Jump to content

Edit filter log

Details for log entry 21137996

00:27, 13 May 2018: VitalPower (talk | contribs) triggered filter 249, performing the action "edit" on Burden of proof (philosophy). Actions taken: Tag; Filter description: New user conducting large scale reverts (examine | diff)

Changes made in edit





stop changes my changes. Swagmathorn, peacing out, once again.
stop changing my changes. Swagmathorn, peacing out, once again.




Action parameters

VariableValue
Whether or not the edit is marked as minor (no longer in use) (minor_edit)
false
Edit count of the user (user_editcount)
206
Name of the user account (user_name)
'VitalPower'
Age of the user account (user_age)
122179
Groups (including implicit) the user is in (user_groups)
[ 0 => '*', 1 => 'user' ]
Rights that the user has (user_rights)
[ 0 => 'createaccount', 1 => 'read', 2 => 'edit', 3 => 'createtalk', 4 => 'writeapi', 5 => 'viewmywatchlist', 6 => 'editmywatchlist', 7 => 'viewmyprivateinfo', 8 => 'editmyprivateinfo', 9 => 'editmyoptions', 10 => 'abusefilter-view', 11 => 'abusefilter-log', 12 => 'abusefilter-log-detail', 13 => 'centralauth-merge', 14 => 'vipsscaler-test', 15 => 'ep-bereviewer', 16 => 'collectionsaveasuserpage', 17 => 'reupload-own', 18 => 'move-rootuserpages', 19 => 'move-categorypages', 20 => 'createpage', 21 => 'minoredit', 22 => 'editmyusercss', 23 => 'editmyuserjson', 24 => 'editmyuserjs', 25 => 'purge', 26 => 'sendemail', 27 => 'applychangetags', 28 => 'spamblacklistlog', 29 => 'ep-enroll', 30 => 'mwoauthmanagemygrants' ]
Whether or not a user is editing through the mobile interface (user_mobile)
false
Page ID (page_id)
26221613
Page namespace (page_namespace)
0
Page title without namespace (page_title)
'Burden of proof (philosophy)'
Full page title (page_prefixedtitle)
'Burden of proof (philosophy)'
Last ten users to contribute to the page (page_recent_contributors)
[ 0 => 'VitalPower', 1 => 'Agorlwhomst', 2 => 'ClueBot NG', 3 => 'GliderMaven', 4 => 'Editor85213', 5 => '198.84.253.202', 6 => 'Crawiki', 7 => '86.135.221.92', 8 => 'Onel5969', 9 => 'Arjayay' ]
Action (action)
'edit'
Edit summary/reason (summary)
'Undid revision 840928732 by [[Special:Contributions/VitalPower|VitalPower]] ([[User talk:VitalPower|talk]])'
Old content model (old_content_model)
'wikitext'
New content model (new_content_model)
'wikitext'
Old page wikitext, before the edit (old_wikitext)
' stop changes my changes. Swagmathorn, peacing out, once again. {{about|burden of proof as a philosophical concept|other uses|Burden of proof (disambiguation)}} The '''burden of proof''' ([[Latin language|Latin]]: '''''onus probandi''''', shortened from ''Onus probandi incumbit ei qui dicit, non ei qui negat'') is the obligation on a party in a dispute to provide sufficient [[warrant (philosophy)|warrant]] for their position. ==Holder of the burden== When two parties are in a discussion and one makes a claim <!-- DO NOT ADD THE WORD "positive" HERE. There is no logical distinction between positive and negative claims -->that the other disputes, the one who makes the claim typically has a ''burden of proof'' to justify or substantiate that claim especially when it challenges a perceived status quo.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Cargile |first=James | date=January 1997 |title=On the burden of proof |journal=[[Philosophy (journal)|Philosophy]] |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |volume=72 |issue=279 |pages=59–83 |doi=10.1017/s0031819100056655}}</ref> This is also stated in [[Hitchens's razor]]. Carl Sagan proposed a related criteria, the [[Sagan standard]], "extraordinary claims require extraordinary evidence".<ref>Marc Kaufman, ''First Contact: Scientific Breakthroughs in the Hunt for Life Beyond Earth'', Simon and Schuster, p. 124.</ref> While certain kinds of arguments, such as logical [[syllogism]]s, require [[Mathematical proof|mathematical]] or strictly [[Formal proof|logical proof]]s, the standard for [[evidence]] to meet the burden of proof is usually determined by context and community standards and conventions.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Leite |first=Adam |year=2005 |title=A localist solution to the regress of justification |journal=[[Australasian Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=83 |issue=3 |pages=395–421 [p. 418] |doi=10.1080/00048400500191974 |quote=[t]he point of articulating reasons in defense of one's belief is to establish that one is justified in believing as one does. }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Leite |first=Adam |year=2005 |title=A localist solution to the regress of justification |journal=[[Australasian Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=83 |issue=3 |pages=395–421 [p. 403] |doi=10.1080/00048400500191974 |quote=justificatory conversation...[is]...characterized by a person's sincere attempt to vindicate his or her entitlement to a belief by providing adequate reasons in its defense and responding to objections. }}</ref> Philosophical debate can devolve into arguing about who has the burden of proof about a particular claim. This has been described as "burden tennis" or the "onus game".<ref>{{cite journal |last=Dennett |first=Daniel C. |authorlink=Daniel Dennett |date=July 1988 |title=Review of ''Psychosemantics'' by Jerry Fodor |journal=[[The Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=85 |issue=7 |pages=384–389 (389) |doi=10.2307/2026956 |url=http://cogprints.org/253/1/fodor.htm |jstor=2026956 |quote=Fodor is too wise to think his series of arguments can flat disprove the claims of the opposition, so time and again he resorts to claims about shifting the burden of proof, begging the question, outsmarting by embracing the conclusions of reductios, and other exploitations of the rules of the game. The book is a tireless exercise of that philosopher's pasttime, burden-tennis. Burden, burden, who has the burden of proof now? Fodor mostly plays solitaire burden-tennis, against an imaginary opponent often personified as Granny or Aunty, which permits him to express the opposition view in terms that suit his rebuttal, without having to address the issue of whether this is a sympathetic rendering of any real opponent's claims.}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Rodych |first=Victor |date=1996 |origyear=1986 |chapter=Wittgenstein's inversion of Gödel's theorem |editor1-last=Shanker |editor1-first=Stuart |editor1-link=Stuart Shanker |editor2-last=Kilfoyle |editor2-first=David |title=Ludwig Wittgenstein: critical assessments |volume=2. The later Wittgenstein: from ''Philosophical investigations'' to ''On certainty'' |location=London; New York |publisher=[[Routledge]] |pages=232–265 ([//books.google.com/books?id=1MQaXJHzBooC&pg=PA261 261]) |isbn=0415149150 |oclc=47938413 |quote=Thus, in 1991 Wang seems to understand ''why'' Wittgenstein rejects GIT, but, apparently favouring the "onus game" (or "burden tennis"), he unfortunately concludes (pp. 257–58) that "the burden of proof falls ... squarely on Wittgenstein's side" because of Wang's own 'principle of presumed innocence'.}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Abelson |first=Robert P. |authorlink=Robert Abelson |date=1995 |chapter=Credibility of argument |title=Statistics as principled argument |location=Hillsdale, NJ |publisher=[[Lawrence Erlbaum Associates]] |page=[//books.google.com/books?id=yQLFl1ILjZwC&pg=PA170 170] |isbn=0805805273 |oclc=31011850 |quote=When research presentations advance claims that many or most readers deem incredible, these claims are vulnerable to severe challenge. In response, there will typically be a rebuttal by the investigator, and then a fresh round of criticism. The burden of proof shifts back and forth between the investigator and the critic in what might be called the game of 'burden tennis'.}}</ref> ==Shifting the burden of proof== One way in which one would attempt to shift the burden of proof is by committing a logical fallacy known as the [[argument from ignorance]]. It occurs when either a [[proposition]] is assumed to be true because it has not yet been proved false or a proposition is assumed to be false because it has not yet been proved true.<ref>{{cite web|title= Argumentum ad Ignorantiam|url= http://philosophy.lander.edu/logic/ignorance.html|work= Philosophy 103: Introduction to Logic|publisher= [[Lander University]]|year= 2004|accessdate= 2009-04-29| archiveurl= https://web.archive.org/web/20090430170946/http://philosophy.lander.edu/logic/ignorance.html| archivedate= 30 April 2009 <!--DASHBot-->| deadurl= no}}</ref><ref>{{cite encyclopedia | first=Bradley | last=Dowden | encyclopedia=[[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] | title=Appeal to ignorance | url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/fallacy/#AppealtoIgnorance | accessdate=2016-02-24}}</ref> ==Proving a negative== A [[affirmative and negative|negative]] claim is a colloquialism for an affirmative claim that asserts the non-existence or exclusion of something.<ref name="Hales">{{cite journal |last=Hales |first=Steven D. |date=Summer 2005 |title=Thinking tools: You ''can'' prove a negative |journal=[[Think (journal)|Think]] |volume=4 |issue=10 |pages=109–112 |doi=10.1017/S1477175600001287 |url=http://departments.bloomu.edu/philosophy/pages/content/hales/articlepdf/proveanegative.pdf |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]]}}</ref> Saying "You cannot prove a negative" has been called pseudologic because there are many proofs that substantiate negative claims in mathematics, science, and economics including [[Arrow's impossibility theorem]]. There can be multiple claims within a [[debate]]. Nevertheless, it has been said whoever makes a claim carries the burden of proof regardless of positive or negative content in the claim. A negative claim may or may not exist as a counterpoint to a previous claim. A [[proof of impossibility]] or an [[evidence of absence]] argument are typical methods to fulfill the burden of proof for a negative claim.<ref name="Hales"/><ref>{{cite book |last=Damer |first=T. Edward |authorlink=T. Edward Damer |title=[[Attacking Faulty Reasoning|Attacking faulty reasoning: a practical guide to fallacy-free arguments]] | publisher=[[Cengage Learning]] |year=2009 |page=[//books.google.com/?id=-qZabUx0FmkC&pg=PA17 17] |isbn=9780495095064 }}</ref> ==Application== ===In public discourse=== Burden of proof is also an important concept in the [[public sphere|public arena of ideas]]. Once participants in discourse establish common [[Presupposition|assumption]]s, the mechanism of burden of proof helps to ensure that all parties contribute productively, using relevant arguments.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Goldman |first=Alvin |year=1994 |title=Argumentation and social epistemology |journal=[[The Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=91 |issue=1 |pages=27–49 |jstor=2940949 |doi=10.2307/2940949}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=van Eemeren |first=Frans H. |authorlink1=Frans H. van Eemeren |last2=Grootendorst |first2=Rob |authorlink2=Rob Grootendorst |year=2004 |title=A systematic theory of argumentation |location=Cambridge, UK; New York |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |isbn=0521830753 |page=60 |quote=[t]here is no point in venturing to resolve a difference of opinion through an argumentative exchange of views if there is no mutual commitment to a common starting point. }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Brandom |first=Robert |year=1994 |title=Making it explicit |location=Cambridge, MA |publisher=[[Harvard University Press]] |page=222 |isbn=067454319X |quote=[t]here are sentence types that would require a great deal of work for one to get into a position to challenge, such as 'Red is a color,' 'There have been black dogs,' 'Lighting frequently precedes thunder,' and similar commonplaces. These are treated as 'free moves' by members of our speech community—they are available to just about anyone any time to use as premises, to assert unchallenged. }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Adler |first=Jonathan E. |year=2002 |title=Belief's own ethics |location=Cambridge, MA |publisher=[[MIT Press]] |pages=164–167 |isbn=0262011921}}</ref> ===In law=== {{main|Burden of proof (law)}} The legal burden of proof ({{lang-la|onus probandi}}) is the obligation of a [[party (law)|party]] in a [[trial]] to produce the [[evidence]] that will prove the claims they have made against the other party. In a legal dispute, one party is initially presumed to be correct and gets the benefit of the doubt, while the other side bears the burden of proof. When a party bearing the burden of proof meets their burden, the burden of proof switches to the other side. Burdens may be of different kinds for each party, in different phases of litigation. The [[Prima facie|burden of production]] is a minimal burden to produce at least enough evidence for the [[trier of fact]] to ''consider'' a disputed claim.<ref name=CL>''Criminal Law - Cases and Materials'', 7th ed. 2012, [[Wolters Kluwer Law & Business]]; [[John Kaplan (law professor)|John Kaplan]], [[Robert Weisberg]], Guyora Binder, {{ISBN|978-1-4548-0698-1}}, [https://law.stanford.edu/publications/criminal-law-cases-and-materials-7th-edition/]</ref>{{rp|16–17}} After litigants have met the burden of production and their claim is being considered by a trier of fact, they have the burden of persuasion, that enough evidence has been presented to persuade the trier of fact that their side is correct. There are different ''standards'' of persuasiveness ranging from a [[preponderance of the evidence]], where there is just enough evidence to tip the balance, to proof beyond a reasonable doubt, as in United States criminal courts.<ref name="CL"/>{{rp|17}} The burden of proof is usually on the person who brings a claim in a dispute. It is often associated with the Latin [[Maxim (philosophy)|maxim]] ''semper necessitas probandi incumbit ei qui agit'', a translation of which in this context is: "the necessity of proof always lies with the person who lays charges."<ref>Transnational principle of law: [http://www.trans-lex.org/966000 Trans-Lex.org]</ref> The party that does not carry the burden of proof carries the benefit of assumption of being correct, they are presumed to be correct, until the burden shifts after presentation of evidence by the party bringing the action. An example is in an American [[criminal case]], where there is a [[presumption of innocence]] by the [[defendant]]. Fulfilling the burden of proof effectively captures the benefit of assumption, passing the burden of proof off to another party. ===In statistics=== {{main|Null hypothesis}} In [[inferential statistics]], the null hypothesis is a general statement or default position that there is no relationship between two measured phenomena, or no association among groups.<ref>{{cite book | last = Everitt | first = Brian | title = The Cambridge Dictionary of Statistics | publisher = Cambridge University Press | location = Cambridge, UK New York | year = 1998 | isbn = 0521593468 }}</ref> Rejecting or disproving the null [[hypothesis]]—and thus concluding that there are grounds for believing that there ''is'' a relationship between two phenomena (e.g. that a potential treatment has a measurable effect)—is a central task in the modern practice of science; the field of statistics gives precise criteria for rejecting a null hypothesis{{citation needed|date=December 2017}}. The null hypothesis is generally assumed to be true until evidence indicates otherwise. In statistics, it is often denoted '''''H''<sub>0</sub>''' (read “H-nought”, "H-null", "H-oh", or "H-zero"). The concept of a null hypothesis is used differently in two approaches to statistical inference. In the significance testing approach of [[Ronald Fisher]], a null hypothesis is rejected if the observed data are [[Statistical significance|significantly]] unlikely to have occurred if the null hypothesis were true. In this case the null hypothesis is rejected and an [[alternative hypothesis]] is accepted in its place. If the data are consistent with the null hypothesis, then the null hypothesis is not rejected. In neither case is the null hypothesis or its alternative proven; the null hypothesis is tested with data and a decision is made based on how likely or unlikely the data are. This is analogous to the legal principle of [[presumption of innocence]], in which a suspect or defendant is assumed to be innocent (null is not rejected) until proven guilty (null is rejected) beyond a reasonable doubt (to a statistically significant degree). In the [[Statistical hypothesis testing|hypothesis testing]] approach of [[Jerzy Neyman]] and [[Egon Pearson]], a null hypothesis is contrasted with an alternative hypothesis and the two hypotheses are distinguished on the basis of data, with certain error rates. Proponents of each approach criticize the other approach. Nowadays, though, a hybrid approach is widely practiced and presented in textbooks. The hybrid is in turn criticized as incorrect and incoherent—for details, see [[Statistical hypothesis testing]]. Statistical inference can be done without a null hypothesis, by specifying a [[statistical model]] corresponding to each candidate hypothesis and using [[model selection]] techniques to choose the most appropriate model.<ref>{{Citation |last=Burnham |first=K. P. |last2=Anderson |first2=D. R. |year=2002 |title=Model Selection and Multimodel Inference: A Practical Information-Theoretic Approach |edition=2nd |publisher=Springer-Verlag |isbn=0-387-95364-7 }}.</ref> (The most common selection techniques are based on either [[Akaike information criterion]] or [[Bayes factor]].) ==Example== Internet personality [[Matt Dillahunty]] gives the example of a large jar full of gumballs to illustrate the burden of proof.<ref>{{Cite episode |title=The Atheist Experience #808 with Matt Dillahunty and Jeff Dee |url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ek4M1trIYr8 |network=channelAustin 16 |series=The Atheist Experience |date=7 April 2013 |number=808}}</ref><ref>{{cite AV media |people=Matt Dillahunty |year=2013 |title =Does God exist? |medium=Debate |url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=QKrKK6Kcnis |location=[[Texas State University]] |accessdate =2016-02-24}}</ref> The number of whole gumballs in the jar is either [[Parity (mathematics)|even or odd]], but the degree of personal acceptance or rejection of claims about that characteristic may vary. We can choose to consider two claims about the situation, given as: # The number of gumballs is even. # The number of gumballs is odd. Either claim could be explored separately; however, both claims tautologically take bearing on the same question. [[parity (mathematics)|Odd]] in this case means "not even" and could be described as a negative claim. Before we have any information about the number of gumballs, we have no means of checking either of the two claims. When we have no evidence to resolve the proposition, we may suspend judgment. From a cognitive sense, when no personal preference toward opposing claims exists, one may be either skeptical about both claims or ambivalent about both claims.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Song |first1=Hyunjin |last2=Ewoldsen |first2=David R. |date=February 2015 |title=Metacognitive model of ambivalence: the role of multiple beliefs and metacognitions in creating attitude ambivalence |journal=[[Communication Theory (journal)|Communication Theory]] |volume=25 |issue=1 |pages=23–45 |doi=10.1111/comt.12050}}</ref> If there is a dispute, the burden of proof falls onto the challenger of the status quo from the perspective of any given social narrative.<ref>{{cite book |last1=van Eemeren |first1=Frans H. |authorlink1=Frans H. van Eemeren |last2=Houtlosser |first2=Peter |date=2003 |chapter=A pragmatic view of the burden of proof |editor1-last=van Eemeren |editor1-first=Frans H. |editor1-link=Frans H. van Eemeren |editor2-last=Blair |editor2-first=J. Anthony |editor2-link=J. Anthony Blair |editor3-last=Willard |editor3-first=Charles A. |editor3-link=Charles Arthur Willard |editor4-last=Snoeck Henkemans |editor4-first=A. Francisca |title=Anyone who has a view: theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation |series=Argumentation library |volume=8 |location=Dordrecht; Boston |publisher=[[Kluwer Academic Publishers]] |pages=123–132 |isbn=1402014554 |oclc=53059441 |doi=10.1007/978-94-007-1078-8_10 |chapterurl=https://books.google.com/books?id=bplsGVDFav8C&pg=PA123}}</ref> If there is no agreeable and adequate proof of evidence to support a claim, the claim is considered an [[argument from ignorance]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Cummings |first=Louise |date=2015 |chapter=Argument from ignorance |title=Reasoning and public health: new ways of coping with uncertainty |location=Cham; New York |publisher=[[Springer-Verlag]] |pages=41–66 |isbn=9783319150123 |oclc=905902693 |doi=10.1007/978-3-319-15013-0_3 |chapterurl=https://books.google.com/books?id=-Ju1BwAAQBAJ&pg=PA41}}</ref> ==See also== {{Portal|Logic|Philosophy}} {{columns-list|colwidth=30em| * [[Evidentialism]] * {{section link|J.B. Bury|On the argument from ignorance and the burden of proof}} * [[Justificationism]] * [[Legal burden of proof]] * [[Null hypothesis]] * [[Occam's razor|Parsimony]] * [[Pragma-dialectics]] * [[Presumption of guilt]] * [[Russell's teapot]] * [[Statistical hypothesis testing]] }} ==References== {{Reflist|30em}} {{Authority control}} {{DEFAULTSORT:Burden Of Proof}} [[Category:Epistemology]] [[Category:Doubt]] [[Category:Logic]]'
New page wikitext, after the edit (new_wikitext)
' stop changing my changes. Swagmathorn, peacing out, once again. {{about|burden of proof as a philosophical concept|other uses|Burden of proof (disambiguation)}} The '''burden of proof''' ([[Latin language|Latin]]: '''''onus probandi''''', shortened from ''Onus probandi incumbit ei qui dicit, non ei qui negat'') is the obligation on a party in a dispute to provide sufficient [[warrant (philosophy)|warrant]] for their position. ==Holder of the burden== When two parties are in a discussion and one makes a claim <!-- DO NOT ADD THE WORD "positive" HERE. There is no logical distinction between positive and negative claims -->that the other disputes, the one who makes the claim typically has a ''burden of proof'' to justify or substantiate that claim especially when it challenges a perceived status quo.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Cargile |first=James | date=January 1997 |title=On the burden of proof |journal=[[Philosophy (journal)|Philosophy]] |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |volume=72 |issue=279 |pages=59–83 |doi=10.1017/s0031819100056655}}</ref> This is also stated in [[Hitchens's razor]]. Carl Sagan proposed a related criteria, the [[Sagan standard]], "extraordinary claims require extraordinary evidence".<ref>Marc Kaufman, ''First Contact: Scientific Breakthroughs in the Hunt for Life Beyond Earth'', Simon and Schuster, p. 124.</ref> While certain kinds of arguments, such as logical [[syllogism]]s, require [[Mathematical proof|mathematical]] or strictly [[Formal proof|logical proof]]s, the standard for [[evidence]] to meet the burden of proof is usually determined by context and community standards and conventions.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Leite |first=Adam |year=2005 |title=A localist solution to the regress of justification |journal=[[Australasian Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=83 |issue=3 |pages=395–421 [p. 418] |doi=10.1080/00048400500191974 |quote=[t]he point of articulating reasons in defense of one's belief is to establish that one is justified in believing as one does. }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Leite |first=Adam |year=2005 |title=A localist solution to the regress of justification |journal=[[Australasian Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=83 |issue=3 |pages=395–421 [p. 403] |doi=10.1080/00048400500191974 |quote=justificatory conversation...[is]...characterized by a person's sincere attempt to vindicate his or her entitlement to a belief by providing adequate reasons in its defense and responding to objections. }}</ref> Philosophical debate can devolve into arguing about who has the burden of proof about a particular claim. This has been described as "burden tennis" or the "onus game".<ref>{{cite journal |last=Dennett |first=Daniel C. |authorlink=Daniel Dennett |date=July 1988 |title=Review of ''Psychosemantics'' by Jerry Fodor |journal=[[The Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=85 |issue=7 |pages=384–389 (389) |doi=10.2307/2026956 |url=http://cogprints.org/253/1/fodor.htm |jstor=2026956 |quote=Fodor is too wise to think his series of arguments can flat disprove the claims of the opposition, so time and again he resorts to claims about shifting the burden of proof, begging the question, outsmarting by embracing the conclusions of reductios, and other exploitations of the rules of the game. The book is a tireless exercise of that philosopher's pasttime, burden-tennis. Burden, burden, who has the burden of proof now? Fodor mostly plays solitaire burden-tennis, against an imaginary opponent often personified as Granny or Aunty, which permits him to express the opposition view in terms that suit his rebuttal, without having to address the issue of whether this is a sympathetic rendering of any real opponent's claims.}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Rodych |first=Victor |date=1996 |origyear=1986 |chapter=Wittgenstein's inversion of Gödel's theorem |editor1-last=Shanker |editor1-first=Stuart |editor1-link=Stuart Shanker |editor2-last=Kilfoyle |editor2-first=David |title=Ludwig Wittgenstein: critical assessments |volume=2. The later Wittgenstein: from ''Philosophical investigations'' to ''On certainty'' |location=London; New York |publisher=[[Routledge]] |pages=232–265 ([//books.google.com/books?id=1MQaXJHzBooC&pg=PA261 261]) |isbn=0415149150 |oclc=47938413 |quote=Thus, in 1991 Wang seems to understand ''why'' Wittgenstein rejects GIT, but, apparently favouring the "onus game" (or "burden tennis"), he unfortunately concludes (pp. 257–58) that "the burden of proof falls ... squarely on Wittgenstein's side" because of Wang's own 'principle of presumed innocence'.}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Abelson |first=Robert P. |authorlink=Robert Abelson |date=1995 |chapter=Credibility of argument |title=Statistics as principled argument |location=Hillsdale, NJ |publisher=[[Lawrence Erlbaum Associates]] |page=[//books.google.com/books?id=yQLFl1ILjZwC&pg=PA170 170] |isbn=0805805273 |oclc=31011850 |quote=When research presentations advance claims that many or most readers deem incredible, these claims are vulnerable to severe challenge. In response, there will typically be a rebuttal by the investigator, and then a fresh round of criticism. The burden of proof shifts back and forth between the investigator and the critic in what might be called the game of 'burden tennis'.}}</ref> ==Shifting the burden of proof== One way in which one would attempt to shift the burden of proof is by committing a logical fallacy known as the [[argument from ignorance]]. It occurs when either a [[proposition]] is assumed to be true because it has not yet been proved false or a proposition is assumed to be false because it has not yet been proved true.<ref>{{cite web|title= Argumentum ad Ignorantiam|url= http://philosophy.lander.edu/logic/ignorance.html|work= Philosophy 103: Introduction to Logic|publisher= [[Lander University]]|year= 2004|accessdate= 2009-04-29| archiveurl= https://web.archive.org/web/20090430170946/http://philosophy.lander.edu/logic/ignorance.html| archivedate= 30 April 2009 <!--DASHBot-->| deadurl= no}}</ref><ref>{{cite encyclopedia | first=Bradley | last=Dowden | encyclopedia=[[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] | title=Appeal to ignorance | url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/fallacy/#AppealtoIgnorance | accessdate=2016-02-24}}</ref> ==Proving a negative== A [[affirmative and negative|negative]] claim is a colloquialism for an affirmative claim that asserts the non-existence or exclusion of something.<ref name="Hales">{{cite journal |last=Hales |first=Steven D. |date=Summer 2005 |title=Thinking tools: You ''can'' prove a negative |journal=[[Think (journal)|Think]] |volume=4 |issue=10 |pages=109–112 |doi=10.1017/S1477175600001287 |url=http://departments.bloomu.edu/philosophy/pages/content/hales/articlepdf/proveanegative.pdf |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]]}}</ref> Saying "You cannot prove a negative" has been called pseudologic because there are many proofs that substantiate negative claims in mathematics, science, and economics including [[Arrow's impossibility theorem]]. There can be multiple claims within a [[debate]]. Nevertheless, it has been said whoever makes a claim carries the burden of proof regardless of positive or negative content in the claim. A negative claim may or may not exist as a counterpoint to a previous claim. A [[proof of impossibility]] or an [[evidence of absence]] argument are typical methods to fulfill the burden of proof for a negative claim.<ref name="Hales"/><ref>{{cite book |last=Damer |first=T. Edward |authorlink=T. Edward Damer |title=[[Attacking Faulty Reasoning|Attacking faulty reasoning: a practical guide to fallacy-free arguments]] | publisher=[[Cengage Learning]] |year=2009 |page=[//books.google.com/?id=-qZabUx0FmkC&pg=PA17 17] |isbn=9780495095064 }}</ref> ==Application== ===In public discourse=== Burden of proof is also an important concept in the [[public sphere|public arena of ideas]]. Once participants in discourse establish common [[Presupposition|assumption]]s, the mechanism of burden of proof helps to ensure that all parties contribute productively, using relevant arguments.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Goldman |first=Alvin |year=1994 |title=Argumentation and social epistemology |journal=[[The Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=91 |issue=1 |pages=27–49 |jstor=2940949 |doi=10.2307/2940949}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=van Eemeren |first=Frans H. |authorlink1=Frans H. van Eemeren |last2=Grootendorst |first2=Rob |authorlink2=Rob Grootendorst |year=2004 |title=A systematic theory of argumentation |location=Cambridge, UK; New York |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |isbn=0521830753 |page=60 |quote=[t]here is no point in venturing to resolve a difference of opinion through an argumentative exchange of views if there is no mutual commitment to a common starting point. }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Brandom |first=Robert |year=1994 |title=Making it explicit |location=Cambridge, MA |publisher=[[Harvard University Press]] |page=222 |isbn=067454319X |quote=[t]here are sentence types that would require a great deal of work for one to get into a position to challenge, such as 'Red is a color,' 'There have been black dogs,' 'Lighting frequently precedes thunder,' and similar commonplaces. These are treated as 'free moves' by members of our speech community—they are available to just about anyone any time to use as premises, to assert unchallenged. }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Adler |first=Jonathan E. |year=2002 |title=Belief's own ethics |location=Cambridge, MA |publisher=[[MIT Press]] |pages=164–167 |isbn=0262011921}}</ref> ===In law=== {{main|Burden of proof (law)}} The legal burden of proof ({{lang-la|onus probandi}}) is the obligation of a [[party (law)|party]] in a [[trial]] to produce the [[evidence]] that will prove the claims they have made against the other party. In a legal dispute, one party is initially presumed to be correct and gets the benefit of the doubt, while the other side bears the burden of proof. When a party bearing the burden of proof meets their burden, the burden of proof switches to the other side. Burdens may be of different kinds for each party, in different phases of litigation. The [[Prima facie|burden of production]] is a minimal burden to produce at least enough evidence for the [[trier of fact]] to ''consider'' a disputed claim.<ref name=CL>''Criminal Law - Cases and Materials'', 7th ed. 2012, [[Wolters Kluwer Law & Business]]; [[John Kaplan (law professor)|John Kaplan]], [[Robert Weisberg]], Guyora Binder, {{ISBN|978-1-4548-0698-1}}, [https://law.stanford.edu/publications/criminal-law-cases-and-materials-7th-edition/]</ref>{{rp|16–17}} After litigants have met the burden of production and their claim is being considered by a trier of fact, they have the burden of persuasion, that enough evidence has been presented to persuade the trier of fact that their side is correct. There are different ''standards'' of persuasiveness ranging from a [[preponderance of the evidence]], where there is just enough evidence to tip the balance, to proof beyond a reasonable doubt, as in United States criminal courts.<ref name="CL"/>{{rp|17}} The burden of proof is usually on the person who brings a claim in a dispute. It is often associated with the Latin [[Maxim (philosophy)|maxim]] ''semper necessitas probandi incumbit ei qui agit'', a translation of which in this context is: "the necessity of proof always lies with the person who lays charges."<ref>Transnational principle of law: [http://www.trans-lex.org/966000 Trans-Lex.org]</ref> The party that does not carry the burden of proof carries the benefit of assumption of being correct, they are presumed to be correct, until the burden shifts after presentation of evidence by the party bringing the action. An example is in an American [[criminal case]], where there is a [[presumption of innocence]] by the [[defendant]]. Fulfilling the burden of proof effectively captures the benefit of assumption, passing the burden of proof off to another party. ===In statistics=== {{main|Null hypothesis}} In [[inferential statistics]], the null hypothesis is a general statement or default position that there is no relationship between two measured phenomena, or no association among groups.<ref>{{cite book | last = Everitt | first = Brian | title = The Cambridge Dictionary of Statistics | publisher = Cambridge University Press | location = Cambridge, UK New York | year = 1998 | isbn = 0521593468 }}</ref> Rejecting or disproving the null [[hypothesis]]—and thus concluding that there are grounds for believing that there ''is'' a relationship between two phenomena (e.g. that a potential treatment has a measurable effect)—is a central task in the modern practice of science; the field of statistics gives precise criteria for rejecting a null hypothesis{{citation needed|date=December 2017}}. The null hypothesis is generally assumed to be true until evidence indicates otherwise. In statistics, it is often denoted '''''H''<sub>0</sub>''' (read “H-nought”, "H-null", "H-oh", or "H-zero"). The concept of a null hypothesis is used differently in two approaches to statistical inference. In the significance testing approach of [[Ronald Fisher]], a null hypothesis is rejected if the observed data are [[Statistical significance|significantly]] unlikely to have occurred if the null hypothesis were true. In this case the null hypothesis is rejected and an [[alternative hypothesis]] is accepted in its place. If the data are consistent with the null hypothesis, then the null hypothesis is not rejected. In neither case is the null hypothesis or its alternative proven; the null hypothesis is tested with data and a decision is made based on how likely or unlikely the data are. This is analogous to the legal principle of [[presumption of innocence]], in which a suspect or defendant is assumed to be innocent (null is not rejected) until proven guilty (null is rejected) beyond a reasonable doubt (to a statistically significant degree). In the [[Statistical hypothesis testing|hypothesis testing]] approach of [[Jerzy Neyman]] and [[Egon Pearson]], a null hypothesis is contrasted with an alternative hypothesis and the two hypotheses are distinguished on the basis of data, with certain error rates. Proponents of each approach criticize the other approach. Nowadays, though, a hybrid approach is widely practiced and presented in textbooks. The hybrid is in turn criticized as incorrect and incoherent—for details, see [[Statistical hypothesis testing]]. Statistical inference can be done without a null hypothesis, by specifying a [[statistical model]] corresponding to each candidate hypothesis and using [[model selection]] techniques to choose the most appropriate model.<ref>{{Citation |last=Burnham |first=K. P. |last2=Anderson |first2=D. R. |year=2002 |title=Model Selection and Multimodel Inference: A Practical Information-Theoretic Approach |edition=2nd |publisher=Springer-Verlag |isbn=0-387-95364-7 }}.</ref> (The most common selection techniques are based on either [[Akaike information criterion]] or [[Bayes factor]].) ==Example== Internet personality [[Matt Dillahunty]] gives the example of a large jar full of gumballs to illustrate the burden of proof.<ref>{{Cite episode |title=The Atheist Experience #808 with Matt Dillahunty and Jeff Dee |url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ek4M1trIYr8 |network=channelAustin 16 |series=The Atheist Experience |date=7 April 2013 |number=808}}</ref><ref>{{cite AV media |people=Matt Dillahunty |year=2013 |title =Does God exist? |medium=Debate |url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=QKrKK6Kcnis |location=[[Texas State University]] |accessdate =2016-02-24}}</ref> The number of whole gumballs in the jar is either [[Parity (mathematics)|even or odd]], but the degree of personal acceptance or rejection of claims about that characteristic may vary. We can choose to consider two claims about the situation, given as: # The number of gumballs is even. # The number of gumballs is odd. Either claim could be explored separately; however, both claims tautologically take bearing on the same question. [[parity (mathematics)|Odd]] in this case means "not even" and could be described as a negative claim. Before we have any information about the number of gumballs, we have no means of checking either of the two claims. When we have no evidence to resolve the proposition, we may suspend judgment. From a cognitive sense, when no personal preference toward opposing claims exists, one may be either skeptical about both claims or ambivalent about both claims.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Song |first1=Hyunjin |last2=Ewoldsen |first2=David R. |date=February 2015 |title=Metacognitive model of ambivalence: the role of multiple beliefs and metacognitions in creating attitude ambivalence |journal=[[Communication Theory (journal)|Communication Theory]] |volume=25 |issue=1 |pages=23–45 |doi=10.1111/comt.12050}}</ref> If there is a dispute, the burden of proof falls onto the challenger of the status quo from the perspective of any given social narrative.<ref>{{cite book |last1=van Eemeren |first1=Frans H. |authorlink1=Frans H. van Eemeren |last2=Houtlosser |first2=Peter |date=2003 |chapter=A pragmatic view of the burden of proof |editor1-last=van Eemeren |editor1-first=Frans H. |editor1-link=Frans H. van Eemeren |editor2-last=Blair |editor2-first=J. Anthony |editor2-link=J. Anthony Blair |editor3-last=Willard |editor3-first=Charles A. |editor3-link=Charles Arthur Willard |editor4-last=Snoeck Henkemans |editor4-first=A. Francisca |title=Anyone who has a view: theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation |series=Argumentation library |volume=8 |location=Dordrecht; Boston |publisher=[[Kluwer Academic Publishers]] |pages=123–132 |isbn=1402014554 |oclc=53059441 |doi=10.1007/978-94-007-1078-8_10 |chapterurl=https://books.google.com/books?id=bplsGVDFav8C&pg=PA123}}</ref> If there is no agreeable and adequate proof of evidence to support a claim, the claim is considered an [[argument from ignorance]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Cummings |first=Louise |date=2015 |chapter=Argument from ignorance |title=Reasoning and public health: new ways of coping with uncertainty |location=Cham; New York |publisher=[[Springer-Verlag]] |pages=41–66 |isbn=9783319150123 |oclc=905902693 |doi=10.1007/978-3-319-15013-0_3 |chapterurl=https://books.google.com/books?id=-Ju1BwAAQBAJ&pg=PA41}}</ref> ==See also== {{Portal|Logic|Philosophy}} {{columns-list|colwidth=30em| * [[Evidentialism]] * {{section link|J.B. Bury|On the argument from ignorance and the burden of proof}} * [[Justificationism]] * [[Legal burden of proof]] * [[Null hypothesis]] * [[Occam's razor|Parsimony]] * [[Pragma-dialectics]] * [[Presumption of guilt]] * [[Russell's teapot]] * [[Statistical hypothesis testing]] }} ==References== {{Reflist|30em}} {{Authority control}} {{DEFAULTSORT:Burden Of Proof}} [[Category:Epistemology]] [[Category:Doubt]] [[Category:Logic]]'
Unified diff of changes made by edit (edit_diff)
'@@ -2,5 +2,5 @@ -stop changes my changes. Swagmathorn, peacing out, once again. +stop changing my changes. Swagmathorn, peacing out, once again. '
New page size (new_size)
18999
Old page size (old_size)
18998
Size change in edit (edit_delta)
1
Lines added in edit (added_lines)
[ 0 => 'stop changing my changes. Swagmathorn, peacing out, once again. ' ]
Lines removed in edit (removed_lines)
[ 0 => 'stop changes my changes. Swagmathorn, peacing out, once again. ' ]
Whether or not the change was made through a Tor exit node (tor_exit_node)
0
Unix timestamp of change (timestamp)
1526171221