Simulation hypothesis: Difference between revisions
Randy Kryn (talk | contribs) Undid revision, had been removed and reverted then removed again |
Undid revision 1048861207 by Randy Kryn (talk) I’m not trying to vandalise, there is genuine sincerity for why I believe this should be removed or at least heavily altered. I’ve started the discussion of this on the talk page |
||
Line 53: | Line 53: | ||
Physicist [[Marcelo Gleiser]] objects to the notion that posthumans would have a reason to run simulated universes: "...being so advanced they would have collected enough knowledge about their past to have little interest in this kind of simulation. ...They may have virtual-reality museums, where they could go and experience the lives and tribulations of their ancestors. But a full-fledged, resource-consuming simulation of an ''entire'' universe? Sounds like a colossal waste of time." Gleiser also points out that there is no plausible reason to stop at one level of simulation, so that the simulated ancestors might also be simulating their ancestors, and so on, creating an infinite regress akin to the "[[Turtles all the way down|problem of the First Cause]]."<ref>{{Cite web |last=Gleiser |first=Marcelo |author-link=Marcelo Gleiser |date=March 9, 2017 |title=Why Reality Is Not A Video Game — And Why It Matters |url=https://www.npr.org/sections/13.7/2017/03/09/519376356/why-reality-is-not-a-video-game-and-why-it-matters |url-status=live |access-date=January 18, 2021 |website=NPR}}</ref> |
Physicist [[Marcelo Gleiser]] objects to the notion that posthumans would have a reason to run simulated universes: "...being so advanced they would have collected enough knowledge about their past to have little interest in this kind of simulation. ...They may have virtual-reality museums, where they could go and experience the lives and tribulations of their ancestors. But a full-fledged, resource-consuming simulation of an ''entire'' universe? Sounds like a colossal waste of time." Gleiser also points out that there is no plausible reason to stop at one level of simulation, so that the simulated ancestors might also be simulating their ancestors, and so on, creating an infinite regress akin to the "[[Turtles all the way down|problem of the First Cause]]."<ref>{{Cite web |last=Gleiser |first=Marcelo |author-link=Marcelo Gleiser |date=March 9, 2017 |title=Why Reality Is Not A Video Game — And Why It Matters |url=https://www.npr.org/sections/13.7/2017/03/09/519376356/why-reality-is-not-a-video-game-and-why-it-matters |url-status=live |access-date=January 18, 2021 |website=NPR}}</ref> |
||
== The simulation hypothesis in physics == |
|||
In physics, the view of the universe and its workings as the ebb and flow of information was first observed by Wheeler.<ref>Wheeler, J.A. (1990) Information, Physics, Quantum. In: Zurek, W.H., Ed., Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information, Addison-Wesley, Boston, 354-368.</ref> This shift of [[paradigm]] from understanding the universe as energy transformation to the information processing universe leads to the [[emergence]] of a new branch of science called [[Quantum computing|quantum computation]]. Quantum evolution of a system is represented in quantum computation by a [[quantum circuit]] built from [[Quantum logic gate|quantum gates]]. Consequently, two views of the world emerged: the first one proposes that the universe is a [[Quantum computing|quantum computer]],<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Lloyd |first=Seth |title=The Universe as Quantum Computer |date=2011-10-24 |url=https://www.worldscientific.com/doi/abs/10.1142/9789814374309_0029 |journal=A Computable Universe |pages=567–581 |publisher=World Scientific |arxiv=1312.4455 |doi=10.1142/9789814374309_0029 |isbn=978-981-4374-29-3 |access-date=2021-04-13}}</ref> while the other one proposes that the system performing the simulation is distinct from its simulation (the universe).<ref>Campbell, T., Owhadi, H., Sauvageau, J. and Watkinson, D. (2017) On Testing the Simulation Theory.</ref> |
|||
Under the assumption of finite computational resources, the simulation of the universe would be performed by dividing the continuum spacetime into a discrete set of points. Many physical aspects can support the simulation hypothesis, for instance: |
|||
# No [[Absolute space and time|absolute frame]] of reference in [[Theory of relativity|relativity theory]]. |
|||
# The [[measurement problem]] in quantum mechanics depends on the observer. |
|||
# Problem of time in [[quantum gravity]] which is an extrinsic parameter and need suitable observable of the clock from outside the visible universe.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Marletto |first1=C. |last2=Vedral |first2=V. |date=2017-02-13 |title=Evolution without evolution and without ambiguities |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.95.043510 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=95 |issue=4 |pages=043510 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.95.043510|arxiv=1610.04773 |bibcode=2017PhRvD..95d3510M |s2cid=119215987 }}</ref> |
|||
# The [[Bekenstein bound]],<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Bekenstein |first=Jacob D. |date=1981-01-15 |title=Universal upper bound on the entropy-to-energy ratio for bounded systems |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.23.287 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=23 |issue=2 |pages=287–298 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.23.287|bibcode=1981PhRvD..23..287B }}</ref> which relate the [[Curvature of Riemannian manifolds|curvature]] of the [[spacetime]] with [[Information theory|information]]. |
|||
# The [[Holographic principle]], the [[AdS/CFT correspondence|AdS/CFT]] correspondence, which relate quantum gravity and [[quantum information]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Ryu |first1=Shinsei |last2=Takayanagi |first2=Tadashi |date=2006-08-21 |title=Aspects of holographic entanglement entropy |url=https://doi.org/10.1088/1126-6708/2006/08/045 |journal=Journal of High Energy Physics |language=en |volume=2006 |issue=8 |pages=045 |arxiv=hep-th/0605073 |doi=10.1088/1126-6708/2006/08/045 |bibcode=2006JHEP...08..045R |s2cid=14858887 |issn=1029-8479}}</ref> |
|||
# Objective reality does not exist in quantum mechanics; this can be seen in the [[Wheeler's delayed-choice experiment|delayed choice experiment]]. |
|||
Many physical results can be derived from the above description of the world, such as: |
|||
* The time dilation in [[special relativity]] can be viewed as [[Frame rate|framerate]] adaptation of a moving object who need more resources for rendering. |
|||
* [[Gravitational lens]]ing can be interpreted as a bounded massive object need more local resources to be rendered which in turn need a compromise between the [[Polygon (computer graphics)|polygon counts]] and the model fidelity and that can be achieved by changing the structure of the spacetime around the object (fewer polygons). |
|||
* [[Multiverse|Extradimension]] and [[Compactification (mathematics)|compactification]] are similar to a projection of a 3D object to a 2D screen with [[Wire-frame model|wireframe]] rendering. |
|||
* [[Black hole information paradox|Black hole Information]] paradox can be understood as a [[Memory paging|memory]] saturation and [[Hawking radiation|black hole radiations]] as freeing that memory. |
|||
* [[Measurement in quantum mechanics|Quantum measurement]] can be seen as an intelligent agent in a specific state receive and process information and then make an action from a set of possible actions which forces the system to be projected into a specific state.<ref name=":1">Everett, H., Wheeler, J.A., DeWitt, B.S., Cooper, L.N., Van Vechten, D. and Graham, N. (1973) The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics, Princeton University Press, Princeton.</ref> |
|||
[[Temporal paradox|Time travel paradox]]es, [[antimatter]], and other similar physical phenomena can also be interpreted within the context of the simulation hypothesis. |
|||
=== Proposal of the Universe Evolution within the simulation hypothesis === |
|||
Inspired by the [[Many-worlds interpretation|many world interpretation]] of quantum mechanics<ref name=":1" /> and the [[subjective idealism]] view of [[reality]], the authors hypothesize the [[Chronology of the universe|evolution of the universe]] in the following fashion: a cosmological consciousness being equipped with [[Six Thinking Hats|thinking tools]] that include [[Inductive reasoning|inductive]], [[Deductive reasoning|deductive]], and [[abductive reasoning|abductive]] reasoning, as well as other types of thinking created or simulated the universe<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Sørensen |first=Torquil MacDonald |date=2005-05-24 |title=Numerical solution of the ekpyrotic scenario in the moduli space approximation |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.71.107302 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=71 |issue=10 |pages=107302 |arxiv=hep-th/0502136 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.71.107302|bibcode=2005PhRvD..71j7302S |s2cid=15247984 }}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Hawking |first1=S. W. |last2=Hertog |first2=Thomas |date=2018-04-27 |title=A smooth exit from eternal inflation? |journal=Journal of High Energy Physics |language=en |volume=2018 |issue=4 |pages=147 |doi=10.1007/JHEP04(2018)147 |arxiv=1707.07702 |bibcode=2018JHEP...04..147H |issn=1029-8479 |doi-access=free}}</ref><ref>He, D.S., Gao, D.F. and Cai, Q.-Y. (2014) Physical Review D, 89, Article ID: 083510.</ref> and started injecting random qubits, "[[quantum fluctuation]]",<ref>Ade, P., et al. (2016) Astronomy and Astrophysics, 594, 1.</ref> into the baby universe where information gets processed. By measuring the results, a new quantum circuits can be exited and the cycle repeat through a [[Feedback|feedback loop]] in a process similar to the working of the brain where the [[born rule]] can be compared to the [[Neural network|weights in the neural network]]. As the system evolves subsystems emerge each of which has its own computation abilities and functionalities. This construction is reminiscent of [[Conway's Game of Life]] (GOL), which is a cellular automaton invented by British mathematician [[John Horton Conway|John Conway]].<ref>{{Cite journal |title=Mathematical Games |url=https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/mathematical-games-1970-10/ |access-date=2021-04-15 |journal=Scientific American |year=1970 |language=en |doi=10.1038/scientificamerican1070-120|last1=Gardner |first1=Martin |volume=223 |issue=4 |pages=120–123 |bibcode=1970SciAm.223d.120G }}</ref> By choosing an appropriate initial configuration of the game, [[complex system]] emerges and [[self-replication]] object can appear, even more surprising, emerging laws could entail new concepts and entities which do not apparently exist in the original laws.<ref>Hawking, S. (2010) The Grand Design.</ref><ref>{{Cite book|last=Hawking |first=Stephen |title=Grand Design, the|date=2010|url=http://worldcat.org/oclc/995878477|publisher=Random House|isbn=978-1-4159-6573-3|oclc=995878477|access-date=2021-08-04}}</ref> |
|||
In a more abstract way, this construction of the universe can be imagined as each cognitive subsystem is equipped with a [[formal language]] that "lives" in a [[metalanguage]]<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Tarski |first=Alfred |date=1944 |title=The Semantic Conception of Truth: and the Foundations of Semantics |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2102968 |journal=Philosophy and Phenomenological Research |volume=4 |issue=3 |pages=341–376 |doi=10.2307/2102968 |jstor=2102968 |issn=0031-8205}}</ref> and having finite set of [[axiom]]s (although [[Gödel's incompleteness theorems|not complete]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Gödel |first=Kurt Friedrich |url=http://worldcat.org/oclc/769889619 |title=Collected works |date=1995 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=0-19-507255-3 |oclc=769889619}}</ref>{{rp|304-323}}) that define its dynamics according to some [[Semantics|interpretation]] (model-dependent reality) and evolves into different forms. Furthermore, this world can be decomposed into three types of entities: inorganic matter, which is small structure uses simple quantum logic gates that determine its evolution; organic matter, which acquire more computational abilities for learning; and human, that has the ability to reason. Space and time and physical laws can be thought of, in a [[Immanuel Kant|Kantian]] language,<ref>{{Cite book |last=Kant |first=E. |title=Critics of Pure Reason |year=1781}}</ref> as a type of relations in a [[mathematical structure]] and matter is a realization of this philosophical matter.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Brightwell |first1=Graham |last2=Gregory |first2=Ruth |date=1991-01-21 |title=Structure of random discrete spacetime |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevLett.66.260 |journal=Physical Review Letters |volume=66 |issue=3 |pages=260–263 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.66.260 |pmid=10043761 |bibcode=1991PhRvL..66..260B |hdl-access=free |hdl=2060/19900019113}}</ref> |
|||
Evolution in this structure can be imagined as a process of mind from state to another state which can be translated in the material world into a [[Turing machine]] where logical statements about proofs are translated into actions of machines. Even though Turing machines are built from simple [[logic gate]]s, they are able to simulate very sophisticated virtual worlds, such as those in [[open world|open world video games]]. The difference between modern computers that are built upon the [[Von Neumann architecture|Von Neumann]] architecture of Turing machines and the universal computation is that a Turing machine uses [[deterministic computation]], whereas universal computation uses quantum computation to explore the whole spectrum of computation and so enables the system to evolve by [[machine learning|learning and making decisions]]. This imagination about the universe formation is similar to Von Neumann method of creating natural numbers out of empty sets who imagined that all numbers could be bootstrapped out of the empty set by the operations of the mind. In a platonic sense, that is in the world of ideas, each partition of the world would evolve by increasing its content toward the infinity or decreasing toward the emptiness or it can be locked in a minima. Therefore, attention plays a major role in this approach which depends on the system "[[Personality psychology|personalities]]".<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Rothmann |first1=S. |last2=Coetzer |first2=E. P. |date=2003-10-24 |title=The big five personality dimensions and job performance |url=https://sajip.co.za/index.php/sajip/article/view/88 |journal=SA Journal of Industrial Psychology |language=en |volume=29 |issue=1 |doi=10.4102/sajip.v29i1.88 |issn=2071-0763 |doi-access=free}}</ref> Furthermore, the driving force for a subsystem to grow, that is to increase its knowledge base, is speculated as the "force of love"<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Peirce |first=Charles S. |date=1893-01-01 |title=Evolutionary Love. |url=https://doi.org/10.5840/monist18933235 |journal=The Monist |volume=3 |issue=2 |pages=176–200 |doi=10.5840/monist18933235 |issn=0026-9662}}</ref> which, in a systemic view<ref>{{Cite book |last1=Capra |first1=Fritjof |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/cbo9780511895555 |title=The Systems View of Life |last2=Luisi |first2=Pier Luigi |date=2014 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-511-89555-5 |location=Cambridge|doi=10.1017/cbo9780511895555 }}</ref> translate into creativity and novelty (this aspect is included in a video game<ref>Hamieh, S. (2019) Wormhole Gate. Google Play.</ref>). This construction can be compared to [[computational ontology]], used in [[Semantic Web|semantic web]], which defines a set of representational primitives with which to model a domain of knowledge or [[discourse]]. The representational primitives are typically [[Classes of computers|classes]] (or sets), attributes (or properties), and relationships (or relations among class members). |
|||
==Hypothesis advocates== |
==Hypothesis advocates== |
Revision as of 12:12, 8 October 2021
The simulation hypothesis is a proposal regarding the nature of existence. The proposal is that all the current existence that humans know, including the Earth and the rest of the universe, could in fact be an artificial simulation, such as a computer simulation. Some versions rely on the development of a simulated reality, a proposed technology that would be able to convince its inhabitants that the simulation was "real".
The simulation hypothesis bears a close resemblance to various other skeptical scenarios from throughout the history of philosophy. The hypothesis was popularized in its current form by Nick Bostrom. The suggestion that such a hypothesis is compatible with all human perceptual experiences is thought to have significant epistemological consequences in the form of philosophical skepticism. Versions of the hypothesis have also been featured in science fiction, appearing as a central plot device in many stories and films. The hypothesis popularized by Bostrom is very disputed, with, for example, theoretical physicist Sabine Hossenfelder, who called it pseudoscience[1] and cosmologist George F. R. Ellis, who stated that "[the hypothesis] is totally impracticable from a technical viewpoint" and that "protagonists seem to have confused science fiction with science. Late night pub discussion is not a viable theory."[2] A bigger proposal that builds on this idea is that Earth could be the end of a long stack of simulations.
Origins
There is a long philosophical and scientific history to the underlying thesis that reality is an illusion. This skeptical hypothesis can be traced back to antiquity; for example, to the "Butterfly Dream" of Zhuangzi,[3] or the Indian philosophy of Maya, or in Ancient Greek philosophy Anaxarchus and Monimus likened existing things to a scene-painting and supposed them to resemble the impressions experienced in sleep or madness.[4]
Aztec philosophical texts theorised that the world was a painting or book written by the Teotl.[5]
Simulation hypothesis in philosophy
Nick Bostrom's premise:
Many works of science fiction as well as some forecasts by serious technologists and futurologists predict that enormous amounts of computing power will be available in the future. Let us suppose for a moment that these predictions are correct. One thing that later generations might do with their super-powerful computers is run detailed simulations of their forebears or of people like their forebears. Because their computers would be so powerful, they could run a great many such simulations. Suppose that these simulated people are conscious (as they would be if the simulations were sufficiently fine-grained and if a certain quite widely accepted position in the philosophy of mind is correct). Then it could be the case that the vast majority of minds like ours do not belong to the original race but rather to people simulated by the advanced descendants of an original race.
Nick Bostrom's conclusion:
It is then possible to argue that, if this were the case, we would be rational to think that we are likely among the simulated minds rather than among the original biological ones.
Therefore, if we don't think that we are currently living in a computer simulation, we are not entitled to believe that we will have descendants who will run lots of such simulations of their forebears.— Nick Bostrom, Are You Living in a Computer Simulation?, 2003[6]
The simulation argument
In 2003, philosopher Nick Bostrom proposed a trilemma that he called "the simulation argument". Despite the name, Bostrom's "simulation argument" does not directly argue that humans live in a simulation; instead, Bostrom's trilemma argues that one of three unlikely-seeming propositions is almost certainly true:
- "The fraction of human-level civilizations that reach a posthuman stage (that is, one capable of running high-fidelity ancestor simulations) is very close to zero", or
- "The fraction of posthuman civilizations that are interested in running simulations of their evolutionary history, or variations thereof, is very close to zero", or
- "The fraction of all people with our kind of experiences that are living in a simulation is very close to one."
The trilemma points out that a technologically mature "posthuman" civilization would have enormous computing power; if even a tiny percentage of them were to run "ancestor simulations" (that is, "high-fidelity" simulations of ancestral life that would be indistinguishable from reality to the simulated ancestor), the total number of simulated ancestors, or "Sims", in the universe (or multiverse, if it exists) would greatly exceed the total number of actual ancestors.
Bostrom goes on to use a type of anthropic reasoning to claim that, if the third proposition is the one of those three that is true, and almost all people live in simulations, then humans are almost certainly living in a simulation.
Bostrom claims his argument goes beyond the classical ancient "skeptical hypothesis", claiming that "...we have interesting empirical reasons to believe that a certain disjunctive claim about the world is true", the third of the three disjunctive propositions being that we are almost certainly living in a simulation. Thus, Bostrom, and writers in agreement with Bostrom such as David Chalmers, argue there might be empirical reasons for the "simulation hypothesis", and that therefore the simulation hypothesis is not a skeptical hypothesis but rather a "metaphysical hypothesis". Bostrom states he personally sees no strong argument as to which of the three trilemma propositions is the true one: "If (1) is true, then we will almost certainly go extinct before reaching posthumanity. If (2) is true, then there must be a strong convergence among the courses of advanced civilizations so that virtually none contains any individuals who desire to run ancestor-simulations and are free to do so. If (3) is true, then we almost certainly live in a simulation. In the dark forest of our current ignorance, it seems sensible to apportion one's credence roughly evenly between (1), (2), and (3)... I note that people who hear about the simulation argument often react by saying, 'Yes, I accept the argument, and it is obvious that it is possibility #n that obtains.' But different people pick a different n. Some think it obvious that (1) is true, others that (2) is true, yet others that (3) is true."
As a corollary to the trilemma, Bostrom states that "Unless we are now living in a simulation, our descendants will almost certainly never run an ancestor-simulation."[6][7][8][9]
Criticism of Bostrom's anthropic reasoning
Bostrom argues that if "the fraction of all people with our kind of experiences that are living in a simulation is very close to one", then it follows that humans probably live in a simulation. Some philosophers disagree, proposing that perhaps "Sims" do not have conscious experiences the same way that unsimulated humans do, or that it can otherwise be self-evident to a human that they are a human rather than a Sim.[7][10] Philosopher Barry Dainton modifies Bostrom's trilemma by substituting "neural ancestor simulations" (ranging from literal brains in a vat, to far-future humans with induced high-fidelity hallucinations that they are their own distant ancestors) for Bostrom's "ancestor simulations", on the grounds that every philosophical school of thought can agree that sufficiently high-tech neural ancestor simulation experiences would be indistinguishable from non-simulated experiences. Even if high-fidelity computer Sims are never conscious, Dainton's reasoning leads to the following conclusion: either the fraction of human-level civilizations that reach a posthuman stage and are able and willing to run large numbers of neural ancestor simulations is close to zero, or some kind of (possibly neural) ancestor simulation.[11]
Some scholars categorically reject—or are uninterested in—anthropic reasoning, dismissing it as "merely philosophical", unfalsifiable, or inherently unscientific.[7]
Some critics propose that the simulation could be in the first generation, and all the simulated people that will one day be created do not yet exist.[7]
The cosmologist Sean M. Carroll argues that the simulation hypothesis leads to a contradiction: if humans are typical, as it is assumed, and not capable of performing simulations, this contradicts the arguer's assumption that it is easy for us to foresee that other civilizations can most likely perform simulations.[12]
Physicist Frank Wilczek raises an empirical objection, saying that the laws of the universe have hidden complexity which is "not used for anything" and the laws are constrained by time and location – all of this being unnecessary and extraneous in a simulation. He further argues that the simulation argument amounts to "begging the question," due to the "embarrassing question" of the nature of the underlying reality in which this universe is simulated. "Okay if this is a simulated world, what is the thing in which it is simulated made out of? What are the laws for that?"[13]
It has been argued that humans cannot be the ones being simulated, since the simulation argument uses its descendants as the ones running the simulations.[14] In other words, it has been argued that the probability that humans live in a simulated universe is not independent of the prior probability that is assigned to the existence of other universes.
Arguments, within the trilemma, against the simulation hypothesis
Some scholars accept the trilemma, and argue that the first or second of the propositions are true, and that the third proposition (the proposition that humans live in a simulation) is false. Physicist Paul Davies use Bostrom's trilemma as part of one possible argument against a near-infinite multiverse. This argument runs as follows: if there were a near-infinite multiverse, there would be posthuman civilizations running ancestor simulations, which would lead to the untenable and scientifically self-defeating conclusion that humans live in a simulation; therefore, by reductio ad absurdum, existing multiverse theories are likely false. (Unlike Bostrom and Chalmers, Davies (among others) considers the simulation hypothesis to be self-defeating.)[7][15]
Some point out that there is currently no proof of technology which would facilitate the existence of sufficiently high-fidelity ancestor simulation. Additionally, there is no proof that it is physically possible or feasible for a posthuman civilization to create such a simulation, and therefore for the present, the first proposition must be taken to be true.[7] Additionally there are limits of computation.[6][16]
Physicist Marcelo Gleiser objects to the notion that posthumans would have a reason to run simulated universes: "...being so advanced they would have collected enough knowledge about their past to have little interest in this kind of simulation. ...They may have virtual-reality museums, where they could go and experience the lives and tribulations of their ancestors. But a full-fledged, resource-consuming simulation of an entire universe? Sounds like a colossal waste of time." Gleiser also points out that there is no plausible reason to stop at one level of simulation, so that the simulated ancestors might also be simulating their ancestors, and so on, creating an infinite regress akin to the "problem of the First Cause."[17]
Hypothesis advocates
Elon Musk firmly believes in the simulation hypothesis.[18] In a podcast with Joe Rogan, Musk said "If you assume any rate of improvement at all, games will eventually be indistinguishable from reality" before concluding "that it's most likely we're in a simulation."[19] He also stated in a 2016 interview that "there's a one in billions chance we're in base reality".[18]
Another high-profile proponent to the hypothesis is astrophysicist Neil Degrasse Tyson, who said in an NBC News interview that the hypothesis is correct giving "better than 50-50 odds" and adding:[20]
"I wish I could summon a strong argument against it, but I can find none."
However, in a subsequent interview with Chuck Nice on a YouTube episode of "StarTalk," Tyson shares that his friend J. Richard Gott, a professor of astrophysical sciences at Princeton University made him aware of a strong objection to the simulation hypothesis. The objection points out that the common trait that all hypothetical high fidelity simulated universes possess is the ability to produce high fidelity simulated universes. And being that our current world does not posses this ability it would mean the we are either the real universe, and therefore simulated universes have not yet been created, or we are the last in a very long chain of simulated universes, an observation that makes the simulation hypothesis seem less probable. Regarding this objection Tyson remarks "that changes my life."[21]
Consequences of living in a simulation
Economist Robin Hanson argues a self-interested occupant of a high-fidelity simulation should strive to be entertaining and praiseworthy in order to avoid being turned off or being shunted into a non-conscious low-fidelity part of the simulation. Hanson additionally speculates that someone who is aware that he might be in a simulation might care less about others and live more for today: "your motivation to save for retirement, or to help the poor in Ethiopia, might be muted by realizing that in your simulation, you will never retire and there is no Ethiopia."[22]
Testing the hypothesis physically
A method to test one type of simulation hypothesis was proposed in 2012 in a joint paper by physicists Silas R. Beane from the University of Bonn (now at the University of Washington, Seattle), and Zohreh Davoudi and Martin J. Savage from the University of Washington, Seattle.[23] Under the assumption of finite computational resources, the simulation of the universe would be performed by dividing the continuum space-time into a discrete set of points. In analogy with the mini-simulations that lattice-gauge theorists run today to build up nuclei from the underlying theory of strong interactions (known as quantum chromodynamics), several observational consequences of a grid-like space-time have been studied in their work. Among proposed signatures is an anisotropy in the distribution of ultra-high-energy cosmic rays, that, if observed, would be consistent with the simulation hypothesis according to these physicists.[24] In 2017, Campbell et al. proposed several experiments aimed at testing the simulation hypothesis in their paper "On Testing the Simulation Theory".[25]
In 2019, philosopher Preston Greene suggested that it may be best not to find out if we're living in a simulation since, if it were found to be true, such knowing may end the simulation.[26]
Other uses of the simulation hypothesis in philosophy
Besides attempting to assess whether the simulation hypothesis is true or false, philosophers have also used it to illustrate other philosophical problems, especially in metaphysics and epistemology. David Chalmers has argued that simulated beings might wonder whether their mental lives are governed by the physics of their environment, when in fact these mental lives are simulated separately (and are thus, in fact, not governed by the simulated physics).[27] Chalmers claims that they might eventually find that their thoughts fail to be physically caused, and argues that this means that Cartesian dualism is not necessarily as problematic of a philosophical view as is commonly supposed, though he does not endorse it. Similar arguments have been made for philosophical views about personal identity that say that an individual could have been another human being in the past, as well as views about qualia that say that colors could have appeared differently than they do (the inverted spectrum scenario). In both cases, the claim is that all this would require is hooking up the mental lives to the simulated physics in a different way.[28]
Brain in a vat and parsimony
Skeptical arguments have historically played a role in the evolution of philosophical discussion, particularly in the fields of ontology, metaphysics, the theory of knowledge and the philosophy of science. The fallibility of perception, knowledge and thought have been made obvious employing several arguments.[29] Solipsist scenarios, a common ground of debate in this fields, are extreme cases prompting these dilemmas for further discussion.
In virtue of computational simplicity, achieving this last kind of simulations with equal resolution seems much more undemanding than assembling a super simulator that runs a complete reality, including multiple participants. If humanity was being simulated, as noted by Lorenzo Pieri, it is more “likely to be one of such Brain-in-a-Vat or «solo players», as it is much easier to simulate the inputs to the brain than the full blown reality”.[30]
This probabilistic argument deferring to parsimony, is based on the idea that “if we randomly select the simulation (…) the likelihood of picking a given simulation is inversely correlated to the computational complexity of the simulation”.[30]
Science fiction themes
Science fiction has highlighted themes such as virtual reality, artificial intelligence and computer gaming for more than fifty years.[citation needed] Jokester (1956) by Isaac Asimov explores the idea that humor is actually a psychological study tool imposed from without by extraterrestrials studying mankind, similarly to how humans study mice. Simulacron-3 (1964) by Daniel F. Galouye (alternative title: Counterfeit World) tells the story of a virtual city developed as a computer simulation for market research purposes, in which the simulated inhabitants possess consciousness; all but one of the inhabitants are unaware of the true nature of their world. The book was made into a German made-for-TV film called World on a Wire (1973) directed by Rainer Werner Fassbinder. The film The Thirteenth Floor (1999) was also loosely based on this book. We Can Remember It for You Wholesale is a short story by American writer Philip K. Dick, first published in The Magazine of Fantasy & Science Fiction in April 1966, and was the basis for the 1990 film Total Recall and its 2012 remake. In Overdrawn at the Memory Bank, a 1983 television film, the main character pays to have his mind connected to a simulation.[citation needed]
The same theme was repeated in the 1999 film The Matrix, which depicted a world in which artificially intelligent robots enslaved humanity within a simulation set in the contemporary world. The 2012 play World of Wires was partially inspired by the Bostrom essay on the simulation hypothesis.[31]
See also
References
- ^ Hossenfelder, Sabine (February 13, 2021). "The Simulation Hypothesis is Pseudoscience". BackReAction. Retrieved April 18, 2021.
- ^ Ellis, George (2012). "The multiverse: conjecture, proof, and science" (PDF). Retrieved April 18, 2021.
- ^ Grabianowski, Ed (7 May 2011). "You're living in a computer simulation, and math proves it". Gizmodo. Retrieved 29 October 2016.
- ^ Sextus Empiricus Against the Logicians 1.88
- ^ Maffie, James. "Aztec Philosophy". Internet Enclyopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 April 2021.
- ^ a b c Bostrom, Nick (2003). "Are You Living in a Computer Simulation?". Philosophical Quarterly. 53 (211): 243–255. doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00309.
- ^ a b c d e f "The Simulation Argument Website FAQ".
- ^ Bostrom, Nick (2003). "The Simulation Argument: Why the Probability that You Are Living in a Matrix is Quite High".
- ^ Chalmers, Davis J. "The Matrix as Metaphysics".
- ^ Weatherson, Brian (2003). "Are You a Sim?". The Philosophical Quarterly. 53 (212): 425–431. doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00323. JSTOR 3543127.
- ^ Dainton, Barry (2012). "On singularities and simulations". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 19 (1): 42. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.374.7434.
- ^ Carroll, Sean (22 August 2016). "Maybe We Do Not Live in a Simulation: The Resolution Conundrum". PreposterousUniverse.com.
- ^ Sean Carroll (January 18, 2021). "SEAN CARROLL'S MINDSCAPE". Preposterousuniverse.com (Podcast). Sean Carroll. Event occurs at 0:53.37.
The laws that we observe just don't look like a competently programmed simulation… They have a lot of hidden complexity. So when you dig deeper you find that there's hidden structure that's not used for anything. Why would you do that, if you're simulating a world? Also the laws are very constrained. They are local; they don't change in time; they don't change in place. In a programmed environment there's no reason to obey any of those constraints… And then there's the embarrassing question of, okay if this is a simulated world, what is the thing in which it is simulated made out of? What are the laws for that? So it begs the question.
- ^ Eggleston, Brian. "Bostrom Review". stanford.edu. Retrieved April 18, 2021.
- ^ Davies, P. C. W. (2004). "Multiverse Cosmological Models". Modern Physics Letters A. 19 (10): 727–743. arXiv:astro-ph/0403047. Bibcode:2004MPLA...19..727D. doi:10.1142/S021773230401357X.
- ^ Jaeger, Gregg (2018). "Clockwork Rebooted: Is the Universe a Computer?". Quantum Foundations, Probability and Information. STEAM-H: Science, Technology, Engineering, Agriculture, Mathematics & Health: 71–91. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-74971-6_8. ISBN 978-3-319-74970-9.
- ^ Gleiser, Marcelo (March 9, 2017). "Why Reality Is Not A Video Game — And Why It Matters". NPR. Retrieved January 18, 2021.
{{cite web}}
: CS1 maint: url-status (link) - ^ a b "Elon Musk Says There's a 'One in Billions' Chance Reality Is Not a Simulation - VICE". www.vice.com.
- ^ "Joe Rogan & Elon Musk - Are We in a Simulated Reality?" – via www.youtube.com.
- ^ Powell, Corey S. "Elon Musk says we may live in a simulation. Here's how we might tell if he's right". www.nbcnews.com.
- ^ "Neil deGrasse Tyson Explains the Simulation Hypothesis".
- ^ Hanson, Robin (2001). "How to live in a simulation" (PDF). Journal of Evolution and Technology. 7.
- ^ Beane, Silas; Zohreh Davoudi; Martin J. Savage (9 November 2012). "Constraints on the Universe as a Numerical Simulation". arXiv:1210.1847. Bibcode:2014EPJA...50..148B. doi:10.1140/epja/i2014-14148-0.
ABSTRACT Observable consequences of the hypothesis that the observed universe is a numerical simulation performed on a cubic space-time lattice or grid are explored. The simulation scenario is first motivated by extrapolating current trends in computational resource requirements for lattice QCD into the future. Using the historical development of lattice gauge theory technology as a guide, we assume that our universe is an early numerical simulation with unimproved Wilson fermion discretization and investigate potentially-observable consequences. Among the observables that are considered are the muon g-2 and the current differences between determinations of alpha, but the most stringent bound on the inverse lattice spacing of the universe, b−1 > ~ 10^11 GeV, is derived from the high-energy cut off of the cosmic ray spectrum. The numerical simulation scenario could reveal itself in the distributions of the highest energy cosmic rays exhibiting a degree of rotational symmetry breaking that reflects the structure of the underlying lattice.
{{cite news}}
: Unknown parameter|lay-date=
ignored (help); Unknown parameter|lay-source=
ignored (help); Unknown parameter|lay-url=
ignored (help) - ^ Moskowitz, Clara (7 April 2016). "Are We Living in a Computer Simulation?". Scientific American.
- ^ Campbell, Tom; Owhadi, Houman; Sauvageau, Joe; Watkinson, David (June 17, 2017). "On Testing the Simulation Theory". International Journal of Quantum Foundations. 3 (3): 78–99.
- ^ Greene, Preston (10 August 2019). "Are We Living in a Computer Simulation? Let's Not Find Out - Experimental findings will be either boring or extremely dangerous". The New York Times. Retrieved 11 August 2019.
- ^ Chalmers, David (January 1990). "How Cartesian Dualism Might Have Been True".
- ^ Conitzer, Vincent (2019). "A Puzzle about Further Facts". Erkenntnis. 84 (3): 727–739. arXiv:1802.01161. doi:10.1007/s10670-018-9979-6. S2CID 36796226.
- ^ "Skepticism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved June 6, 2021.
- ^ a b Pieri, L. (2021). "The Simplicity Assumption and Some Implications of the Simulation Argument for our Civilization". OSF Preprints. doi:10.31219/osf.io/ca8se. Retrieved June 6, 2021.
- ^ Brantley, Ben (January 16, 2012). "'World of Wires' at the Kitchen — Review". The New York Times.
Further reading
- "Are We Living in a Simulation?" BBC Focus magazine, March 2013, pages 43–45. Interview with physicist Silas Beane of the University of Bonn discussing a proposed test for simulated reality evidence. Three pages, three photos, including one of Beane and a computer-generated scene from the film The Matrix. Publisher: Immediate Media Company, Bristol, UK.
- "Do We Live in the Matrix?" by Zeeya Merali, Discover, December 2013, pages 24–25. Subtitle: "Physicists have proposed tests to reveal whether we are part of a giant computer simulation."
- Conitzer, Vincent. A Puzzle about Further Facts. Open access version of article in Erkenntnis.
- Lev, Gid'on. Life in the Matrix. Haaretz Magazine, April 25, 2019, page 6.
- Tom Campbell, Houman Owhadi, Joe Sauvageau, David Watkinson: On testing the simulation theory. arXiv:1703.00058.
- Virk, Rizwan. The Simulation Hypothesis: An MIT Computer Scientist Shows Why AI, Quantum Physics, and Eastern Mystics All Agree We Are In a Video Game.