept of social justice, as developing human potential, began to emerge through the work of a series of authors. [[Baruch Spinoza]] in ''[[On the Improvement of the Understanding]]'' (1677) contended that the one true aim of life should be to acquire "a human character much more stable than [one's] own", and to achieve this "pitch of perfection... The chief good is that he should arrive, together with other individuals if possible, at the possession of the aforesaid character."<ref>B Spinoza, ''[[On the Improvement of the Understanding]]'' (1677) [[s:On the Improvement of the Understanding#12|para 13]]</ref> During the [[Age of Enlightenment|enlightenment]] and responding to the [[French Revolution|French]] and [[American Revolution]]s, [[Thomas Paine]] similarly wrote in ''[[The Rights of Man]]'' (1792) society should give "genius a fair and universal chance" and so "the construction of government ought to be such as to bring forward... all that extent of capacity which never fails to appear in revolutions."<ref>[[T Paine]], ''[[Rights of Man]]'' (1792) 197</ref>
[[File:Fr. Luigi Taparelli.jpg|thumb|''Social justice'' has been traditionally credited to be coined by [[Jesuit]] priest [[Luigi Taparelli]] in the 1840s, but the expression is older]]
Although there is no certainty about the first use of the term "social justice", early sources can be found in Europe in the 18th century.<ref name="pérez27">{{Cite journal|last=Pérez-Garzón|first=Carlos Andrés|date=2018-01-14|title=Unveiling the Meaning of Social Justice in Colombia|url=https://revistas.juridicas.unam.mx/index.php/mexican-law-review/article/view/11892|journal=Mexican Law Review|language=en-US|volume=10|issue=2|pages=27–66|issn=2448-5306|access-date=28 March 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180329054435/https://revistas.juridicas.unam.mx/index.php/mexican-law-review/article/view/11892|archive-date=29 March 2018|url-status=dead}}</ref> Some references to the use of the expression are in articles of journals aligned with the spirit of the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]], in which social justice is described as an obligation of the monarch;<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TnMLHOwjqgMC&q=%22justice+sociale%22&pg=PA311|title=Journal encyclopédique... [Ed. Pierre Rousseau]|last=Rousseau|date=1774|publisher=De l'Imprimerie du Journal|language=fr}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xzATAAAAYAAJ&q=justice+sociale&pg=PA131|title=L'Esprit des journaux, françois et étrangers|date=1784|publisher=Valade|language=fr}}</ref> also the term is present in books written by Catholic Italian theologians, notably members of the [[Society of Jesus]].<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=AEBbAAAAcAAJ&q=%22giustizia+sociale%22&pg=PA349|title=L'Episcopato ossia della Potesta di governar la chiesa. Dissertazione|date=1789|publisher=na|language=it}}</ref> Thus, according to this sources and the context, social justice was another term for "the justice of society", the justice that rules the relations among individuals in society, without any mention to socio-economic equity or human dignity.<ref name="pérez27"/>
The usage of the term started to become more frequent by Catholic thinkers from the 1840s, beginning with the [[Jesuit]] [[Luigi Taparelli]] in ''Civiltà Cattolica'', and based on the work of St. [[Thomas Aquinas]]. Taparelli argued that rival [[capitalism|capitalist]] and [[socialist]] theories, based on subjective [[René Descartes|Cartesian]] thinking, undermined the unity of society present in [[Thomism|Thomistic]] [[metaphysics]] as neither were sufficiently concerned with ethics.<ref name=":1" /> Writing in 1861, the influential British philosopher and economist, [[John Stuart Mill]] stated in ''[[Utilitarianism]]'' his view that "Society should treat all equally well who have deserved equally well of it, that is, who have deserved equally well absolutely. This is the highest abstract standard of social and distributive justice; towards which all institutions, and the efforts of all virtuous citizens, should be made in the utmost degree to converge."<ref>[[JS Mill]], ''[[Utilitarianism (book)|Utilitarianism]]'' (1863)</ref>
In the later 19th and early 20th century, social justice became an important theme in American political and legal philosophy, particularly in the work of [[John Dewey]], [[Roscoe Pound]] and [[Louis Brandeis]]. One of the prime concerns was the ''[[Lochner era]]'' decisions of the [[US Supreme Court]] to strike down legislation passed by state governments and the Federal government for social and economic improvement, such as the [[eight-hour day]] or the right to join a [[trade union]]. After the First World War, the founding document of the [[International Labour Organization]] took up the same terminology in its preamble, stating that "peace can be established only if it is based on social justice". From this point, the discussion of social justice entered into mainstream legal and academic discourse.
In 1931, the [[Pope Pius XI]] explicitly referred to the expression, along with the concept of [[subsidiarity]], for the first time in [[Catholic social teaching]] in the encyclical ''[[Quadragesimo anno]]''. Then again in ''[[Divini Redemptoris]]'', the church pointed out that the realization of social justice relied on the promotion of the [[human dignity|dignity of human person]].<ref>{{cite web|url=https://w2.vatican.va/content/pius-xi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_enc_19370319_divini-redemptoris.html|title=Divini Redemptoris (March 19, 1937) {{!}} PIUS XI|website=w2.vatican.va|access-date=2018-03-28}}</ref> During the 1930s, the term was widely associated with pro-[[Nazi]] and [[antisemitic]] groups, such as the [[Christian Front (United States)|Christian Front]].<ref>{{cite magazine |title=The Press: Crackdown on Coughlin |url=http://content.time.com/time/subscriber/article/0,33009,795777,00.html |magazine=Time |access-date=24 February 2022 |date=27 April 1942}}</ref> Social Justice was the slogan of [[Charles Coughlin]], and the name of his [[Social Justice (periodical)|newspaper]]. Because of the documented influence of ''Divini Redemptoris'' in its drafters,<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Moyn|first=Samuel|date=2014|title=The Secret History of Constitutional Dignity|url=http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yhrdlj/vol17/iss1/2/|journal=Yale Human Rights and Development Journal|language=en|volume=17|issue=1|issn=1548-2596}}</ref> the [[Constitution of Ireland]] was the first one to establish the term as a principle of the economy in the State, and then other countries around the world did the same throughout the 20th century, even in [[socialist]] regimes such as the [[Constitution of Cuba|Cuban Constitution]] in 1976.<ref name="pérez27"/>
In the late 20th century, several liberal and conservative thinkers, notably [[Friedrich Hayek]] rejected the concept by stating that it did not mean anything, or meant too many things.<ref>[[FA Hayek]], ''[[Law, Legislation and Liberty]]'' (1973) vol II, ch 3</ref> However the concept remained highly influential, particularly with its promotion by philosophers such as [[John Rawls]]. Even though the meaning of social justice varies, at least three common elements can be identified in the contemporary theories about it: a duty of the State to [[Distributive justice|distribute]] certain vital means (such as [[Economic, social and cultural rights|economic, social, and cultural rights]]), the protection of [[human dignity]], and [[affirmative action]]s to promote [[Equal opportunity|equal opportunities]] for everybody.<ref name="pérez27"/>
== Contemporary theory ==
=== Philosophical perspectives ===
==== Cosmic values ====
[[Hunter Lewis]]' work promoting natural healthcare and sustainable economies advocates for [[Conservation (ethic)|conservation]] as a key premise in social justice. His manifesto on [[sustainability]] ties the continued thriving of human life to real conditions, the environment supporting that life, and associates injustice with the detrimental effects of [[unintended consequences]] of human actions. Quoting classical Greek thinkers like [[Epicurus]] on the good of pursuing happiness, Hunter also cites ornithologist, naturalist, and philosopher [[Alexander Skutch]] in his book Moral Foundations:
{{blockquote|The common feature which unites the activities most consistently forbidden by the moral codes of civilized peoples is that by their very nature they cannot be both habitual and enduring, because they tend to destroy the conditions which make them possible.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.anh-usa.org/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Sustainability-the-Complete-Concept1.pdf |author = Hunter Lewis |title = Sustainability, The Complete Concept, Environment, Healthcare, and Economy |date = 14 October 2009 |publisher = ChangeThis |access-date = 23 January 2011 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304090801/http://www.anh-usa.org/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Sustainability-the-Complete-Concept1.pdf |archive-date = 4 March 2016 |url-status=dead }}</ref>}}
Pope Benedict XVI cites [[Teilhard de Chardin]] in a vision of the cosmos as a 'living host'<ref>{{cite news |url=http://ncronline.org/news/ecology/pope-cites-teilhardian-vision-cosmos-living-host |author = John Allen Jr. |title = Ecology – The first stirring of an 'evolutionary leap' in late Jesuit's official standing? |date = 28 July 2009 |newspaper = National Catholic Reporter |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120824050226/http://ncronline.org/news/ecology/pope-cites-teilhardian-vision-cosmos-living-host |archive-date = 24 August 2012}}</ref> embracing an understanding of ecology that includes humanity's relationship to others, that pollution affects not just the natural world but interpersonal relations as well. Cosmic harmony, justice and peace are closely interrelated:
{{blockquote|If you want to cultivate peace, protect creation.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://chiesa.espresso.repubblica.it/articolo/1341681?eng=y/ |author = Sandro Magister |title = Benedict XVI to the Diplomats: Three Levers for Lifting Up the World |date = 11 January 2010 |publisher = chiesa, Rome |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304083309/http://chiesa.espresso.repubblica.it/articolo/1341681?eng=y%2F |archive-date = 4 March 2016}}</ref>}}
In ''The Quest for Cosmic Justice'', [[Thomas Sowell]] writes that seeking utopia, while admirable, may have disastrous effects if done without strong consideration of the economic underpinnings that support contemporary society.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Sowell |first1=Thomas |title=The quest for cosmic justice |publisher=Simon & Schuster |isbn=0684864630 |edition=1st Touchstone|date=5 February 2002 }}</ref>
==== John Rawls ====
{{Main|John Rawls}}
Political philosopher [[John Rawls]] draws on the [[utilitarian]] insights of [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]] and [[John Stuart Mill|Mill]], the [[social contract]] ideas of [[John Locke]], and the [[categorical imperative]] ideas of [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]]. His first statement of principle was made in ''A Theory of Justice'' where he proposed that, "Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override. For this reason justice denies that the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good shared by others."<ref>John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (2005 reissue), Chapter 1, "Justice as Fairness" – 1. The Role of Justice, pp. 3–4</ref> A [[deontological]] proposition that echoes Kant in framing the moral good of justice in [[Moral absolutism|absolutist]] terms. His views are definitively restated in ''[[Political Liberalism]]'' where society is seen "as a fair system of co-operation over time, from one generation to the next".<ref>John Rawls, ''Political Liberalism'' 15 (Columbia University Press 2003)</ref>
All societies have a basic structure of social, economic, and political institutions, both formal and informal. In testing how well these elements fit and work together, Rawls based a key test of legitimacy on the theories of social contract. To determine whether any particular system of collectively enforced social arrangements is legitimate, he argued that one must look for agreement by the people who are subject to it, but not necessarily to an objective notion of justice based on coherent ideological grounding. Obviously, not every citizen can be asked to participate in a poll to determine his or her consent to every proposal in which some degree of coercion is involved, so one has to assume that all citizens are reasonable. Rawls constructed an argument for a two-stage process to determine a citizen's hypothetical agreement:
* The citizen agrees to be represented by X for certain purposes, and, to that extent, X holds these powers as a [[trustee]] for the citizen.
* X agrees that enforcement in a particular social context is legitimate. The citizen, therefore, is bound by this decision because it is the function of the trustee to represent the citizen in this way.
This applies to one person who represents a small group (e.g., the organiser of a social event setting a dress code) as equally as it does to national governments, which are ultimate trustees, holding representative powers for the benefit of all citizens within their territorial boundaries. Governments that fail to provide for [[social welfare|welfare]] of their citizens according to the principles of justice are not legitimate. To emphasise the general principle that justice should rise from the people and not be dictated by the law-making powers of governments, Rawls asserted that, "There is ... a general presumption against imposing legal and other restrictions on conduct without sufficient reason. But this presumption creates no special priority for any particular liberty."<ref>John Rawls, Political Liberalism 291–92 (Columbia University Press 2003)</ref> This is support for an unranked set of liberties that reasonable citizens in all states should respect and uphold — to some extent, the list proposed by Rawls matches the normative human rights that have international recognition and direct enforcement in some nation states where the citizens need encouragement to act in a way that fixes a greater degree of equality of outcome. According to Rawls, the basic liberties that every good society should guarantee are:
* [[Freedom of thought]];
* Liberty of conscience as it affects social relationships on the grounds of religion, philosophy, and morality;
* Political liberties (e.g., representative democratic institutions, [[freedom of speech]] and the [[freedom of the press|press]], and [[freedom of assembly]]);
* [[Freedom of association]];
* Freedoms necessary for the liberty and integrity of the person (namely: freedom from slavery, freedom of movement and a reasonable degree of freedom to choose one's occupation); and
* Rights and liberties covered by the [[rule of law]].
==== Thomas Pogge ====
[[File:2014-01-08 Thomas Pogge 4737-cropped.JPG|thumb|upright|[[Thomas Pogge]]]]
[[Thomas Pogge]]'s arguments pertain to a standard of social justice that creates [[human rights defender|human rights deficits]]. He assigns responsibility to those who actively cooperate in designing or imposing the social institution, that the order is foreseeable as harming the global poor and is reasonably avoidable. Pogge argues that social institutions have a [[negative duty]] to not harm the poor.<ref>{{cite web |last1 = James |first1 = Nickel |title = Human Rights |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ |website = stanford.edu |publisher = The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date = 10 February 2015 }}</ref><ref>{{cite web |last1 = Pogge |first1 = Thomas Pogge |title = World Poverty and Human Rights |url=http://thomaspogge.com/books/world-poverty-human-rights/ |website = thomaspogge.com |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150919070037/http://thomaspogge.com/books/world-poverty-human-rights/ |archive-date = 19 September 2015}}</ref>
Pogge speaks of "institutional cosmopolitanism" and assigns responsibility to institutional schemes<ref>{{cite journal |last1 = North |first1 = James |title = The Resource Privilege |url=http://www.thenation.com/article/181724/resource-privilege# |journal = The Nation |access-date = 10 February 2015 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150210065716/http://www.thenation.com/article/181724/resource-privilege |archive-date = 10 February 2015|date = 23 September 2014 }}</ref> for deficits of human rights. An example given is slavery and third parties. A third party should not recognize or enforce slavery. The institutional order should be held responsible only for deprivations of human rights that it establishes or authorizes. The current institutional design, he says, systematically harms developing economies by enabling corporate tax evasion,<ref>{{cite web |last1 = Pogge |first1 = Thomas |title = Human Rights and Just Taxation – Global Financial Transparency |url=http://thomaspogge.com/human-rights-and-just-taxation-global-financial-transparency/ |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150210074345/http://thomaspogge.com/human-rights-and-just-taxation-global-financial-transparency/ |archive-date = 10 February 2015}}</ref> illicit financial flows, corruption, trafficking of people and weapons. [[Joshua Cohen (philosopher)|Joshua Cohen]] disputes his claims based on the fact that some poor countries have done well with the current institutional design.<ref>{{cite book |editor1 = Alison M. Jaggar1 by |title = Thomas Pogge and His Critics. |date = 2010 |publisher = Polity Press |location = Cambridge |isbn = 978-0-7456-4258-1 |edition = 1. publ. }}</ref> Elizabeth Kahn argues that some of these responsibilities{{vague|date=April 2017}} should apply globally.<ref>{{cite journal |last1 = Kahn |first1 = Elizabeth |title = Global Economic Justice: A Structural Approach |journal = Public Reason |date = June–December 2012 |volume = 4 |issue = 1–2 |pages = 48–67 }}</ref>
==== United Nations ====
The United Nations calls social justice "an underlying principle for peaceful and prosperous coexistence within and among nations.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.un.org/en/events/socialjusticeday/index.shtml|title=World Day of Social Justice, 20 February|website=www.un.org|language=EN|access-date=2019-11-08}}</ref>
The United Nations' 2006 document ''Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations'', states that "Social justice may be broadly understood as the fair and compassionate distribution of the fruits of economic growth{{nbsp}}..."<ref name="un">{{cite web |title = Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations", The International Forum for Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ESA/305 |publisher = United Nations |location = New York |year = 2006 |url=https://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170829123826/http://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf |archive-date = 29 August 2017}}</ref>{{rp|16}}
The term "social justice" was seen by the U.N. "as a substitute for the protection of human rights [and] first appeared in United Nations texts during the second half of the 1960s. At the initiative of the Soviet Union, and with the support of developing countries, the term was used in the Declaration on Social Progress and Development, adopted in 1969."<ref name="un" />{{rp|52}}
The same document reports, "From the comprehensive global perspective shaped by the United Nations Charter and the [[Universal Declaration of Human Rights]], neglect of the pursuit of social justice in all its dimensions translates into de facto acceptance of a future marred by violence, repression and chaos."<ref name="un" />{{rp|6}} The report concludes, "Social justice is not possible without strong and coherent [[redistribution of income and wealth|redistributive policies]] conceived and implemented by public agencies."<ref name="un" />{{rp|16}}
The same UN document offers a concise history: "[T]he notion of social justice is relatively new. None of history’s great philosophers—not Plato or Aristotle, or Confucius or Averroes, or even Rousseau or Kant—saw the need to consider justice or the redress of injustices from a social perspective. The concept first surfaced in Western thought and political language in the wake of the industrial revolution and the parallel development of the socialist doctrine. It emerged as an expression of protest against what was perceived as the capitalist [[exploitation of labor]] and as a focal point for the development of measures to improve the human condition. It was born as a revolutionary slogan embodying the ideals of progress and fraternity. Following the revolutions that shook Europe in the mid-1800s, social justice became a rallying cry for progressive thinkers and political activists.... By the mid-twentieth century, the concept of social justice had become central to the ideologies and programs of virtually all the leftist and centrist political parties around the world{{nbsp}}..."<ref name="un" />{{rp|11–12}}
Another key area of human rights and social justice is the United Nations's defense of children's rights worldwide. In 1989, the Convention on the Rights of the Child was adopted and available for signature, ratification and accession by General Assembly resolution 44/25.<ref name=":0">{{Cite web|title=OHCHR {{!}} Convention on the Rights of the Child|url=https://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/crc.aspx|access-date=2020-12-21|website=www.ohchr.org}}</ref> According to [[Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights|OHCHR]], this convention entered into force on 2 September 1990. This convention upholds that all states have the obligation to "protect the child from all forms of physical or mental violence, injury or abuse, neglect or negligent treatment, maltreatment or exploitation, including sexual abuse."<ref name=":0" />
== Religious perspectives ==
===Abrahamic religions===
==== Christianity ====
{{See also|Christian ethics|Christian democracy}}
===== Evangelicalism =====
''[[Time (magazine)|Time]]'' magazine noted that younger Evangelicals also increasingly engage in social justice.<ref>{{Cite magazine|last=Sullivan|first=Amy|date=2010-06-01|title=Young Evangelicals: Expanding Their Mission|language=en-US|magazine=Time|url=http://content.time.com/time/nation/article/0,8599,1992463-1,00.html|access-date=2020-10-08|issn=0040-781X}}</ref> John Stott traced the call for social justice back to the cross, "The cross is a revelation of God's justice as well as of his love. That is why the community of the cross should concern itself with social justice as well as with loving philanthropy."<ref>{{Cite book|last=Stott|first=John|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uSHC3qDjFS4C&pg=PA285|title=The Cross of Christ|date=2012-11-29|publisher=InterVarsity Press|isbn=978-0-8308-6636-6|pages=185|language=en}}</ref>
====== Methodism ======
From its founding, Methodism was a Christian social justice movement. Under [[John Wesley]]'s direction, Methodists became leaders in many social justice issues of the day, including the [[prison reform]] and [[abolitionism|abolition]] movements. Wesley himself was among the first to preach for slaves rights attracting significant opposition.<ref>S. R. Valentine, John Bennet & the Origins of Methodism and the Evangelical revival in England, Scarecrow Press, Lanham, 1997.</ref><ref>Carey, Brycchan. "John Wesley (1703–1791)." The British Abolitionists. Brycchan Carey, 11 July 2008. 5 October 2009. [http://www.brycchancarey.com/abolition/index.htm Brycchancarey.com] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160129112229/http://brycchancarey.com/abolition/index.htm |date=29 January 2016 }}</ref><ref>Wesley John, "Thoughts Upon Slavery," John Wesley: Holiness of Heart and Life. Charles Yrigoyen, 1996. 5 October 2009. [http://gbgm-umc.org/umw/wesley/thoughtsuponslavery.stm Gbgm-umc.org] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141016083225/http://gbgm-umc.org/umw/wesley/thoughtsuponslavery.stm |date=16 October 2014 }}</ref>
Today, social justice plays a major role in the [[United Methodist Church]] and the [[Free Methodist Church]].<ref>{{cite web |title=Do Justice |url=https://www.ffmc.org/do-justice |publisher=First Free Methodist Church |access-date=12 June 2021 |language=English}}</ref> The ''Book of Discipline of the United Methodist Church'' says, "We hold governments responsible for the protection of the rights of the people to free and fair elections and to the freedoms of speech, religion, assembly, communications media, and petition for redress of grievances without fear of reprisal; to the [[right to privacy]]; and to the guarantee of the rights to adequate food, clothing, shelter, education, and health care."<ref>The Book of Discipline of The United Methodist Church – 2012 ¶164 V, [http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467671¬oc=1 umc.org] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131206020517/http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467671¬oc=1 |date=6 December 2013 }}</ref> The United Methodist Church also teaches [[Human population control|population control]] as part of its doctrine.<ref>The Book of Discipline of The United Methodist Church – 2008 ¶ 162 K, [http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467635¬oc=1 umc.org] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131206012803/http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467635¬oc=1 |date=6 December 2013 }}</ref>
===== Catholicism =====
{{Main|Catholic social teaching}}
Catholic social teaching consists of those aspects of Roman Catholic doctrine which relate to matters dealing with the respect of the individual human life. A distinctive feature of Catholic social doctrine is its concern for the poorest and most vulnerable members of society. Two of the seven key areas<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/projects/socialteaching/excerpt.htm |title = Seven Key Themes of Catholic Social Teaching |access-date = 29 March 2014 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070608113958/http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/projects/socialteaching/excerpt.htm |archive-date = 8 June 2007 }}</ref> of "Catholic social teaching" are pertinent to social justice:
* Life and dignity of the human person: The foundational principle of all Catholic social teaching is the sanctity of all human life and the inherent dignity of every human person, from conception to natural death. Human life must be valued above all material possessions.
* Preferential option for the poor and [[social vulnerability|vulnerable]]: Catholics believe Jesus taught that on the [[Day of Judgement]] God will ask what each person did to help the poor and needy: "Amen, I say to you, whatever you did for one of these least brothers of mine, you did for me."<ref>[[Gospel of Matthew|Matthew]] 25:40.</ref> The Catholic Church believes that through words, prayers and deeds one must show solidarity with, and compassion for, the poor. The moral test of any society is "how it treats its most vulnerable members. The poor have the most urgent moral claim on the conscience of the nation. People are called to look at public policy decisions in terms of how they affect the poor."<ref>Option for the Poor, [http://www.osjspm.org/cst/themes.htm Major themes from Catholic Social Teaching] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060216183419/http://www.osjspm.org/cst/themes.htm |date=16 February 2006 }}, Office for Social Justice, Archdiocese of St. Paul and Minneapolis.</ref>
Modern Catholic social teaching is often thought to have begun with the encyclicals of Pope Leo XIII.<ref name=":1" />
* [[Pope Leo XIII]], who studied under Taparelli, published in 1891 the [[encyclical]] ''[[Rerum novarum]]'' (On the Condition of the Working Classes; lit. "On new things"), rejecting both [[socialism]] and [[capitalism]], while defending labor unions and private property. He stated that society should be based on cooperation and not [[class conflict]] and [[competition]]. In this document, Leo set out the Catholic Church's response to the social instability and labor conflict that had arisen in the wake of industrialization and had led to the rise of socialism. The Pope advocated that the role of the state was to promote social justice through the protection of rights, while the church must speak out on social issues to teach correct social principles and ensure class harmony.
* The encyclical ''[[Quadragesimo anno]]'' (On Reconstruction of the Social Order, literally "in the fortieth year") of 1931 by [[Pope Pius XI]], encourages a [[living wage]],<ref>Popularised by [[John A. Ryan]], although see [[Sidney Webb]] and [[Beatrice Webb]], ''[[Industrial Democracy]]'' (1897)</ref> [[subsidiarity (Catholicism)|subsidiarity]], and advocates that social justice is a personal virtue as well as an attribute of the social order, saying that society can be just only if individuals and institutions are just.
* [[Pope John Paul II]] added much to the corpus of the Catholic social teaching, penning three encyclicals which focus on issues such as economics, politics, geo-political situations, ownership of the means of production, private property and the "[[social mortgage]]", and private property. The encyclicals ''[[Laborem exercens]]'', ''[[Sollicitudo rei socialis]]'', and ''[[Centesimus annus]]'' are just a small portion of his overall contribution to Catholic social justice. Pope John Paul II was a strong advocate of justice and [[human rights]], and spoke forcefully for the poor. He addresses issues such as the problems that technology can present should it be misused, and admits a fear that the "progress" of the world is not true progress at all, if it should denigrate the value of the human person. He argued in ''[[Centesimus annus]]'' that private property, markets, and honest labor were the keys to alleviating the miseries of the poor and to enabling a life that can express the fullness of the human person.
* [[Pope Benedict XVI]]'s encyclical ''[[Deus caritas est]]'' ("God is Love") of 2006 claims that justice is the defining concern of the state and the central concern of politics, and not of the church, which has charity as its central social concern. It said that the laity has the specific responsibility of pursuing social justice in civil society and that the church's active role in social justice should be to inform the debate, using reason and natural law, and also by providing moral and spiritual formation for those involved in politics.
* The official Catholic doctrine on social justice can be found in the book ''Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church'', published in 2004 and updated in 2006, by the [[Pontifical Council for Justice and Peace|Pontifical Council ''Iustitia et Pax'']].
The ''Catechism of the Catholic Church'' (§§ 1928–1948) contains more detail of the church's view of social justice.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.vatican.va/archive/ccc_css/archive/catechism/p3s1c2a3.htm |title = Catechism of the Catholic Church – Social justice |publisher = Vatican.va |access-date = 29 March 2014 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131105063620/https://www.vatican.va/archive/ccc_css/archive/catechism/p3s1c2a3.htm |archive-date = 5 November 2013}}</ref>
==== Islam ====
In Muslim history, Islamic governance has often been associated with social justice.{{additional citation|date=April 2018}} Establishment of social justice was one of the motivating factors of the [[Umayyad#Insurrection|Abbasid revolt]] against the Umayyads.<ref>{{cite book |author = John L. Esposito |title = Islam and Politics |publisher = Syracuse University Press |year = 1998 |page = 17 |author-link = John L. Esposito }}</ref> The Shi'a believe that the return of the ''Mahdi'' will herald in "the messianic age of justice" and the Mahdi along with the Isa (Jesus) will end plunder, torture, oppression and discrimination.<ref>{{cite book |author = John L. Esposito |title = Islam and Politics |publisher = Syracuse University Press |year = 1998 |page = 205 |author-link = John L. Esposito }}</ref>
For the [[Muslim Brotherhood]] the implementation of social justice would require the rejection of [[consumerism]] and [[communism]]. The Brotherhood strongly affirmed the right to private property as well as differences in personal wealth due to factors such as hard work. However, the Brotherhood held Muslims had an obligation to assist those Muslims in need. It held that ''zakat'' (alms-giving) was not voluntary charity, but rather the poor had the right to assistance from the more fortunate.<ref>{{cite book |author = John L. Esposito |title = Islam and Politics |publisher = Syracuse University Press |year = 1998 |pages = 147–8 |author-link = John L. Esposito }}</ref> Most Islamic governments therefore enforce the ''zakat'' through taxes.
==== Judaism ====
{{Main|Tikkun olam}}
In ''To Heal a Fractured World: The Ethics of Responsibility'', Rabbi [[Jonathan Sacks]] states that social justice has a central place in [[Judaism]]. One of Judaism's most distinctive and challenging ideas is its [[ethics]] of responsibility reflected in the concepts of [[simcha]] ("gladness" or "joy"), [[tzedakah]] ("the religious obligation to perform charity and philanthropic acts"), [[chesed]] ("deeds of kindness"), and [[tikkun olam]] ("repairing the world").<ref>{{Cite book|last=Sacks|first=Jonathan|title=To Heal a Fractured World: The Ethics of Responsibility|publisher=Schocken|year=2005|isbn=9780826486226|location=New York|pages=3}}</ref>
===Eastern religions===
==== Hinduism ====
The present-day [[Jāti]] hierarchy is undergoing changes for a variety of reasons including 'social justice', which is a politically popular stance in democratic India. Institutionalized affirmative action has promoted this. The disparity and wide inequalities in social behaviour of the jātis – exclusive, endogamous communities centred on traditional occupations – has led to various [[Social reformers of India|reform movements]] in [[Hinduism]]. While legally outlawed, the caste system remains strong in practice.<ref>{{cite news |last1 = Patil |first1 = Vijaykumar |title = Caste system hindering the goal of social justice: Siddaramaiah |url=http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/karnataka/caste-system-hindering-the-goal-of-social-justice-cm/article6822818.ece |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150904050652/http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/karnataka/caste-system-hindering-the-goal-of-social-justice-cm/article6822818.ece |archive-date = 4 September 2015|newspaper = The Hindu |date = 26 January 2015 }}</ref>
==== Traditional Chinese religion ====
{{main|Mandate of Heaven}}
The Chinese concept of Tian Ming has occasionally been perceived{{by whom|date=May 2018}} as an expression of social justice.<ref>Lee Jen-der (2014), "Crime and Punishment: The Case of Liu Hui in the Wei Shu", ''Early Medieval China: A Sourcebook'', New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 156–165, {{ISBN|978-0-231-15987-6}}.</ref> Through it, the deposition of unfair rulers is justified in that civic dissatisfaction and economical disasters is perceived as [[Tian|Heaven]] withdrawing its favor from the Emperor. A successful rebellion is considered definite proof that the Emperor is unfit to rule.
== Social justice movements ==
{{liberalism sidebar}}
{{Progressivism}}
{{Social democracy sidebar}}
{{Labor|expanded=unions}}
Social justice is also a concept that is used to describe the movement towards a socially just world, e.g., the [[Global Justice Movement]]. In this context, social justice is based on the concepts of human rights and equality, and can be defined as ''"the way in which human rights are manifested in the everyday lives of people at every level of society"''.<ref>Just Comment – Volume 3 Number 1, 2000</ref>
Several [[social movement|movements]] are working to achieve social justice in society. These movements are working toward the realization of a world where all members of a society, regardless of background or procedural justice, have basic human rights and equal access to the benefits of their society.<ref>{{cite book |last1 = Capeheart |first1 = Loretta |first2 = Dragan |last2 = Milovanovic |title = Social Justice: Theories, Issues, and Movements |title-link = Social Justice: Theories, Issues, and Movements }}</ref>
=== Liberation theology ===
{{Main|Liberation theology}}
Liberation theology<ref>In the mass media, 'Liberation Theology' can sometimes be used loosely, to refer to a wide variety of activist Christian thought. This article uses the term in the narrow sense outlined here.</ref> is a movement in [[Christianity|Christian]] [[theology]] which conveys the teachings of [[Jesus Christ]] in terms of a liberation from unjust economic, political, or social conditions. It has been described by proponents as "an interpretation of Christian faith through the poor's suffering, their struggle and hope, and a critique of society and the Catholic faith and Christianity through the eyes of the poor",<ref>[[Phillip Berryman|Berryman, Phillip]], ''Liberation Theology: essential facts about the revolutionary movement in Latin America and beyond''(1987)</ref> and by detractors as Christianity perverted by [[Marxism]] and [[Communism]].<ref>"[David] Horowitz first describes liberation theology as 'a form of Marxised Christianity,' which has validity despite the awkward phrasing, but then he calls it a form of 'Marxist-Leninist ideology,' which is simply not true for most liberation theology{{nbsp}}..." Robert Shaffer, "[http://www.oah.org/pubs/nl/2007nov/shaffer.html Acceptable Bounds of Academic Discourse] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130904165644/http://www.oah.org/pubs/nl/2007nov/shaffer.html |date=4 September 2013 }}," Organization of American Historians Newsletter 35, November 2007. URL retrieved 12 July 2010.</ref>
Although liberation theology has grown into an international and inter-denominational movement, it began as a movement within the [[Catholic Church]] in Latin America in the 1950s–1960s. It arose principally as a moral reaction to the poverty caused by social injustice in that region.<ref name=Williams>''Liberation Theology and Its Role in Latin America''. Elisabeth Erin Williams. Monitor: Journal of International Studies. The College of William and Mary.</ref> It achieved prominence in the 1970s and 1980s. The term was coined by the [[Peruvian]] priest, [[Gustavo Gutiérrez]], who wrote one of the movement's most famous books, ''A Theology of Liberation'' (1971). According to [[Sarah Kleeb]], "Marx would surely take issue," she writes, "with the appropriation of his works in a religious context...there is no way to reconcile Marx's views of religion with those of Gutierrez, they are simply incompatible. Despite this, in terms of their understanding of the necessity of a just and righteous world, and the nearly inevitable obstructions along such a path, the two have much in common; and, particularly in the first edition of [A Theology of Liberation], the use of Marxian theory is quite evident."<ref>Sarah Kleeb, "[https://www.academia.edu/172232/Envisioning_Emancipation_Karl_Marx_Gustavo_Gutierrez_and_the_Struggle_of_Liberation_Theology Envisioning Emancipation: Karl Marx, Gustavo Gutierrez, and the Struggle of Liberation Theology]{{dead link|date=November 2017 |bot=Checkingfax |fix-attempted=yes }}"; Presented at the Annual Meeting of the Canadian Society for the Study of Religion (CSSR), Toronto, 2006. Retrieved 22 October 2012. {{dead link|date=December 2012}}</ref>
Other noted exponents are [[Leonardo Boff]] of Brazil, [[Carlos Mugica]] of Argentina, [[Jon Sobrino]] of El Salvador, and [[Juan Luis Segundo]] of Uruguay.<ref>Richard P. McBrien, ''Catholicism'' (Harper Collins, 1994), chapter IV.</ref><ref>Gustavo Gutierrez, ''A Theology of Liberation'', First (Spanish) edition published in Lima, Peru, 1971; first English edition published by Orbis Books (Maryknoll, New York), 1973.</ref>
=== Health care ===
Social justice has more recently made its way into the field of [[bioethics]]. Discussion involves topics such as affordable access to health care, especially for low income households and families. The discussion also raises questions such as whether society should bear healthcare costs for low income families, and whether the global marketplace is the best way to distribute healthcare. [[Ruth Faden]] of the [[Johns Hopkins Berman Institute of Bioethics]] and Madison Powers of Georgetown University focus their analysis of social justice on which inequalities matter the most. They develop a social justice theory that answers some of these questions in concrete settings.
Social injustices occur when there is a preventable difference in health states among a population of people. These social injustices take the form of [[health inequities]] when negative health states such as malnourishment, and infectious diseases are more prevalent in impoverished nations.<ref>Farmer, Paul E., Bruce Nizeye, Sara Stulac, and Salmaan Keshavjee. 2006. Structural Violence and Clinical Medicine. PLoS Medicine, 1686–1691</ref> These negative health states can often be prevented by providing social and economic structures such as primary healthcare which ensures the general population has equal access to health care services regardless of income level, gender, education or any other stratifying factors. Integrating social justice with health inherently reflects the social determinants of health model without discounting the role of the bio-medical model.<ref>Cueto, Marcos. 2004. The ORIGINS of Primary Health Care and SELECTIVE Primary Health Care. Am J Public Health 94 (11):1868</ref>
=== Health inequalities ===
The sources of health inequalities are rooted in injustices associated with racism, sex discrimination, and social class. Richard Hofrichter and his colleagues examine the political implications of various perspectives used to explain health inequities and explore alternative strategies for eliminating them.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Hofrichter, Richard (Editor)|title=Health and social justice: Politics, ideology, and inequity in the distribution of disease|publisher=Jossey-Bass|year=2003|isbn=9780787967338|location=San Francisco, CA|pages=}}</ref>
=== Human rights education ===
{{Main|Human rights education}}
The [[Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action]] affirm that "Human rights education should include peace, democracy, development and social justice, as set forth in [[international human rights instruments|international and regional human rights instruments]], to achieve common understanding and awareness to strengthen universal commitment to human rights."<ref>Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, Part II, paragraph 80</ref>
=== Ecology and environment ===
{{Main|Climate justice|environmental justice}}
Social justice principles are embedded in the larger environmental movement. The third principle of the Earth Charter is social and economic justice, which is described as seeking to eradicate poverty as an ethical, social, and environmental imperative, ensure that economic activities and institutions at all levels promote human development in an equitable and sustainable manner, affirm gender equality and equity as prerequisites to sustainable development and ensure universal access to education, health care, and economic opportunity, and uphold the right of all, without discrimination, to a natural and social environment supportive of human dignity, bodily health, and spiritual well-being, with special attention to the rights of indigenous peoples and minorities.
The [[climate justice]] and [[environmental justice]] movements also incorporate social justice principles, ideas, and practices. Climate justice and environmental justice, as movements within the larger ecological and environmental movement, each incorporate social justice in a particular way. Climate justice includes concern for social justice pertaining to greenhouse gas emissions,<ref>EA Posner and CR Sunstein [http://www.ericposner.com/GWSJ.pdf Global Warming and Social Justice]</ref> climate-induced environmental displacement,<ref>JS Mastaler [https://www.liebertpub.com/doi/full/10.1089/env.2018.0029 Social Justice and Environmental Displacement]</ref> as well as climate change mitigation and adaptation. Environmental justice includes concern for social justice pertaining to either environmental benefits<ref>A Dahlberg, R Rohde, K Sandell (2010) [http://www.conservationandsociety.org/article.asp?issn=0972-4923;year=2010;volume=8;issue=3;spage=209;epage=224;aulast=Dahlberg National Parks and Environmental Justice: Comparing Access Rights and Ideological Legacies in Three Countries] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190301013315/http://www.conservationandsociety.org/article.asp?issn=0972-4923;year=2010;volume=8;issue=3;spage=209;epage=224;aulast=Dahlberg |date=1 March 2019 }} 8, no. 3 pp.209-224</ref> or environmental pollution<ref>RD Bullard (2005) ''The Quest for Environmental Justice: Human Rights and the Politics of Pollution'' (Counterpoint) {{ISBN|978-1578051205}}</ref> based on their equitable distribution across communities of color, communities of various socio and economic stratification, or any other barriers to justice.
== Criticism ==
[[Michael Novak]] argues that social justice has seldom been adequately defined, arguing:
{{blockquote|[W]hole books and treatises have been written about social justice without ever defining it. It is allowed to float in the air as if everyone will recognize an instance of it when it appears. This vagueness seems indispensable. The minute one begins to define social justice, one runs into embarrassing intellectual difficulties. It becomes, most often, a term of art whose operational meaning is, "We need a law against that." In other words, it becomes an instrument of ideological intimidation, for the purpose of gaining the power of legal coercion.<ref name="Novak, Michael 2000">Novak, Michael. "Defining social justice." First things (2000): 11-12.</ref>}}
[[Friedrich Hayek]] of the [[Austrian School]] of economics rejected the very idea of social justice as meaningless, self-contradictory, and ideological, believing that to realize any degree of social justice is unfeasible, and that the attempt to do so must destroy all liberty:
{{blockquote|There can be no test by which we can discover what is 'socially unjust' because there is no subject by which such an injustice can be committed, and there are no rules of individual conduct the observance of which in the market order would secure to the individuals and groups the position which as such (as distinguished from the procedure by which it is determined) would appear just to us. [Social justice] does not belong to the category of error but to that of nonsense, like the term 'a moral stone'.<ref>Hayek, F.A. (1982). ''Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 2''. Routledge. p. 78.</ref>}}
Hayek argued that proponents of social justice often present it as a moral virtue but most of their descriptions pertain to impersonal states of affairs (e.g. income inequality, poverty), which are cited as "social injustice." Hayek argued that social justice is either a virtue or it is not. If it is, it can only be ascribed to the actions of individuals. However, most who use the term ascribe it to social systems, so "social justice" in fact describes a regulative principle of order; they are interested not in virtue but power.<ref name="Novak, Michael 2000"/> For Hayek, this notion of social justices presupposes that people are guided by specific external directions rather than internal, personal rules of just conduct. It further presupposes that one can never be held accountable for ones own behaviour, as this would be "blaming the victim." According to Hayek, the function of social justice is to blame someone else, often attributed to "the system" or those who are supposed, mythically, to control it. Thus it is based on the appealing idea of "you suffer; your suffering is caused by powerful others; these oppressors must be destroyed."<ref name="Novak, Michael 2000"/>
Ben O'Neill of the [[University of New South Wales]] and the [[Mises Institute]] argues:
{{blockquote|[For advocates of "social justice"] the notion of "rights" is a mere term of entitlement, indicative of a claim for any possible desirable good, no matter how important or trivial, abstract or tangible, recent or ancient. It is merely an assertion of desire, and a declaration of intention to use the language of rights to acquire said desire.
In fact, since the program of social justice inevitably involves claims for government provision of goods, paid for through the efforts of others, the term actually refers to an intention to use ''force'' to acquire one's desires. Not to earn desirable goods by rational thought and action, production and voluntary exchange, but to go in there and forcibly take goods from those who can supply them!<ref>O'Neill, Ben (16 March 2011) [https://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice The Injustice of Social Justice] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141028092912/http://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice |date=28 October 2014 }}, ''[[Mises Institute]]''</ref>}}
== See also ==
{{cols|colwidth=16em}}
* [[Activism]]
* "[[Beyond Vietnam: A Time to Break Silence]]", one of many [[Sermons and speeches of Martin Luther King Jr.|pro–social justice speeches]] delivered by [[Martin Luther King Jr.]]
* [[Choosing the Common Good]]
* [[Counterculture of the 1960s]]
* [[Economic justice]]
* [[Education for Justice]]
* [[Environmental racism]]
* [[Essentially contested concept]]
* [[Global justice]]
* [[Labour law]] and [[labour rights]]
* [[Left-wing politics]]
* [[Resource justice]]
* [[Right to education]]
* [[Right to health]]
* [[Right to housing]]
* [[Right to social security]]
* [[Social justice art]]
* [[Social justice warrior]]
* [[Social law]]
* [[Social work]]
* [[Solidarity]]
* [[National Union for Social Justice (organization)]]
* [[World Day of Social Justice]]
{{colend}}
* {{Lookfrom}}
* {{in title}}
== References ==
{{reflist}}
== Further reading ==
{{wikiquote}}
{{Library resources box}}
=== Articles ===
* C Pérez-Garzón, '[https://revistas.uexternado.edu.co/index.php/derest/article/view/5907/7607 What is social justice? A new history of its meaning in the transnational legal discourse]' (2019) 43 Revista Derecho del Estado 67-106, originally in Spanish: '[https://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/revderest43&div=1&src=home ¿Qué es justicia social? Una nueva historia de su significado en el discurso jurídico transnacional]'
*[[LD Brandeis]], 'The Living Law' (1915–1916) 10 Illinois Law Review 461
* A Etzioni, '[http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/etzioni/documents/A348-TheFairSociety.pdf The Fair Society, Uniting America: Restoring the Vital Center to American Democracy] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150924041156/http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/etzioni/documents/A348-TheFairSociety.pdf |date=24 September 2015 }}' in N Garfinkle and D Yankelovich (eds) (Yale University Press 2005) pp. 211–223
* [[Otto von Gierke]], ''[https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2861875 The Social Role of Private Law]'' (2016) translated and introduced by E McGaughey, originally in German ''[[Die soziale Aufgabe des Privatrechts]]''
* M Novak, '[https://www.firstthings.com/article/2000/12/defining-social-justice Defining Social Justice]' (2000) First Things
* B O'Neill, '[https://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice The Injustice of Social Justice]' ([[Mises Institute]])
* [[R Pound]], 'Social Justice and Legal Justice' (1912) 75 Central Law Journal 455
* M Powers and R Faden, '[https://courses.edx.org/c4x/GeorgetownX/phlx101-01/asset/10.2powers_faden.pdf Inequalities in health, inequalities in health care: four generations of discussion about justice and cost-effectiveness analysis]' (2000) 10(2) Kennedy Inst Ethics Journal 109–127
* M Powers and R Faden, 'Racial and Ethnic Disparities in Health Care: An Ethical Analysis of When and How They Matter,' in ''Unequal Treatment: Confronting Racial and Ethnic Disparities in Health Care'' (National Academy of Sciences, Institute of Medicine, 2002) 722–38
* United Nations, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, 'Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations' (2006) [https://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf ST/ESA/305]
=== Books ===
* [[AB Atkinson]], ''Social Justice and Public Policy'' (1982) [https://books.google.com/books?lr=&id=UiZ2HdkNHBAC&oi=fnd&pg=PP11&dq=%22Social+Justice+and+Public+Policy%22&ots=-6iPmku71A&sig=yACP-Kt6h174KR5dh3lsPDfGX64#PPP1,M1 previews]
* [[Gad Barzilai]], ''Communities and Law: Politics and Cultures of Legal Identities'' (University of Michigan Press) analysis of justice for non-ruling communities
* [[Thomas Nixon Carver|TN Carver]], ''Essays in Social Justice'' (1915) Chapter [https://archive.org/details/essaysinsocialj01carvgoog/page/n17 <!-- pg=3 quote=zDo9sLfoyZ. --> links.]
* [[Carroll Quigley|C Quigley]] ''The Evolution of Civilizations: An Introduction to Historical Analysis'' (1961) 2nd edition 1979
* P Corning, ''[http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/fairness-and-the-social-contract.php The Fair Society: The Science of Human Nature and the Pursuit of Social Justice]'' (Chicago UP 2011)
* WL Droel ''What is Social Justice'' (ACTA Publications 2011)
* R Faden and M Powers, ''Social Justice: The Moral Foundations of Public Health and Health Policy'' ([https://books.google.com/?id=mTLSzjg9yiIC&printsec=frontcover&dq=ISBN9780195189261&cd=1#v=onepage&q&f=false OUP 2006])
* J Franklin (ed), ''Life to the Full: Rights and Social Justice in Australia'' (Connor Court 2007)
* LC Frederking (2013) ''Reconstructing Social Justice'' (Routledge) {{ISBN|978-1138194021}}
* [[FA Hayek]], ''[[Law, Legislation and Liberty]]'' (1973) vol II, ch 3
* [[G Kitching]], ''Seeking Social Justice through Globalization: Escaping a Nationalist Perspective'' (2003)
* [[JS Mill]], ''[[Utilitarianism (book)|Utilitarianism]]'' (1863)
* T Massaro, S.J. ''Living Justice: Catholic Social Teaching in Action'' (Rowman & Littlefield 2012)
* [[John Rawls]], ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'' (Harvard University Press 1971)
* [[John Rawls]], ''[[Political Liberalism]]'' (Columbia University Press 1993)
* C Philomena, B Hoose and G Mannion (eds), ''Social Justice: Theological and Practical Explorations'' (2007)
* [[A Swift]], ''Political Philosophy'' (3rd edn 2013) ch 1
* Michael J. Thompson, ''[https://www.academia.edu/214008/The_Limits_of_Liberalism_A_Republican_Theory_of_Social_Justice The Limits of Liberalism: A Republican Theory of Social Justice]'' (International Journal of Ethics: vol. 7, no. 3 (2011)
{{social work}}
{{types of justice}}
{{subject bar|commons=yes|commons-search=Category:Social justice|q=yes|q-search=Social justice|d=yes|d-search=Q264892}}
{{authority control}}
[[Category:Social justice| ]]
[[Category:Justice]]
[[Category:Social inequality]]
[[Category:Social work]]
[[Category:Liberalism]]
[[Category:Left-wing politics]]
[[Category:Progressivism]]' |
New page wikitext, after the edit (new_wikitext ) | '{{short description|Concept of fair and just relations between the individual and society}}
{{pp-pc1}}
{{for multi|the early-20th-century periodical|Social Justice (periodical)|the academic journal established in 1974|Social Justice (journal)}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=November 2020}}
{{use American English|date=November 2017}}
'''Social justice''' is justice in terms of the distribution of [[wealth]], [[Equal opportunity|opportunities]], and [[Social privilege|privilege]]s within a society.<ref name="Oxford">{{cite web |title=social justice |url=https://languages.oup.com/google-dictionary-en/ |website=Oxford languages |access-date=26 August 2021}}</ref> In [[Western Civilization|Western]] as well as in older [[Culture of Asia|Asian cultures]], the concept of social justice has often referred to the process of ensuring that individuals fulfill their [[Role theory|societal roles]] and receive what was their due from society.<ref>[[Aristotle]], ''[[The Politics]]'' (ca 350 BC)</ref><ref name="Augustine">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8djVCRFoyQTZYS0k |title = "Augustine on Justice," a Chapter in Augustine and Social Justice |publisher = Lexington Books |author = Clark, Mary T. |year = 2015 |pages = 3–10 |isbn = 978-1-4985-0918-3 }}</ref><ref name="Global Dynamics">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8eXZMWHU3ckpQVUk |title = Social Justice, Global Dynamics : Theoretical and Empirical Perspectives |publisher = Taylor and Francis |author1 = Banai, Ayelet |author2 = Ronzoni, Miriam |author3 = Schemmel, Christian |year = 2011 |location = Florence |isbn = 978-0-203-81929-6 }}</ref> In the current movements for social justice, the emphasis has been on the breaking of barriers for [[social mobility]], the creation of [[Social safety net|safety nets]], and [[economic justice]].<ref>{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8V3hpa0V1ekFQZms |title = Seeking Social Justice Through Globalization Escaping a Nationalist Perspective |publisher = Pennsylvania State University Press |author = Kitching, G. N. |year = 2001 |location = University Park, Pa |pages = 3–10 |isbn = 978-0-271-02377-9 }}</ref><ref name="Globalization and Social Justice">{{cite journal |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8R2tWbXFmelhzVDA |title = Globalization and Social Justice |author = Hillman, Arye L. |journal = The Singapore Economic Review |year = 2008 |volume = 53 |issue = 2 |pages = 173–189 |doi=10.1142/s0217590808002896}}</ref><ref name="Movements in Time">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MWpSSGRWUllXTEE |title = Movements in Time Revolution, Social Justice, and Times of Change |publisher = Cambridge Scholars Pub |author1 = Lawrence, Cecile |author2 = Natalie Churn |name-list-style = amp |year = 2012 |location = Newcastle upon Tyne, UK |pages = xi–xv |isbn = 978-1-4438-4552-6 }}</ref><ref name="The Question of Social Justice">{{cite journal |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8Qm8zcHRRQ0xFN2c |title = Globalization and the Question of Social Justice |author = Agartan, Kaan |journal = Sociology Compass |year = 2014 |volume = 8 |issue = 6 |pages = 903–915 |doi = 10.1111/soc4.12162 }}</ref><ref name="A propositional political approach">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MTk1Qkp2b0ZaNDg |title = Globalization Development and Social Justice : A propositional political approach |publisher = Taylor and Francis |author = El Khoury, Ann |year = 2015 |location = Florence |pages = 1–20 |isbn = 978-1-317-50480-1 }}</ref>{{Excessive citations inline|date=October 2021}} Social justice assigns rights and duties in the [[institution]]s of society, which enables people to receive the basic benefits and burdens of cooperation. The relevant institutions often include [[taxation]], [[social insurance]], [[public health]], [[State school|public school]], [[public services]], [[labor law]] and [[regulation]] of [[Market (economics)|markets]], to ensure [[distribution of wealth]], and [[equal opportunity]].<ref>John Rawls, ''A Theory of Justice'' (1971) 4, "the principles of social justice: they provide a way of assigning rights and duties in the basic institutions of society and they define the appropriate distribution of benefits and burdens of social co-operation."</ref>
Interpretations that relate justice to a [[Reciprocity (social and political philosophy)|reciprocal relationship]] to society are mediated by differences in cultural traditions, some of which emphasize the individual responsibility toward society and others the equilibrium between access to power and its responsible use.<ref>{{cite journal |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8cTlPd2dzZ3d3TG8 |title = The Antecedents of Help Giving in Chinese Culture: Attribution, Judgment of Responsibility, Expectation Change and the Reaction of Affect |author1 = Aiqing Zhang |author2 = Feifei Xia |author3 = Chengwei Li |journal = Social Behavior and Personality |year = 2007 |volume = 35 |issue = 1 |pages = 135–142 |doi=10.2224/sbp.2007.35.1.135}}</ref> Hence, social justice is invoked today while reinterpreting historical figures such as [[Bartolomé de las Casas]], in philosophical debates about differences among human beings, in efforts for gender, ethnic, and [[social equality]], for advocating justice for [[Emigration|migrants]], prisoners, the [[environmental justice|environment]], and the physically and developmentally [[Disability|disabled]].<ref name="Human Nature">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MWRYV0xVUzNlRlU |title = Nature, Human Nature, and Human Difference : Race in Early Modern Philosophy |publisher = Princeton University Press |author = Smith, Justin E. H. |year = 2015 |page = 17 |isbn = 978-1-4008-6631-1 }}</ref><ref name="Migration, Gender and Social Justice">{{cite book |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8RGJGb0RiZEc0NzA |title = Migration, Gender and Social Justice: Perspectives on Human Insecurity |publisher = Springer |author = Trương, Thanh-Đạm |year = 2013 |pages = 3–26 |isbn = 978-3-642-28012-2 }}</ref><ref name="We Cannot Clap">{{cite journal |url=https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8bERZaWVUVGRPLTA |title = We Cannot Clap with One Hand: Global Socio–Political Differences in Social Support for People with Visual Impairment |author = Teklu, Abebe Abay |journal = International Journal of Ethiopian Studies |year = 2010 |volume = 5 |issue = 1 |pages = 93–105 }}</ref>
While concepts of social justice can be found in classical and Christian philosophical sources, from Plato and Aristotle to Augustine of Hippo and Thomas Aquinas, the term ''social justice'' finds its earliest uses in the late 18th century, albeit with unclear theoretical or practical meanings.<ref>J. Zajda, S. Majhanovich, V. Rust, ''Education and Social Justice'', 2006, [[ISBN (identifier)|ISBN]] [[Special:BookSources/1-4020-4721-5|1-4020-4721-5]]</ref><ref>Clark, Mary T. (2015). ''"Augustine on Justice," a Chapter in Augustine and Social Justice''. Lexington Books. pp. 3–10. [[ISBN (identifier)|ISBN]] [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4985-0918-3|<bdi>978-1-4985-0918-3</bdi>]].</ref><ref>Paine, Thomas. ''Agrarian Justice''. Printed by R. Folwell, for Benjamin Franklin Bache.</ref> The use of the term was early on subject to accusations of redundancy and of rhetorical flourish, perhaps but not necessarily related to amplifying one view of distributive justice.<ref name=":1">Behr, Thomas. ''Social Justice and Subsidiarity: Luigi Taparelli and the Origins of Modern Catholic Social Thought'' (Washington DC: Catholic University of American Press, December 2019).</ref> In the coining and definition of the term in the natural law social scientific treatise of Luigi Taparelli, SJ, in the early 1840s,<ref>Luigi Taparelli, SJ, ''Saggio teoretico di dritto naturale appogiato sul fatto'' (Palermo: Antonio Muratori, 1840-43), Sections 341-364.</ref> Taparelli established the natural law principle that corresponded to the evangelical principle of brotherly love—i.e. social justice reflects the duty one has to one’s other self in the interdependent abstract unity of the human person in society.<ref>Behr, Thomas. ''Social Justice and Subsidiarity: Luigi Taparelli and the Origins of Modern Catholic Social Thought''(Washington DC: Catholic University of American Press, December 2019), pp. 149-154.</ref> After the Revolutions of 1848 the term was popularized generically through the writings of Antonio Rosmini-Serbati.<ref>Rosmini-Serbati, ''The Constitution under Social Justice.'' trans. A. Mingardi (Lanham: Lexington Books, 2007).</ref><ref>Pérez-Garzón, Carlos Andrés (14 January 2018). "Unveiling the Meaning of Social Justice in Colombia". ''Mexican Law Review''. '''10''' (2): 27–66. [[ISSN (identifier)|ISSN]] 2448-5306. Archived from the original on 29 March 2018. Retrieved 28 March 2018.</ref>
In the late industrial revolution, [[Progressive Era]] American legal scholars began to use the term more, particularly [[Louis Brandeis]] and [[Roscoe Pound]]. From the early 20th century it was also embedded in [[international law]] and institutions; the preamble to establish the [[International Labour Organization]] recalled that "universal and lasting peace can be established only if it is based upon social justice." In the later 20th century, social justice was made central to the philosophy of the [[social contract]], primarily by [[John Rawls]] in ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'' (1971). In 1993, the [[Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action]] treats social justice as a purpose of [[human rights education]].<ref>[[s:Constitution of the International Labour Organization|The Preamble of ILO Constitution]]</ref><ref>Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, Part II, D.</ref>
== History ==
{{Main|Social contract|Justice|Corrective justice|Distributive justice}}
[[File:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|upright|An artist's rendering of what Plato might have looked like. From Raphael's early 16th century painting "''Scuola di Atene"''.]]
The different concepts of [[justice]], as discussed in ancient [[Western philosophy]], were typically centered upon the community.
[[File:Aristotle Altemps Inv8575.jpg|thumb|upright|Roman copy in marble of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by Lysippos, c. 330 BC. The alabaster mantle is modern.]]
* [[Plato]] wrote in ''[[The Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]'' that it would be an ideal state that "every member of the community must be assigned to the class for which he finds himself best fitted."<ref>[[Plato]], ''[[The Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]'' (ca 380BC)</ref> In an article for J.N.V University, author D.R. Bhandari says, "Justice is, for Plato, at once a part of human virtue and the bond, which joins man together in society. It is the identical quality that makes good and social. Justice is an order and duty of the parts of the soul, it is to the soul as health is to the body. Plato says that justice is not mere strength, but it is a harmonious strength. Justice is not the right of the stronger but the effective harmony of the whole. All moral conceptions revolve about the good of the whole-individual as well as social".<ref name="bu.edu">{{cite web |url=https://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciBhan.htm |title = 20th WCP: Plato's Concept of Justice: An Analysis |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20161005111127/http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciBhan.htm |archive-date = 5 October 2016}}</ref>
* Plato believed rights existed only between free people, and the law should take "account in the first instance of relations of inequality in which individuals are treated in proportion to their worth and only secondarily of relations of equality." Reflecting this time when [[slavery]] and subjugation of women was typical, ancient views of justice tended to reflect the rigid class systems that still prevailed. On the other hand, for the privileged groups, strong concepts of fairness and the community existed. [[Distributive justice]] was said by [[Aristotle]] to require that people were distributed goods and assets according to their merit.<ref>''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' V.3</ref>
[[File:Head of Socrates in Palazzo Massimo alle Terme (Rome).JPG|thumb|upright|Bust of Socrates]]
* [[Socrates]] (through Plato's dialogue ''[[Crito]]'') is credited with developing the idea of a [[social contract]], whereby people ought to follow the rules of a shit
, and accept its burdens because they have accepted its benefits.<ref>[[Plato]], ''[[Crito]]'' (ca 380 BC)</ref> During the Middle Ages, religious scholars particularly, such as [[Thomas Aquinas]] continued discussion of justice in various ways, but ultimately connected being a good citizen to the purpose of serving God.
After the [[Renaissance]] and [[Reformation]], the modern concept of social justice, as developing human potential, began to emerge through the work of a series of authors. [[Baruch Spinoza]] in ''[[On the Improvement of the Understanding]]'' (1677) contended that the one true aim of life should be to acquire "a human character much more stable than [one's] own", and to achieve this "pitch of perfection... The chief good is that he should arrive, together with other individuals if possible, at the possession of the aforesaid character."<ref>B Spinoza, ''[[On the Improvement of the Understanding]]'' (1677) [[s:On the Improvement of the Understanding#12|para 13]]</ref> During the [[Age of Enlightenment|enlightenment]] and responding to the [[French Revolution|French]] and [[American Revolution]]s, [[Thomas Paine]] similarly wrote in ''[[The Rights of Man]]'' (1792) society should give "genius a fair and universal chance" and so "the construction of government ought to be such as to bring forward... all that extent of capacity which never fails to appear in revolutions."<ref>[[T Paine]], ''[[Rights of Man]]'' (1792) 197</ref>
[[File:Fr. Luigi Taparelli.jpg|thumb|''Social justice'' has been traditionally credited to be coined by [[Jesuit]] priest [[Luigi Taparelli]] in the 1840s, but the expression is older]]
Although there is no certainty about the first use of the term "social justice", early sources can be found in Europe in the 18th century.<ref name="pérez27">{{Cite journal|last=Pérez-Garzón|first=Carlos Andrés|date=2018-01-14|title=Unveiling the Meaning of Social Justice in Colombia|url=https://revistas.juridicas.unam.mx/index.php/mexican-law-review/article/view/11892|journal=Mexican Law Review|language=en-US|volume=10|issue=2|pages=27–66|issn=2448-5306|access-date=28 March 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180329054435/https://revistas.juridicas.unam.mx/index.php/mexican-law-review/article/view/11892|archive-date=29 March 2018|url-status=dead}}</ref> Some references to the use of the expression are in articles of journals aligned with the spirit of the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]], in which social justice is described as an obligation of the monarch;<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TnMLHOwjqgMC&q=%22justice+sociale%22&pg=PA311|title=Journal encyclopédique... [Ed. Pierre Rousseau]|last=Rousseau|date=1774|publisher=De l'Imprimerie du Journal|language=fr}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xzATAAAAYAAJ&q=justice+sociale&pg=PA131|title=L'Esprit des journaux, françois et étrangers|date=1784|publisher=Valade|language=fr}}</ref> also the term is present in books written by Catholic Italian theologians, notably members of the [[Society of Jesus]].<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=AEBbAAAAcAAJ&q=%22giustizia+sociale%22&pg=PA349|title=L'Episcopato ossia della Potesta di governar la chiesa. Dissertazione|date=1789|publisher=na|language=it}}</ref> Thus, according to this sources and the context, social justice was another term for "the justice of society", the justice that rules the relations among individuals in society, without any mention to socio-economic equity or human dignity.<ref name="pérez27"/>
The usage of the term started to become more frequent by Catholic thinkers from the 1840s, beginning with the [[Jesuit]] [[Luigi Taparelli]] in ''Civiltà Cattolica'', and based on the work of St. [[Thomas Aquinas]]. Taparelli argued that rival [[capitalism|capitalist]] and [[socialist]] theories, based on subjective [[René Descartes|Cartesian]] thinking, undermined the unity of society present in [[Thomism|Thomistic]] [[metaphysics]] as neither were sufficiently concerned with ethics.<ref name=":1" /> Writing in 1861, the influential British philosopher and economist, [[John Stuart Mill]] stated in ''[[Utilitarianism]]'' his view that "Society should treat all equally well who have deserved equally well of it, that is, who have deserved equally well absolutely. This is the highest abstract standard of social and distributive justice; towards which all institutions, and the efforts of all virtuous citizens, should be made in the utmost degree to converge."<ref>[[JS Mill]], ''[[Utilitarianism (book)|Utilitarianism]]'' (1863)</ref>
In the later 19th and early 20th century, social justice became an important theme in American political and legal philosophy, particularly in the work of [[John Dewey]], [[Roscoe Pound]] and [[Louis Brandeis]]. One of the prime concerns was the ''[[Lochner era]]'' decisions of the [[US Supreme Court]] to strike down legislation passed by state governments and the Federal government for social and economic improvement, such as the [[eight-hour day]] or the right to join a [[trade union]]. After the First World War, the founding document of the [[International Labour Organization]] took up the same terminology in its preamble, stating that "peace can be established only if it is based on social justice". From this point, the discussion of social justice entered into mainstream legal and academic discourse.
In 1931, the [[Pope Pius XI]] explicitly referred to the expression, along with the concept of [[subsidiarity]], for the first time in [[Catholic social teaching]] in the encyclical ''[[Quadragesimo anno]]''. Then again in ''[[Divini Redemptoris]]'', the church pointed out that the realization of social justice relied on the promotion of the [[human dignity|dignity of human person]].<ref>{{cite web|url=https://w2.vatican.va/content/pius-xi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_enc_19370319_divini-redemptoris.html|title=Divini Redemptoris (March 19, 1937) {{!}} PIUS XI|website=w2.vatican.va|access-date=2018-03-28}}</ref> During the 1930s, the term was widely associated with pro-[[Nazi]] and [[antisemitic]] groups, such as the [[Christian Front (United States)|Christian Front]].<ref>{{cite magazine |title=The Press: Crackdown on Coughlin |url=http://content.time.com/time/subscriber/article/0,33009,795777,00.html |magazine=Time |access-date=24 February 2022 |date=27 April 1942}}</ref> Social Justice was the slogan of [[Charles Coughlin]], and the name of his [[Social Justice (periodical)|newspaper]]. Because of the documented influence of ''Divini Redemptoris'' in its drafters,<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Moyn|first=Samuel|date=2014|title=The Secret History of Constitutional Dignity|url=http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yhrdlj/vol17/iss1/2/|journal=Yale Human Rights and Development Journal|language=en|volume=17|issue=1|issn=1548-2596}}</ref> the [[Constitution of Ireland]] was the first one to establish the term as a principle of the economy in the State, and then other countries around the world did the same throughout the 20th century, even in [[socialist]] regimes such as the [[Constitution of Cuba|Cuban Constitution]] in 1976.<ref name="pérez27"/>
In the late 20th century, several liberal and conservative thinkers, notably [[Friedrich Hayek]] rejected the concept by stating that it did not mean anything, or meant too many things.<ref>[[FA Hayek]], ''[[Law, Legislation and Liberty]]'' (1973) vol II, ch 3</ref> However the concept remained highly influential, particularly with its promotion by philosophers such as [[John Rawls]]. Even though the meaning of social justice varies, at least three common elements can be identified in the contemporary theories about it: a duty of the State to [[Distributive justice|distribute]] certain vital means (such as [[Economic, social and cultural rights|economic, social, and cultural rights]]), the protection of [[human dignity]], and [[affirmative action]]s to promote [[Equal opportunity|equal opportunities]] for everybody.<ref name="pérez27"/>
== Contemporary theory ==
=== Philosophical perspectives ===
==== Cosmic values ====
[[Hunter Lewis]]' work promoting natural healthcare and sustainable economies advocates for [[Conservation (ethic)|conservation]] as a key premise in social justice. His manifesto on [[sustainability]] ties the continued thriving of human life to real conditions, the environment supporting that life, and associates injustice with the detrimental effects of [[unintended consequences]] of human actions. Quoting classical Greek thinkers like [[Epicurus]] on the good of pursuing happiness, Hunter also cites ornithologist, naturalist, and philosopher [[Alexander Skutch]] in his book Moral Foundations:
{{blockquote|The common feature which unites the activities most consistently forbidden by the moral codes of civilized peoples is that by their very nature they cannot be both habitual and enduring, because they tend to destroy the conditions which make them possible.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.anh-usa.org/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Sustainability-the-Complete-Concept1.pdf |author = Hunter Lewis |title = Sustainability, The Complete Concept, Environment, Healthcare, and Economy |date = 14 October 2009 |publisher = ChangeThis |access-date = 23 January 2011 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304090801/http://www.anh-usa.org/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Sustainability-the-Complete-Concept1.pdf |archive-date = 4 March 2016 |url-status=dead }}</ref>}}
Pope Benedict XVI cites [[Teilhard de Chardin]] in a vision of the cosmos as a 'living host'<ref>{{cite news |url=http://ncronline.org/news/ecology/pope-cites-teilhardian-vision-cosmos-living-host |author = John Allen Jr. |title = Ecology – The first stirring of an 'evolutionary leap' in late Jesuit's official standing? |date = 28 July 2009 |newspaper = National Catholic Reporter |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120824050226/http://ncronline.org/news/ecology/pope-cites-teilhardian-vision-cosmos-living-host |archive-date = 24 August 2012}}</ref> embracing an understanding of ecology that includes humanity's relationship to others, that pollution affects not just the natural world but interpersonal relations as well. Cosmic harmony, justice and peace are closely interrelated:
{{blockquote|If you want to cultivate peace, protect creation.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://chiesa.espresso.repubblica.it/articolo/1341681?eng=y/ |author = Sandro Magister |title = Benedict XVI to the Diplomats: Three Levers for Lifting Up the World |date = 11 January 2010 |publisher = chiesa, Rome |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304083309/http://chiesa.espresso.repubblica.it/articolo/1341681?eng=y%2F |archive-date = 4 March 2016}}</ref>}}
In ''The Quest for Cosmic Justice'', [[Thomas Sowell]] writes that seeking utopia, while admirable, may have disastrous effects if done without strong consideration of the economic underpinnings that support contemporary society.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Sowell |first1=Thomas |title=The quest for cosmic justice |publisher=Simon & Schuster |isbn=0684864630 |edition=1st Touchstone|date=5 February 2002 }}</ref>
==== John Rawls ====
{{Main|John Rawls}}
Political philosopher [[John Rawls]] draws on the [[utilitarian]] insights of [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]] and [[John Stuart Mill|Mill]], the [[social contract]] ideas of [[John Locke]], and the [[categorical imperative]] ideas of [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]]. His first statement of principle was made in ''A Theory of Justice'' where he proposed that, "Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override. For this reason justice denies that the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good shared by others."<ref>John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (2005 reissue), Chapter 1, "Justice as Fairness" – 1. The Role of Justice, pp. 3–4</ref> A [[deontological]] proposition that echoes Kant in framing the moral good of justice in [[Moral absolutism|absolutist]] terms. His views are definitively restated in ''[[Political Liberalism]]'' where society is seen "as a fair system of co-operation over time, from one generation to the next".<ref>John Rawls, ''Political Liberalism'' 15 (Columbia University Press 2003)</ref>
All societies have a basic structure of social, economic, and political institutions, both formal and informal. In testing how well these elements fit and work together, Rawls based a key test of legitimacy on the theories of social contract. To determine whether any particular system of collectively enforced social arrangements is legitimate, he argued that one must look for agreement by the people who are subject to it, but not necessarily to an objective notion of justice based on coherent ideological grounding. Obviously, not every citizen can be asked to participate in a poll to determine his or her consent to every proposal in which some degree of coercion is involved, so one has to assume that all citizens are reasonable. Rawls constructed an argument for a two-stage process to determine a citizen's hypothetical agreement:
* The citizen agrees to be represented by X for certain purposes, and, to that extent, X holds these powers as a [[trustee]] for the citizen.
* X agrees that enforcement in a particular social context is legitimate. The citizen, therefore, is bound by this decision because it is the function of the trustee to represent the citizen in this way.
This applies to one person who represents a small group (e.g., the organiser of a social event setting a dress code) as equally as it does to national governments, which are ultimate trustees, holding representative powers for the benefit of all citizens within their territorial boundaries. Governments that fail to provide for [[social welfare|welfare]] of their citizens according to the principles of justice are not legitimate. To emphasise the general principle that justice should rise from the people and not be dictated by the law-making powers of governments, Rawls asserted that, "There is ... a general presumption against imposing legal and other restrictions on conduct without sufficient reason. But this presumption creates no special priority for any particular liberty."<ref>John Rawls, Political Liberalism 291–92 (Columbia University Press 2003)</ref> This is support for an unranked set of liberties that reasonable citizens in all states should respect and uphold — to some extent, the list proposed by Rawls matches the normative human rights that have international recognition and direct enforcement in some nation states where the citizens need encouragement to act in a way that fixes a greater degree of equality of outcome. According to Rawls, the basic liberties that every good society should guarantee are:
* [[Freedom of thought]];
* Liberty of conscience as it affects social relationships on the grounds of religion, philosophy, and morality;
* Political liberties (e.g., representative democratic institutions, [[freedom of speech]] and the [[freedom of the press|press]], and [[freedom of assembly]]);
* [[Freedom of association]];
* Freedoms necessary for the liberty and integrity of the person (namely: freedom from slavery, freedom of movement and a reasonable degree of freedom to choose one's occupation); and
* Rights and liberties covered by the [[rule of law]].
==== Thomas Pogge ====
[[File:2014-01-08 Thomas Pogge 4737-cropped.JPG|thumb|upright|[[Thomas Pogge]]]]
[[Thomas Pogge]]'s arguments pertain to a standard of social justice that creates [[human rights defender|human rights deficits]]. He assigns responsibility to those who actively cooperate in designing or imposing the social institution, that the order is foreseeable as harming the global poor and is reasonably avoidable. Pogge argues that social institutions have a [[negative duty]] to not harm the poor.<ref>{{cite web |last1 = James |first1 = Nickel |title = Human Rights |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ |website = stanford.edu |publisher = The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date = 10 February 2015 }}</ref><ref>{{cite web |last1 = Pogge |first1 = Thomas Pogge |title = World Poverty and Human Rights |url=http://thomaspogge.com/books/world-poverty-human-rights/ |website = thomaspogge.com |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150919070037/http://thomaspogge.com/books/world-poverty-human-rights/ |archive-date = 19 September 2015}}</ref>
Pogge speaks of "institutional cosmopolitanism" and assigns responsibility to institutional schemes<ref>{{cite journal |last1 = North |first1 = James |title = The Resource Privilege |url=http://www.thenation.com/article/181724/resource-privilege# |journal = The Nation |access-date = 10 February 2015 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150210065716/http://www.thenation.com/article/181724/resource-privilege |archive-date = 10 February 2015|date = 23 September 2014 }}</ref> for deficits of human rights. An example given is slavery and third parties. A third party should not recognize or enforce slavery. The institutional order should be held responsible only for deprivations of human rights that it establishes or authorizes. The current institutional design, he says, systematically harms developing economies by enabling corporate tax evasion,<ref>{{cite web |last1 = Pogge |first1 = Thomas |title = Human Rights and Just Taxation – Global Financial Transparency |url=http://thomaspogge.com/human-rights-and-just-taxation-global-financial-transparency/ |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150210074345/http://thomaspogge.com/human-rights-and-just-taxation-global-financial-transparency/ |archive-date = 10 February 2015}}</ref> illicit financial flows, corruption, trafficking of people and weapons. [[Joshua Cohen (philosopher)|Joshua Cohen]] disputes his claims based on the fact that some poor countries have done well with the current institutional design.<ref>{{cite book |editor1 = Alison M. Jaggar1 by |title = Thomas Pogge and His Critics. |date = 2010 |publisher = Polity Press |location = Cambridge |isbn = 978-0-7456-4258-1 |edition = 1. publ. }}</ref> Elizabeth Kahn argues that some of these responsibilities{{vague|date=April 2017}} should apply globally.<ref>{{cite journal |last1 = Kahn |first1 = Elizabeth |title = Global Economic Justice: A Structural Approach |journal = Public Reason |date = June–December 2012 |volume = 4 |issue = 1–2 |pages = 48–67 }}</ref>
==== United Nations ====
The United Nations calls social justice "an underlying principle for peaceful and prosperous coexistence within and among nations.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.un.org/en/events/socialjusticeday/index.shtml|title=World Day of Social Justice, 20 February|website=www.un.org|language=EN|access-date=2019-11-08}}</ref>
The United Nations' 2006 document ''Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations'', states that "Social justice may be broadly understood as the fair and compassionate distribution of the fruits of economic growth{{nbsp}}..."<ref name="un">{{cite web |title = Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations", The International Forum for Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ESA/305 |publisher = United Nations |location = New York |year = 2006 |url=https://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170829123826/http://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf |archive-date = 29 August 2017}}</ref>{{rp|16}}
The term "social justice" was seen by the U.N. "as a substitute for the protection of human rights [and] first appeared in United Nations texts during the second half of the 1960s. At the initiative of the Soviet Union, and with the support of developing countries, the term was used in the Declaration on Social Progress and Development, adopted in 1969."<ref name="un" />{{rp|52}}
The same document reports, "From the comprehensive global perspective shaped by the United Nations Charter and the [[Universal Declaration of Human Rights]], neglect of the pursuit of social justice in all its dimensions translates into de facto acceptance of a future marred by violence, repression and chaos."<ref name="un" />{{rp|6}} The report concludes, "Social justice is not possible without strong and coherent [[redistribution of income and wealth|redistributive policies]] conceived and implemented by public agencies."<ref name="un" />{{rp|16}}
The same UN document offers a concise history: "[T]he notion of social justice is relatively new. None of history’s great philosophers—not Plato or Aristotle, or Confucius or Averroes, or even Rousseau or Kant—saw the need to consider justice or the redress of injustices from a social perspective. The concept first surfaced in Western thought and political language in the wake of the industrial revolution and the parallel development of the socialist doctrine. It emerged as an expression of protest against what was perceived as the capitalist [[exploitation of labor]] and as a focal point for the development of measures to improve the human condition. It was born as a revolutionary slogan embodying the ideals of progress and fraternity. Following the revolutions that shook Europe in the mid-1800s, social justice became a rallying cry for progressive thinkers and political activists.... By the mid-twentieth century, the concept of social justice had become central to the ideologies and programs of virtually all the leftist and centrist political parties around the world{{nbsp}}..."<ref name="un" />{{rp|11–12}}
Another key area of human rights and social justice is the United Nations's defense of children's rights worldwide. In 1989, the Convention on the Rights of the Child was adopted and available for signature, ratification and accession by General Assembly resolution 44/25.<ref name=":0">{{Cite web|title=OHCHR {{!}} Convention on the Rights of the Child|url=https://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/crc.aspx|access-date=2020-12-21|website=www.ohchr.org}}</ref> According to [[Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights|OHCHR]], this convention entered into force on 2 September 1990. This convention upholds that all states have the obligation to "protect the child from all forms of physical or mental violence, injury or abuse, neglect or negligent treatment, maltreatment or exploitation, including sexual abuse."<ref name=":0" />
== Religious perspectives ==
===Abrahamic religions===
==== Christianity ====
{{See also|Christian ethics|Christian democracy}}
===== Evangelicalism =====
''[[Time (magazine)|Time]]'' magazine noted that younger Evangelicals also increasingly engage in social justice.<ref>{{Cite magazine|last=Sullivan|first=Amy|date=2010-06-01|title=Young Evangelicals: Expanding Their Mission|language=en-US|magazine=Time|url=http://content.time.com/time/nation/article/0,8599,1992463-1,00.html|access-date=2020-10-08|issn=0040-781X}}</ref> John Stott traced the call for social justice back to the cross, "The cross is a revelation of God's justice as well as of his love. That is why the community of the cross should concern itself with social justice as well as with loving philanthropy."<ref>{{Cite book|last=Stott|first=John|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uSHC3qDjFS4C&pg=PA285|title=The Cross of Christ|date=2012-11-29|publisher=InterVarsity Press|isbn=978-0-8308-6636-6|pages=185|language=en}}</ref>
====== Methodism ======
From its founding, Methodism was a Christian social justice movement. Under [[John Wesley]]'s direction, Methodists became leaders in many social justice issues of the day, including the [[prison reform]] and [[abolitionism|abolition]] movements. Wesley himself was among the first to preach for slaves rights attracting significant opposition.<ref>S. R. Valentine, John Bennet & the Origins of Methodism and the Evangelical revival in England, Scarecrow Press, Lanham, 1997.</ref><ref>Carey, Brycchan. "John Wesley (1703–1791)." The British Abolitionists. Brycchan Carey, 11 July 2008. 5 October 2009. [http://www.brycchancarey.com/abolition/index.htm Brycchancarey.com] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160129112229/http://brycchancarey.com/abolition/index.htm |date=29 January 2016 }}</ref><ref>Wesley John, "Thoughts Upon Slavery," John Wesley: Holiness of Heart and Life. Charles Yrigoyen, 1996. 5 October 2009. [http://gbgm-umc.org/umw/wesley/thoughtsuponslavery.stm Gbgm-umc.org] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141016083225/http://gbgm-umc.org/umw/wesley/thoughtsuponslavery.stm |date=16 October 2014 }}</ref>
Today, social justice plays a major role in the [[United Methodist Church]] and the [[Free Methodist Church]].<ref>{{cite web |title=Do Justice |url=https://www.ffmc.org/do-justice |publisher=First Free Methodist Church |access-date=12 June 2021 |language=English}}</ref> The ''Book of Discipline of the United Methodist Church'' says, "We hold governments responsible for the protection of the rights of the people to free and fair elections and to the freedoms of speech, religion, assembly, communications media, and petition for redress of grievances without fear of reprisal; to the [[right to privacy]]; and to the guarantee of the rights to adequate food, clothing, shelter, education, and health care."<ref>The Book of Discipline of The United Methodist Church – 2012 ¶164 V, [http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467671¬oc=1 umc.org] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131206020517/http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467671¬oc=1 |date=6 December 2013 }}</ref> The United Methodist Church also teaches [[Human population control|population control]] as part of its doctrine.<ref>The Book of Discipline of The United Methodist Church – 2008 ¶ 162 K, [http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467635¬oc=1 umc.org] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131206012803/http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467635¬oc=1 |date=6 December 2013 }}</ref>
===== Catholicism =====
{{Main|Catholic social teaching}}
Catholic social teaching consists of those aspects of Roman Catholic doctrine which relate to matters dealing with the respect of the individual human life. A distinctive feature of Catholic social doctrine is its concern for the poorest and most vulnerable members of society. Two of the seven key areas<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/projects/socialteaching/excerpt.htm |title = Seven Key Themes of Catholic Social Teaching |access-date = 29 March 2014 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070608113958/http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/projects/socialteaching/excerpt.htm |archive-date = 8 June 2007 }}</ref> of "Catholic social teaching" are pertinent to social justice:
* Life and dignity of the human person: The foundational principle of all Catholic social teaching is the sanctity of all human life and the inherent dignity of every human person, from conception to natural death. Human life must be valued above all material possessions.
* Preferential option for the poor and [[social vulnerability|vulnerable]]: Catholics believe Jesus taught that on the [[Day of Judgement]] God will ask what each person did to help the poor and needy: "Amen, I say to you, whatever you did for one of these least brothers of mine, you did for me."<ref>[[Gospel of Matthew|Matthew]] 25:40.</ref> The Catholic Church believes that through words, prayers and deeds one must show solidarity with, and compassion for, the poor. The moral test of any society is "how it treats its most vulnerable members. The poor have the most urgent moral claim on the conscience of the nation. People are called to look at public policy decisions in terms of how they affect the poor."<ref>Option for the Poor, [http://www.osjspm.org/cst/themes.htm Major themes from Catholic Social Teaching] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060216183419/http://www.osjspm.org/cst/themes.htm |date=16 February 2006 }}, Office for Social Justice, Archdiocese of St. Paul and Minneapolis.</ref>
Modern Catholic social teaching is often thought to have begun with the encyclicals of Pope Leo XIII.<ref name=":1" />
* [[Pope Leo XIII]], who studied under Taparelli, published in 1891 the [[encyclical]] ''[[Rerum novarum]]'' (On the Condition of the Working Classes; lit. "On new things"), rejecting both [[socialism]] and [[capitalism]], while defending labor unions and private property. He stated that society should be based on cooperation and not [[class conflict]] and [[competition]]. In this document, Leo set out the Catholic Church's response to the social instability and labor conflict that had arisen in the wake of industrialization and had led to the rise of socialism. The Pope advocated that the role of the state was to promote social justice through the protection of rights, while the church must speak out on social issues to teach correct social principles and ensure class harmony.
* The encyclical ''[[Quadragesimo anno]]'' (On Reconstruction of the Social Order, literally "in the fortieth year") of 1931 by [[Pope Pius XI]], encourages a [[living wage]],<ref>Popularised by [[John A. Ryan]], although see [[Sidney Webb]] and [[Beatrice Webb]], ''[[Industrial Democracy]]'' (1897)</ref> [[subsidiarity (Catholicism)|subsidiarity]], and advocates that social justice is a personal virtue as well as an attribute of the social order, saying that society can be just only if individuals and institutions are just.
* [[Pope John Paul II]] added much to the corpus of the Catholic social teaching, penning three encyclicals which focus on issues such as economics, politics, geo-political situations, ownership of the means of production, private property and the "[[social mortgage]]", and private property. The encyclicals ''[[Laborem exercens]]'', ''[[Sollicitudo rei socialis]]'', and ''[[Centesimus annus]]'' are just a small portion of his overall contribution to Catholic social justice. Pope John Paul II was a strong advocate of justice and [[human rights]], and spoke forcefully for the poor. He addresses issues such as the problems that technology can present should it be misused, and admits a fear that the "progress" of the world is not true progress at all, if it should denigrate the value of the human person. He argued in ''[[Centesimus annus]]'' that private property, markets, and honest labor were the keys to alleviating the miseries of the poor and to enabling a life that can express the fullness of the human person.
* [[Pope Benedict XVI]]'s encyclical ''[[Deus caritas est]]'' ("God is Love") of 2006 claims that justice is the defining concern of the state and the central concern of politics, and not of the church, which has charity as its central social concern. It said that the laity has the specific responsibility of pursuing social justice in civil society and that the church's active role in social justice should be to inform the debate, using reason and natural law, and also by providing moral and spiritual formation for those involved in politics.
* The official Catholic doctrine on social justice can be found in the book ''Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church'', published in 2004 and updated in 2006, by the [[Pontifical Council for Justice and Peace|Pontifical Council ''Iustitia et Pax'']].
The ''Catechism of the Catholic Church'' (§§ 1928–1948) contains more detail of the church's view of social justice.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.vatican.va/archive/ccc_css/archive/catechism/p3s1c2a3.htm |title = Catechism of the Catholic Church – Social justice |publisher = Vatican.va |access-date = 29 March 2014 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131105063620/https://www.vatican.va/archive/ccc_css/archive/catechism/p3s1c2a3.htm |archive-date = 5 November 2013}}</ref>
==== Islam ====
In Muslim history, Islamic governance has often been associated with social justice.{{additional citation|date=April 2018}} Establishment of social justice was one of the motivating factors of the [[Umayyad#Insurrection|Abbasid revolt]] against the Umayyads.<ref>{{cite book |author = John L. Esposito |title = Islam and Politics |publisher = Syracuse University Press |year = 1998 |page = 17 |author-link = John L. Esposito }}</ref> The Shi'a believe that the return of the ''Mahdi'' will herald in "the messianic age of justice" and the Mahdi along with the Isa (Jesus) will end plunder, torture, oppression and discrimination.<ref>{{cite book |author = John L. Esposito |title = Islam and Politics |publisher = Syracuse University Press |year = 1998 |page = 205 |author-link = John L. Esposito }}</ref>
For the [[Muslim Brotherhood]] the implementation of social justice would require the rejection of [[consumerism]] and [[communism]]. The Brotherhood strongly affirmed the right to private property as well as differences in personal wealth due to factors such as hard work. However, the Brotherhood held Muslims had an obligation to assist those Muslims in need. It held that ''zakat'' (alms-giving) was not voluntary charity, but rather the poor had the right to assistance from the more fortunate.<ref>{{cite book |author = John L. Esposito |title = Islam and Politics |publisher = Syracuse University Press |year = 1998 |pages = 147–8 |author-link = John L. Esposito }}</ref> Most Islamic governments therefore enforce the ''zakat'' through taxes.
==== Judaism ====
{{Main|Tikkun olam}}
In ''To Heal a Fractured World: The Ethics of Responsibility'', Rabbi [[Jonathan Sacks]] states that social justice has a central place in [[Judaism]]. One of Judaism's most distinctive and challenging ideas is its [[ethics]] of responsibility reflected in the concepts of [[simcha]] ("gladness" or "joy"), [[tzedakah]] ("the religious obligation to perform charity and philanthropic acts"), [[chesed]] ("deeds of kindness"), and [[tikkun olam]] ("repairing the world").<ref>{{Cite book|last=Sacks|first=Jonathan|title=To Heal a Fractured World: The Ethics of Responsibility|publisher=Schocken|year=2005|isbn=9780826486226|location=New York|pages=3}}</ref>
===Eastern religions===
==== Hinduism ====
The present-day [[Jāti]] hierarchy is undergoing changes for a variety of reasons including 'social justice', which is a politically popular stance in democratic India. Institutionalized affirmative action has promoted this. The disparity and wide inequalities in social behaviour of the jātis – exclusive, endogamous communities centred on traditional occupations – has led to various [[Social reformers of India|reform movements]] in [[Hinduism]]. While legally outlawed, the caste system remains strong in practice.<ref>{{cite news |last1 = Patil |first1 = Vijaykumar |title = Caste system hindering the goal of social justice: Siddaramaiah |url=http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/karnataka/caste-system-hindering-the-goal-of-social-justice-cm/article6822818.ece |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150904050652/http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/karnataka/caste-system-hindering-the-goal-of-social-justice-cm/article6822818.ece |archive-date = 4 September 2015|newspaper = The Hindu |date = 26 January 2015 }}</ref>
==== Traditional Chinese religion ====
{{main|Mandate of Heaven}}
The Chinese concept of Tian Ming has occasionally been perceived{{by whom|date=May 2018}} as an expression of social justice.<ref>Lee Jen-der (2014), "Crime and Punishment: The Case of Liu Hui in the Wei Shu", ''Early Medieval China: A Sourcebook'', New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 156–165, {{ISBN|978-0-231-15987-6}}.</ref> Through it, the deposition of unfair rulers is justified in that civic dissatisfaction and economical disasters is perceived as [[Tian|Heaven]] withdrawing its favor from the Emperor. A successful rebellion is considered definite proof that the Emperor is unfit to rule.
== Social justice movements ==
{{liberalism sidebar}}
{{Progressivism}}
{{Social democracy sidebar}}
{{Labor|expanded=unions}}
Social justice is also a concept that is used to describe the movement towards a socially just world, e.g., the [[Global Justice Movement]]. In this context, social justice is based on the concepts of human rights and equality, and can be defined as ''"the way in which human rights are manifested in the everyday lives of people at every level of society"''.<ref>Just Comment – Volume 3 Number 1, 2000</ref>
Several [[social movement|movements]] are working to achieve social justice in society. These movements are working toward the realization of a world where all members of a society, regardless of background or procedural justice, have basic human rights and equal access to the benefits of their society.<ref>{{cite book |last1 = Capeheart |first1 = Loretta |first2 = Dragan |last2 = Milovanovic |title = Social Justice: Theories, Issues, and Movements |title-link = Social Justice: Theories, Issues, and Movements }}</ref>
=== Liberation theology ===
{{Main|Liberation theology}}
Liberation theology<ref>In the mass media, 'Liberation Theology' can sometimes be used loosely, to refer to a wide variety of activist Christian thought. This article uses the term in the narrow sense outlined here.</ref> is a movement in [[Christianity|Christian]] [[theology]] which conveys the teachings of [[Jesus Christ]] in terms of a liberation from unjust economic, political, or social conditions. It has been described by proponents as "an interpretation of Christian faith through the poor's suffering, their struggle and hope, and a critique of society and the Catholic faith and Christianity through the eyes of the poor",<ref>[[Phillip Berryman|Berryman, Phillip]], ''Liberation Theology: essential facts about the revolutionary movement in Latin America and beyond''(1987)</ref> and by detractors as Christianity perverted by [[Marxism]] and [[Communism]].<ref>"[David] Horowitz first describes liberation theology as 'a form of Marxised Christianity,' which has validity despite the awkward phrasing, but then he calls it a form of 'Marxist-Leninist ideology,' which is simply not true for most liberation theology{{nbsp}}..." Robert Shaffer, "[http://www.oah.org/pubs/nl/2007nov/shaffer.html Acceptable Bounds of Academic Discourse] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130904165644/http://www.oah.org/pubs/nl/2007nov/shaffer.html |date=4 September 2013 }}," Organization of American Historians Newsletter 35, November 2007. URL retrieved 12 July 2010.</ref>
Although liberation theology has grown into an international and inter-denominational movement, it began as a movement within the [[Catholic Church]] in Latin America in the 1950s–1960s. It arose principally as a moral reaction to the poverty caused by social injustice in that region.<ref name=Williams>''Liberation Theology and Its Role in Latin America''. Elisabeth Erin Williams. Monitor: Journal of International Studies. The College of William and Mary.</ref> It achieved prominence in the 1970s and 1980s. The term was coined by the [[Peruvian]] priest, [[Gustavo Gutiérrez]], who wrote one of the movement's most famous books, ''A Theology of Liberation'' (1971). According to [[Sarah Kleeb]], "Marx would surely take issue," she writes, "with the appropriation of his works in a religious context...there is no way to reconcile Marx's views of religion with those of Gutierrez, they are simply incompatible. Despite this, in terms of their understanding of the necessity of a just and righteous world, and the nearly inevitable obstructions along such a path, the two have much in common; and, particularly in the first edition of [A Theology of Liberation], the use of Marxian theory is quite evident."<ref>Sarah Kleeb, "[https://www.academia.edu/172232/Envisioning_Emancipation_Karl_Marx_Gustavo_Gutierrez_and_the_Struggle_of_Liberation_Theology Envisioning Emancipation: Karl Marx, Gustavo Gutierrez, and the Struggle of Liberation Theology]{{dead link|date=November 2017 |bot=Checkingfax |fix-attempted=yes }}"; Presented at the Annual Meeting of the Canadian Society for the Study of Religion (CSSR), Toronto, 2006. Retrieved 22 October 2012. {{dead link|date=December 2012}}</ref>
Other noted exponents are [[Leonardo Boff]] of Brazil, [[Carlos Mugica]] of Argentina, [[Jon Sobrino]] of El Salvador, and [[Juan Luis Segundo]] of Uruguay.<ref>Richard P. McBrien, ''Catholicism'' (Harper Collins, 1994), chapter IV.</ref><ref>Gustavo Gutierrez, ''A Theology of Liberation'', First (Spanish) edition published in Lima, Peru, 1971; first English edition published by Orbis Books (Maryknoll, New York), 1973.</ref>
=== Health care ===
Social justice has more recently made its way into the field of [[bioethics]]. Discussion involves topics such as affordable access to health care, especially for low income households and families. The discussion also raises questions such as whether society should bear healthcare costs for low income families, and whether the global marketplace is the best way to distribute healthcare. [[Ruth Faden]] of the [[Johns Hopkins Berman Institute of Bioethics]] and Madison Powers of Georgetown University focus their analysis of social justice on which inequalities matter the most. They develop a social justice theory that answers some of these questions in concrete settings.
Social injustices occur when there is a preventable difference in health states among a population of people. These social injustices take the form of [[health inequities]] when negative health states such as malnourishment, and infectious diseases are more prevalent in impoverished nations.<ref>Farmer, Paul E., Bruce Nizeye, Sara Stulac, and Salmaan Keshavjee. 2006. Structural Violence and Clinical Medicine. PLoS Medicine, 1686–1691</ref> These negative health states can often be prevented by providing social and economic structures such as primary healthcare which ensures the general population has equal access to health care services regardless of income level, gender, education or any other stratifying factors. Integrating social justice with health inherently reflects the social determinants of health model without discounting the role of the bio-medical model.<ref>Cueto, Marcos. 2004. The ORIGINS of Primary Health Care and SELECTIVE Primary Health Care. Am J Public Health 94 (11):1868</ref>
=== Health inequalities ===
The sources of health inequalities are rooted in injustices associated with racism, sex discrimination, and social class. Richard Hofrichter and his colleagues examine the political implications of various perspectives used to explain health inequities and explore alternative strategies for eliminating them.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Hofrichter, Richard (Editor)|title=Health and social justice: Politics, ideology, and inequity in the distribution of disease|publisher=Jossey-Bass|year=2003|isbn=9780787967338|location=San Francisco, CA|pages=}}</ref>
=== Human rights education ===
{{Main|Human rights education}}
The [[Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action]] affirm that "Human rights education should include peace, democracy, development and social justice, as set forth in [[international human rights instruments|international and regional human rights instruments]], to achieve common understanding and awareness to strengthen universal commitment to human rights."<ref>Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, Part II, paragraph 80</ref>
=== Ecology and environment ===
{{Main|Climate justice|environmental justice}}
Social justice principles are embedded in the larger environmental movement. The third principle of the Earth Charter is social and economic justice, which is described as seeking to eradicate poverty as an ethical, social, and environmental imperative, ensure that economic activities and institutions at all levels promote human development in an equitable and sustainable manner, affirm gender equality and equity as prerequisites to sustainable development and ensure universal access to education, health care, and economic opportunity, and uphold the right of all, without discrimination, to a natural and social environment supportive of human dignity, bodily health, and spiritual well-being, with special attention to the rights of indigenous peoples and minorities.
The [[climate justice]] and [[environmental justice]] movements also incorporate social justice principles, ideas, and practices. Climate justice and environmental justice, as movements within the larger ecological and environmental movement, each incorporate social justice in a particular way. Climate justice includes concern for social justice pertaining to greenhouse gas emissions,<ref>EA Posner and CR Sunstein [http://www.ericposner.com/GWSJ.pdf Global Warming and Social Justice]</ref> climate-induced environmental displacement,<ref>JS Mastaler [https://www.liebertpub.com/doi/full/10.1089/env.2018.0029 Social Justice and Environmental Displacement]</ref> as well as climate change mitigation and adaptation. Environmental justice includes concern for social justice pertaining to either environmental benefits<ref>A Dahlberg, R Rohde, K Sandell (2010) [http://www.conservationandsociety.org/article.asp?issn=0972-4923;year=2010;volume=8;issue=3;spage=209;epage=224;aulast=Dahlberg National Parks and Environmental Justice: Comparing Access Rights and Ideological Legacies in Three Countries] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190301013315/http://www.conservationandsociety.org/article.asp?issn=0972-4923;year=2010;volume=8;issue=3;spage=209;epage=224;aulast=Dahlberg |date=1 March 2019 }} 8, no. 3 pp.209-224</ref> or environmental pollution<ref>RD Bullard (2005) ''The Quest for Environmental Justice: Human Rights and the Politics of Pollution'' (Counterpoint) {{ISBN|978-1578051205}}</ref> based on their equitable distribution across communities of color, communities of various socio and economic stratification, or any other barriers to justice.
== Criticism ==
[[Michael Novak]] argues that social justice has seldom been adequately defined, arguing:
{{blockquote|[W]hole books and treatises have been written about social justice without ever defining it. It is allowed to float in the air as if everyone will recognize an instance of it when it appears. This vagueness seems indispensable. The minute one begins to define social justice, one runs into embarrassing intellectual difficulties. It becomes, most often, a term of art whose operational meaning is, "We need a law against that." In other words, it becomes an instrument of ideological intimidation, for the purpose of gaining the power of legal coercion.<ref name="Novak, Michael 2000">Novak, Michael. "Defining social justice." First things (2000): 11-12.</ref>}}
[[Friedrich Hayek]] of the [[Austrian School]] of economics rejected the very idea of social justice as meaningless, self-contradictory, and ideological, believing that to realize any degree of social justice is unfeasible, and that the attempt to do so must destroy all liberty:
{{blockquote|There can be no test by which we can discover what is 'socially unjust' because there is no subject by which such an injustice can be committed, and there are no rules of individual conduct the observance of which in the market order would secure to the individuals and groups the position which as such (as distinguished from the procedure by which it is determined) would appear just to us. [Social justice] does not belong to the category of error but to that of nonsense, like the term 'a moral stone'.<ref>Hayek, F.A. (1982). ''Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 2''. Routledge. p. 78.</ref>}}
Hayek argued that proponents of social justice often present it as a moral virtue but most of their descriptions pertain to impersonal states of affairs (e.g. income inequality, poverty), which are cited as "social injustice." Hayek argued that social justice is either a virtue or it is not. If it is, it can only be ascribed to the actions of individuals. However, most who use the term ascribe it to social systems, so "social justice" in fact describes a regulative principle of order; they are interested not in virtue but power.<ref name="Novak, Michael 2000"/> For Hayek, this notion of social justices presupposes that people are guided by specific external directions rather than internal, personal rules of just conduct. It further presupposes that one can never be held accountable for ones own behaviour, as this would be "blaming the victim." According to Hayek, the function of social justice is to blame someone else, often attributed to "the system" or those who are supposed, mythically, to control it. Thus it is based on the appealing idea of "you suffer; your suffering is caused by powerful others; these oppressors must be destroyed."<ref name="Novak, Michael 2000"/>
Ben O'Neill of the [[University of New South Wales]] and the [[Mises Institute]] argues:
{{blockquote|[For advocates of "social justice"] the notion of "rights" is a mere term of entitlement, indicative of a claim for any possible desirable good, no matter how important or trivial, abstract or tangible, recent or ancient. It is merely an assertion of desire, and a declaration of intention to use the language of rights to acquire said desire.
In fact, since the program of social justice inevitably involves claims for government provision of goods, paid for through the efforts of others, the term actually refers to an intention to use ''force'' to acquire one's desires. Not to earn desirable goods by rational thought and action, production and voluntary exchange, but to go in there and forcibly take goods from those who can supply them!<ref>O'Neill, Ben (16 March 2011) [https://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice The Injustice of Social Justice] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141028092912/http://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice |date=28 October 2014 }}, ''[[Mises Institute]]''</ref>}}
== See also ==
{{cols|colwidth=16em}}
* [[Activism]]
* "[[Beyond Vietnam: A Time to Break Silence]]", one of many [[Sermons and speeches of Martin Luther King Jr.|pro–social justice speeches]] delivered by [[Martin Luther King Jr.]]
* [[Choosing the Common Good]]
* [[Counterculture of the 1960s]]
* [[Economic justice]]
* [[Education for Justice]]
* [[Environmental racism]]
* [[Essentially contested concept]]
* [[Global justice]]
* [[Labour law]] and [[labour rights]]
* [[Left-wing politics]]
* [[Resource justice]]
* [[Right to education]]
* [[Right to health]]
* [[Right to housing]]
* [[Right to social security]]
* [[Social justice art]]
* [[Social justice warrior]]
* [[Social law]]
* [[Social work]]
* [[Solidarity]]
* [[National Union for Social Justice (organization)]]
* [[World Day of Social Justice]]
{{colend}}
* {{Lookfrom}}
* {{in title}}
== References ==
{{reflist}}
== Further reading ==
{{wikiquote}}
{{Library resources box}}
=== Articles ===
* C Pérez-Garzón, '[https://revistas.uexternado.edu.co/index.php/derest/article/view/5907/7607 What is social justice? A new history of its meaning in the transnational legal discourse]' (2019) 43 Revista Derecho del Estado 67-106, originally in Spanish: '[https://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/revderest43&div=1&src=home ¿Qué es justicia social? Una nueva historia de su significado en el discurso jurídico transnacional]'
*[[LD Brandeis]], 'The Living Law' (1915–1916) 10 Illinois Law Review 461
* A Etzioni, '[http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/etzioni/documents/A348-TheFairSociety.pdf The Fair Society, Uniting America: Restoring the Vital Center to American Democracy] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150924041156/http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/etzioni/documents/A348-TheFairSociety.pdf |date=24 September 2015 }}' in N Garfinkle and D Yankelovich (eds) (Yale University Press 2005) pp. 211–223
* [[Otto von Gierke]], ''[https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2861875 The Social Role of Private Law]'' (2016) translated and introduced by E McGaughey, originally in German ''[[Die soziale Aufgabe des Privatrechts]]''
* M Novak, '[https://www.firstthings.com/article/2000/12/defining-social-justice Defining Social Justice]' (2000) First Things
* B O'Neill, '[https://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice The Injustice of Social Justice]' ([[Mises Institute]])
* [[R Pound]], 'Social Justice and Legal Justice' (1912) 75 Central Law Journal 455
* M Powers and R Faden, '[https://courses.edx.org/c4x/GeorgetownX/phlx101-01/asset/10.2powers_faden.pdf Inequalities in health, inequalities in health care: four generations of discussion about justice and cost-effectiveness analysis]' (2000) 10(2) Kennedy Inst Ethics Journal 109–127
* M Powers and R Faden, 'Racial and Ethnic Disparities in Health Care: An Ethical Analysis of When and How They Matter,' in ''Unequal Treatment: Confronting Racial and Ethnic Disparities in Health Care'' (National Academy of Sciences, Institute of Medicine, 2002) 722–38
* United Nations, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, 'Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations' (2006) [https://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf ST/ESA/305]
=== Books ===
* [[AB Atkinson]], ''Social Justice and Public Policy'' (1982) [https://books.google.com/books?lr=&id=UiZ2HdkNHBAC&oi=fnd&pg=PP11&dq=%22Social+Justice+and+Public+Policy%22&ots=-6iPmku71A&sig=yACP-Kt6h174KR5dh3lsPDfGX64#PPP1,M1 previews]
* [[Gad Barzilai]], ''Communities and Law: Politics and Cultures of Legal Identities'' (University of Michigan Press) analysis of justice for non-ruling communities
* [[Thomas Nixon Carver|TN Carver]], ''Essays in Social Justice'' (1915) Chapter [https://archive.org/details/essaysinsocialj01carvgoog/page/n17 <!-- pg=3 quote=zDo9sLfoyZ. --> links.]
* [[Carroll Quigley|C Quigley]] ''The Evolution of Civilizations: An Introduction to Historical Analysis'' (1961) 2nd edition 1979
* P Corning, ''[http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/fairness-and-the-social-contract.php The Fair Society: The Science of Human Nature and the Pursuit of Social Justice]'' (Chicago UP 2011)
* WL Droel ''What is Social Justice'' (ACTA Publications 2011)
* R Faden and M Powers, ''Social Justice: The Moral Foundations of Public Health and Health Policy'' ([https://books.google.com/?id=mTLSzjg9yiIC&printsec=frontcover&dq=ISBN9780195189261&cd=1#v=onepage&q&f=false OUP 2006])
* J Franklin (ed), ''Life to the Full: Rights and Social Justice in Australia'' (Connor Court 2007)
* LC Frederking (2013) ''Reconstructing Social Justice'' (Routledge) {{ISBN|978-1138194021}}
* [[FA Hayek]], ''[[Law, Legislation and Liberty]]'' (1973) vol II, ch 3
* [[G Kitching]], ''Seeking Social Justice through Globalization: Escaping a Nationalist Perspective'' (2003)
* [[JS Mill]], ''[[Utilitarianism (book)|Utilitarianism]]'' (1863)
* T Massaro, S.J. ''Living Justice: Catholic Social Teaching in Action'' (Rowman & Littlefield 2012)
* [[John Rawls]], ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'' (Harvard University Press 1971)
* [[John Rawls]], ''[[Political Liberalism]]'' (Columbia University Press 1993)
* C Philomena, B Hoose and G Mannion (eds), ''Social Justice: Theological and Practical Explorations'' (2007)
* [[A Swift]], ''Political Philosophy'' (3rd edn 2013) ch 1
* Michael J. Thompson, ''[https://www.academia.edu/214008/The_Limits_of_Liberalism_A_Republican_Theory_of_Social_Justice The Limits of Liberalism: A Republican Theory of Social Justice]'' (International Journal of Ethics: vol. 7, no. 3 (2011)
{{social work}}
{{types of justice}}
{{subject bar|commons=yes|commons-search=Category:Social justice|q=yes|q-search=Social justice|d=yes|d-search=Q264892}}
{{authority control}}
[[Category:Social justice| ]]
[[Category:Justice]]
[[Category:Social inequality]]
[[Category:Social work]]
[[Category:Liberalism]]
[[Category:Left-wing politics]]
[[Category:Progressivism]]' |
Unified diff of changes made by edit (edit_diff ) | '@@ -21,5 +21,6 @@
* Plato believed rights existed only between free people, and the law should take "account in the first instance of relations of inequality in which individuals are treated in proportion to their worth and only secondarily of relations of equality." Reflecting this time when [[slavery]] and subjugation of women was typical, ancient views of justice tended to reflect the rigid class systems that still prevailed. On the other hand, for the privileged groups, strong concepts of fairness and the community existed. [[Distributive justice]] was said by [[Aristotle]] to require that people were distributed goods and assets according to their merit.<ref>''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' V.3</ref>
[[File:Head of Socrates in Palazzo Massimo alle Terme (Rome).JPG|thumb|upright|Bust of Socrates]]
-* [[Socrates]] (through Plato's dialogue ''[[Crito]]'') is credited with developing the idea of a [[social contract]], whereby people ought to follow the rules of a society, and accept its burdens because they have accepted its benefits.<ref>[[Plato]], ''[[Crito]]'' (ca 380 BC)</ref> During the Middle Ages, religious scholars particularly, such as [[Thomas Aquinas]] continued discussion of justice in various ways, but ultimately connected being a good citizen to the purpose of serving God.
+* [[Socrates]] (through Plato's dialogue ''[[Crito]]'') is credited with developing the idea of a [[social contract]], whereby people ought to follow the rules of a shit
+, and accept its burdens because they have accepted its benefits.<ref>[[Plato]], ''[[Crito]]'' (ca 380 BC)</ref> During the Middle Ages, religious scholars particularly, such as [[Thomas Aquinas]] continued discussion of justice in various ways, but ultimately connected being a good citizen to the purpose of serving God.
After the [[Renaissance]] and [[Reformation]], the modern concept of social justice, as developing human potential, began to emerge through the work of a series of authors. [[Baruch Spinoza]] in ''[[On the Improvement of the Understanding]]'' (1677) contended that the one true aim of life should be to acquire "a human character much more stable than [one's] own", and to achieve this "pitch of perfection... The chief good is that he should arrive, together with other individuals if possible, at the possession of the aforesaid character."<ref>B Spinoza, ''[[On the Improvement of the Understanding]]'' (1677) [[s:On the Improvement of the Understanding#12|para 13]]</ref> During the [[Age of Enlightenment|enlightenment]] and responding to the [[French Revolution|French]] and [[American Revolution]]s, [[Thomas Paine]] similarly wrote in ''[[The Rights of Man]]'' (1792) society should give "genius a fair and universal chance" and so "the construction of government ought to be such as to bring forward... all that extent of capacity which never fails to appear in revolutions."<ref>[[T Paine]], ''[[Rights of Man]]'' (1792) 197</ref>
' |
New page size (new_size ) | 68974 |
Old page size (old_size ) | 68976 |
Size change in edit (edit_delta ) | -2 |
Lines added in edit (added_lines ) | [
0 => '* [[Socrates]] (through Plato's dialogue ''[[Crito]]'') is credited with developing the idea of a [[social contract]], whereby people ought to follow the rules of a shit',
1 => ', and accept its burdens because they have accepted its benefits.<ref>[[Plato]], ''[[Crito]]'' (ca 380 BC)</ref> During the Middle Ages, religious scholars particularly, such as [[Thomas Aquinas]] continued discussion of justice in various ways, but ultimately connected being a good citizen to the purpose of serving God.'
] |
Lines removed in edit (removed_lines ) | [
0 => '* [[Socrates]] (through Plato's dialogue ''[[Crito]]'') is credited with developing the idea of a [[social contract]], whereby people ought to follow the rules of a society, and accept its burdens because they have accepted its benefits.<ref>[[Plato]], ''[[Crito]]'' (ca 380 BC)</ref> During the Middle Ages, religious scholars particularly, such as [[Thomas Aquinas]] continued discussion of justice in various ways, but ultimately connected being a good citizen to the purpose of serving God.'
] |
All external links added in the edit (added_links ) | [] |
All external links removed in the edit (removed_links ) | [] |
All external links in the new text (all_links ) | [
0 => 'https://languages.oup.com/google-dictionary-en/',
1 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8djVCRFoyQTZYS0k',
2 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8eXZMWHU3ckpQVUk',
3 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8V3hpa0V1ekFQZms',
4 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8R2tWbXFmelhzVDA',
5 => '//doi.org/10.1142%2Fs0217590808002896',
6 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MWpSSGRWUllXTEE',
7 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8Qm8zcHRRQ0xFN2c',
8 => '//doi.org/10.1111%2Fsoc4.12162',
9 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MTk1Qkp2b0ZaNDg',
10 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8cTlPd2dzZ3d3TG8',
11 => '//doi.org/10.2224%2Fsbp.2007.35.1.135',
12 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MWRYV0xVUzNlRlU',
13 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8RGJGb0RiZEc0NzA',
14 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8bERZaWVUVGRPLTA',
15 => 'https://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciBhan.htm',
16 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20161005111127/http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciBhan.htm',
17 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20180329054435/https://revistas.juridicas.unam.mx/index.php/mexican-law-review/article/view/11892',
18 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/2448-5306',
19 => 'https://revistas.juridicas.unam.mx/index.php/mexican-law-review/article/view/11892',
20 => 'https://books.google.com/books?id=TnMLHOwjqgMC&q=%22justice+sociale%22&pg=PA311',
21 => 'https://books.google.com/books?id=xzATAAAAYAAJ&q=justice+sociale&pg=PA131',
22 => 'https://books.google.com/books?id=AEBbAAAAcAAJ&q=%22giustizia+sociale%22&pg=PA349',
23 => 'https://w2.vatican.va/content/pius-xi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_enc_19370319_divini-redemptoris.html',
24 => 'http://content.time.com/time/subscriber/article/0,33009,795777,00.html',
25 => 'http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yhrdlj/vol17/iss1/2/',
26 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/1548-2596',
27 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20160304090801/http://www.anh-usa.org/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Sustainability-the-Complete-Concept1.pdf',
28 => 'http://www.anh-usa.org/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Sustainability-the-Complete-Concept1.pdf',
29 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20120824050226/http://ncronline.org/news/ecology/pope-cites-teilhardian-vision-cosmos-living-host',
30 => 'http://ncronline.org/news/ecology/pope-cites-teilhardian-vision-cosmos-living-host',
31 => 'http://chiesa.espresso.repubblica.it/articolo/1341681?eng=y/',
32 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20160304083309/http://chiesa.espresso.repubblica.it/articolo/1341681?eng=y/',
33 => 'http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/',
34 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150919070037/http://thomaspogge.com/books/world-poverty-human-rights/',
35 => 'http://thomaspogge.com/books/world-poverty-human-rights/',
36 => 'http://www.thenation.com/article/181724/resource-privilege#',
37 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150210065716/http://www.thenation.com/article/181724/resource-privilege',
38 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150210074345/http://thomaspogge.com/human-rights-and-just-taxation-global-financial-transparency/',
39 => 'http://thomaspogge.com/human-rights-and-just-taxation-global-financial-transparency/',
40 => 'https://www.un.org/en/events/socialjusticeday/index.shtml',
41 => 'https://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf',
42 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20170829123826/http://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf',
43 => 'https://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/crc.aspx',
44 => 'http://content.time.com/time/nation/article/0,8599,1992463-1,00.html',
45 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/0040-781X',
46 => 'https://books.google.com/books?id=uSHC3qDjFS4C&pg=PA285',
47 => 'http://www.brycchancarey.com/abolition/index.htm',
48 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20160129112229/http://brycchancarey.com/abolition/index.htm',
49 => 'http://gbgm-umc.org/umw/wesley/thoughtsuponslavery.stm',
50 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20141016083225/http://gbgm-umc.org/umw/wesley/thoughtsuponslavery.stm',
51 => 'https://www.ffmc.org/do-justice',
52 => 'http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467671¬oc=1',
53 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20131206020517/http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467671¬oc=1',
54 => 'http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467635¬oc=1',
55 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20131206012803/http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467635¬oc=1',
56 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20070608113958/http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/projects/socialteaching/excerpt.htm',
57 => 'http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/projects/socialteaching/excerpt.htm',
58 => 'http://www.osjspm.org/cst/themes.htm',
59 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20060216183419/http://www.osjspm.org/cst/themes.htm',
60 => 'https://www.vatican.va/archive/ccc_css/archive/catechism/p3s1c2a3.htm',
61 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20131105063620/https://www.vatican.va/archive/ccc_css/archive/catechism/p3s1c2a3.htm',
62 => 'http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/karnataka/caste-system-hindering-the-goal-of-social-justice-cm/article6822818.ece',
63 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150904050652/http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/karnataka/caste-system-hindering-the-goal-of-social-justice-cm/article6822818.ece',
64 => 'http://www.oah.org/pubs/nl/2007nov/shaffer.html',
65 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20130904165644/http://www.oah.org/pubs/nl/2007nov/shaffer.html',
66 => 'https://www.academia.edu/172232/Envisioning_Emancipation_Karl_Marx_Gustavo_Gutierrez_and_the_Struggle_of_Liberation_Theology',
67 => 'http://www.ericposner.com/GWSJ.pdf',
68 => 'https://www.liebertpub.com/doi/full/10.1089/env.2018.0029',
69 => 'http://www.conservationandsociety.org/article.asp?issn=0972-4923;year=2010;volume=8;issue=3;spage=209;epage=224;aulast=Dahlberg',
70 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20190301013315/http://www.conservationandsociety.org/article.asp?issn=0972-4923;year=2010;volume=8;issue=3;spage=209;epage=224;aulast=Dahlberg',
71 => 'https://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice',
72 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20141028092912/http://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice',
73 => 'https://www.wikidata.org/wiki/Q264892#identifiers',
74 => 'https://ftl.toolforge.org/cgi-bin/ftl?st=wp&su=Social+justice',
75 => 'https://ftl.toolforge.org/cgi-bin/ftl?st=wp&su=Social+justice&library=0CHOOSE0',
76 => 'https://revistas.uexternado.edu.co/index.php/derest/article/view/5907/7607',
77 => 'https://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/revderest43&div=1&src=home',
78 => 'http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/etzioni/documents/A348-TheFairSociety.pdf',
79 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150924041156/http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/etzioni/documents/A348-TheFairSociety.pdf',
80 => 'https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2861875',
81 => 'https://www.firstthings.com/article/2000/12/defining-social-justice',
82 => 'https://courses.edx.org/c4x/GeorgetownX/phlx101-01/asset/10.2powers_faden.pdf',
83 => 'https://books.google.com/books?lr=&id=UiZ2HdkNHBAC&oi=fnd&pg=PP11&dq=%22Social+Justice+and+Public+Policy%22&ots=-6iPmku71A&sig=yACP-Kt6h174KR5dh3lsPDfGX64#PPP1,M1',
84 => 'https://archive.org/details/essaysinsocialj01carvgoog/page/n17',
85 => 'http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/fairness-and-the-social-contract.php',
86 => 'https://books.google.com/?id=mTLSzjg9yiIC&printsec=frontcover&dq=ISBN9780195189261&cd=1#v=onepage&q&f=false',
87 => 'https://www.academia.edu/214008/The_Limits_of_Liberalism_A_Republican_Theory_of_Social_Justice',
88 => 'https://catalogue.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb11956289g',
89 => 'https://data.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb11956289g',
90 => 'https://d-nb.info/gnd/4236433-4',
91 => 'http://uli.nli.org.il/F/?func=find-b&local_base=NLX10&find_code=UID&request=987007551038205171',
92 => 'https://id.loc.gov/authorities/subjects/sh85123969'
] |
Links in the page, before the edit (old_links ) | [
0 => '//doi.org/10.1111%2Fsoc4.12162',
1 => '//doi.org/10.1111%2Fsoc4.12162',
2 => '//doi.org/10.1142%2Fs0217590808002896',
3 => '//doi.org/10.1142%2Fs0217590808002896',
4 => '//doi.org/10.2224%2Fsbp.2007.35.1.135',
5 => '//doi.org/10.2224%2Fsbp.2007.35.1.135',
6 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/0040-781X',
7 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/0040-781X',
8 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/1548-2596',
9 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/1548-2596',
10 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/2448-5306',
11 => '//www.worldcat.org/issn/2448-5306',
12 => 'http://chiesa.espresso.repubblica.it/articolo/1341681?eng=y/',
13 => 'http://content.time.com/time/nation/article/0,8599,1992463-1,00.html',
14 => 'http://content.time.com/time/subscriber/article/0,33009,795777,00.html',
15 => 'http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yhrdlj/vol17/iss1/2/',
16 => 'http://gbgm-umc.org/umw/wesley/thoughtsuponslavery.stm',
17 => 'http://ncronline.org/news/ecology/pope-cites-teilhardian-vision-cosmos-living-host',
18 => 'http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/',
19 => 'http://thomaspogge.com/books/world-poverty-human-rights/',
20 => 'http://thomaspogge.com/human-rights-and-just-taxation-global-financial-transparency/',
21 => 'http://uli.nli.org.il/F/?func=find-b&local_base=NLX10&find_code=UID&request=987007551038205171',
22 => 'http://www.anh-usa.org/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Sustainability-the-Complete-Concept1.pdf',
23 => 'http://www.brycchancarey.com/abolition/index.htm',
24 => 'http://www.conservationandsociety.org/article.asp?issn=0972-4923;year=2010;volume=8;issue=3;spage=209;epage=224;aulast=Dahlberg',
25 => 'http://www.ericposner.com/GWSJ.pdf',
26 => 'http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/etzioni/documents/A348-TheFairSociety.pdf',
27 => 'http://www.oah.org/pubs/nl/2007nov/shaffer.html',
28 => 'http://www.osjspm.org/cst/themes.htm',
29 => 'http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/karnataka/caste-system-hindering-the-goal-of-social-justice-cm/article6822818.ece',
30 => 'http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/fairness-and-the-social-contract.php',
31 => 'http://www.thenation.com/article/181724/resource-privilege#',
32 => 'http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467671¬oc=1',
33 => 'http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467635¬oc=1',
34 => 'http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/projects/socialteaching/excerpt.htm',
35 => 'https://archive.org/details/essaysinsocialj01carvgoog/page/n17',
36 => 'https://books.google.com/?id=mTLSzjg9yiIC&printsec=frontcover&dq=ISBN9780195189261&cd=1#v=onepage&q&f=false',
37 => 'https://books.google.com/books?id=AEBbAAAAcAAJ&q=%22giustizia+sociale%22&pg=PA349',
38 => 'https://books.google.com/books?id=TnMLHOwjqgMC&q=%22justice+sociale%22&pg=PA311',
39 => 'https://books.google.com/books?id=uSHC3qDjFS4C&pg=PA285',
40 => 'https://books.google.com/books?id=xzATAAAAYAAJ&q=justice+sociale&pg=PA131',
41 => 'https://books.google.com/books?lr=&id=UiZ2HdkNHBAC&oi=fnd&pg=PP11&dq=%22Social+Justice+and+Public+Policy%22&ots=-6iPmku71A&sig=yACP-Kt6h174KR5dh3lsPDfGX64#PPP1,M1',
42 => 'https://catalogue.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb11956289g',
43 => 'https://courses.edx.org/c4x/GeorgetownX/phlx101-01/asset/10.2powers_faden.pdf',
44 => 'https://d-nb.info/gnd/4236433-4',
45 => 'https://data.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb11956289g',
46 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8cTlPd2dzZ3d3TG8',
47 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MWRYV0xVUzNlRlU',
48 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8RGJGb0RiZEc0NzA',
49 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8bERZaWVUVGRPLTA',
50 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8djVCRFoyQTZYS0k',
51 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8eXZMWHU3ckpQVUk',
52 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8V3hpa0V1ekFQZms',
53 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8R2tWbXFmelhzVDA',
54 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8Qm8zcHRRQ0xFN2c',
55 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MTk1Qkp2b0ZaNDg',
56 => 'https://drive.google.com/open?id=0B5cQDUWg9Kd8MWpSSGRWUllXTEE',
57 => 'https://ftl.toolforge.org/cgi-bin/ftl?st=wp&su=Social+justice',
58 => 'https://ftl.toolforge.org/cgi-bin/ftl?st=wp&su=Social+justice&library=0CHOOSE0',
59 => 'https://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/revderest43&div=1&src=home',
60 => 'https://id.loc.gov/authorities/subjects/sh85123969',
61 => 'https://languages.oup.com/google-dictionary-en/',
62 => 'https://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice',
63 => 'https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2861875',
64 => 'https://revistas.juridicas.unam.mx/index.php/mexican-law-review/article/view/11892',
65 => 'https://revistas.uexternado.edu.co/index.php/derest/article/view/5907/7607',
66 => 'https://w2.vatican.va/content/pius-xi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_enc_19370319_divini-redemptoris.html',
67 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20060216183419/http://www.osjspm.org/cst/themes.htm',
68 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20070608113958/http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/projects/socialteaching/excerpt.htm',
69 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20120824050226/http://ncronline.org/news/ecology/pope-cites-teilhardian-vision-cosmos-living-host',
70 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20130904165644/http://www.oah.org/pubs/nl/2007nov/shaffer.html',
71 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20131105063620/https://www.vatican.va/archive/ccc_css/archive/catechism/p3s1c2a3.htm',
72 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20131206012803/http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467635¬oc=1',
73 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20131206020517/http://www.umc.org/site/apps/nlnet/content.aspx?c=lwL4KnN1LtH&b=5066539&ct=6467671¬oc=1',
74 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20141016083225/http://gbgm-umc.org/umw/wesley/thoughtsuponslavery.stm',
75 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20141028092912/http://mises.org/daily/5099/The-Injustice-of-Social-Justice',
76 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150210065716/http://www.thenation.com/article/181724/resource-privilege',
77 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150210074345/http://thomaspogge.com/human-rights-and-just-taxation-global-financial-transparency/',
78 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150904050652/http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/karnataka/caste-system-hindering-the-goal-of-social-justice-cm/article6822818.ece',
79 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150919070037/http://thomaspogge.com/books/world-poverty-human-rights/',
80 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20150924041156/http://www.gwu.edu/~ccps/etzioni/documents/A348-TheFairSociety.pdf',
81 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20160129112229/http://brycchancarey.com/abolition/index.htm',
82 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20160304083309/http://chiesa.espresso.repubblica.it/articolo/1341681?eng=y/',
83 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20160304090801/http://www.anh-usa.org/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Sustainability-the-Complete-Concept1.pdf',
84 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20161005111127/http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciBhan.htm',
85 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20170829123826/http://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf',
86 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20180329054435/https://revistas.juridicas.unam.mx/index.php/mexican-law-review/article/view/11892',
87 => 'https://web.archive.org/web/20190301013315/http://www.conservationandsociety.org/article.asp?issn=0972-4923;year=2010;volume=8;issue=3;spage=209;epage=224;aulast=Dahlberg',
88 => 'https://www.academia.edu/172232/Envisioning_Emancipation_Karl_Marx_Gustavo_Gutierrez_and_the_Struggle_of_Liberation_Theology',
89 => 'https://www.academia.edu/214008/The_Limits_of_Liberalism_A_Republican_Theory_of_Social_Justice',
90 => 'https://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciBhan.htm',
91 => 'https://www.ffmc.org/do-justice',
92 => 'https://www.firstthings.com/article/2000/12/defining-social-justice',
93 => 'https://www.liebertpub.com/doi/full/10.1089/env.2018.0029',
94 => 'https://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/crc.aspx',
95 => 'https://www.un.org/en/events/socialjusticeday/index.shtml',
96 => 'https://www.un.org/esa/socdev/documents/ifsd/SocialJustice.pdf',
97 => 'https://www.vatican.va/archive/ccc_css/archive/catechism/p3s1c2a3.htm',
98 => 'https://www.wikidata.org/wiki/Q264892#identifiers'
] |
Whether or not the change was made through a Tor exit node (tor_exit_node ) | false |
Unix timestamp of change (timestamp ) | 1650380346 |