User:Phlsph7/Value theory - History
History
[edit]The origin of value theory lies in the ancient period, with early reflections on the good life and the ends worth pursuing.[1] Socrates (c. 469–399 BCE)[2] identified the highest good as the right combination of knowledge, pleasure, and virtue, holding that active inquiry is associated with pleasure while knowledge of the good leads to virtuous action.[3] Plato (c. 428–347 BCE)[4] conceived the good as a universal and changeless idea. It is the highest form in his theory of forms, acting as the source of all other forms and the foundation of reality and knowledge.[5] Aristotle (384–322 BCE)[6] saw eudaimonia as the highest good and ultimate goal of human life. He understood eudaimonia as a form of happiness or flourishing achieved through the exercise of virtues in accordance with reason, leading to the full realization of human potential.[7] Epicurus (c. 341–271 BCE) proposed a nuanced egoistic hedonism, stating that personal pleasure is the greatest good while recommending moderation to avoid the negative effects of excessive desires and anxiety about the future.[8] According to the Stoics, a virtuous life following nature and reason is the highest good. They thought that self-mastery and rationality lead to a pleasant equanimity independent of external circumstances.[9] Influenced by Plato, Plotinus (c. 204/5–270 CE) held that the Good is the ultimate principle of reality from which everything emanates. For him, evil is not a distinct opposing principle but merely a deficiency or absence of being resulting from a missing connection to the Good.[10]
In ancient Indian philosophy, the idea that people are trapped in a cycle of rebirths arose around 600 BCE.[11] Many traditions adopted it, arguing that liberation from this cycle is the highest good.[12] Hindu philosophy distinguishes the four fundamental values of duty, economic wealth, sensory pleasure, and liberation.[13] Many Hindu schools of thought prioritize the value of liberation.[14] A similar outlook is found in ancient Buddhist philosophy, starting between the sixth and the fifth centuries BCE, where the cessation of suffering through the attainment of Nirvana is considered the ultimate goal.[15] In ancient China, Confucius (c. 551–479 BCE)[16] explored the role of self-cultivation in leading a virtuous life, viewing general benevolence towards humanity as the supreme virtue.[17] In comparing the highest virtue to water, Laozi (6th century BCE)[a] emphasized the importance of living in harmony with the natural order of the universe.[19]
Religious teachings influenced value theory in the medieval period. Early Christian thinkers, such as St. Augustine of Hippo (354–430 CE),[20] adapted the theories of Plato and Plotinus into a religious framework. They identified God as the ultimate source of existence and goodness, seeing evil as a mere lack or privation of good.[21] Drawing on Aristotelianism, Christian philosopher Thomas Aquinas (1224–1274 CE)[22] said that communion with the divine, achieved through a beatific vision of God, is the highest end of humans.[23] In Arabic–Persian philosophy, al-Farabi (c. 878–950 CE)[24] asserted that the supreme form of human perfection is an intellectual happiness, reachable in the afterlife by developing the intellect to its fullest potential.[25] Avicenna (980–1037 CE)[26] also regarded the intellect as the highest human faculty. He thought that a contemplative life prepares humans for the greatest good, which is only attained in the afterlife when humans are free from bodily distractions.[27] In Indian philosophy, Adi Shankara (c. 700–750 CE)[28] taught that liberation, the highest human end, is reached by realizing that the self is the same as ultimate reality encompassing all of existence.[29] In Chinese thought, the early neo-Confucian philosopher Han Yu (768–824) identified the sage as an ideal role model who, through self-cultivation, achieves personal integrity expressed in harmony between theory and action in daily life.[30]
Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679)[31] understood values as subjective phenomena that depend on a person's interests. He examined how the interests of individuals can be aggregated to guide political decisions.[32] David Hume (1711–1776)[33] agreed with Hobbes's subjectivism, exploring how values differ from objective facts.[34] Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)[35] asserted that the highest good is happiness in proportion to moral virtue. He emphasized the primacy of virtue by respecting the moral law and the inherent value of people, adding that moral virtue is ideally, but not always, accompanied by personal happiness.[36] Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)[37] and John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)[38] formulated classical utilitarianism, combining a hedonist theory about value with a consequentialist theory about right action.[39] Hermann Lotze (1817–1881)[40] developed a philosophy of values, holding that values make the world meaningful as an ordered whole centered around goodness.[41] Influenced by Lotze, the neo-Kantian philosopher Wilhelm Windelband (1848–1915)[42] understood philosophy as a theory of values, claiming that universal values determine the principles that all subjects should follow, including the norms of knowledge and action.[43] Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900)[44] held that values are human creations. He criticized traditional values in general and Christian values in particular, calling for a revaluation of all values centered on life-affirmation, power, and excellence.[45]
Pragmatist philosopher John Dewey (1859–1952)[46] formulated an axiological naturalism. He distinguished values from value judgments, adding that the skill of correct value assessment must be learned through experience.[47][b] G. E. Moore (1873–1958)[49] developed and refined various axiological concepts, such as organic wholes and the contrast between intrinsic and extrinsic value. He defended non-naturalism about the nature of values and intuitionism about the knowledge of values.[50] W. D. Ross (1877–1971)[51] accepted and further elaborated on Moore's intuitionism, using it to formulate an axiological pluralism.[52][c] R. B. Perry (1876–1957)[54] and D. W. Prall (1886–1940)[55] articulated systematic theories of value based on the idea that values originate in affective states such as interest and liking.[56] Robert S. Hartman (1910–1973)[57] developed formal axiology, saying that values measure the level to which a thing embodies its ideal concept.[58] A. J. Ayer (1910–1989)[59] proposed anti-realism about values, arguing that value statements merely express the speaker's approval or disapproval.[60] A different type of anti-realism, formulated by J. L. Mackie (1917–1981),[61] asserts that all value assertions are false since no values exist.[62] G. H. von Wright (1916–2003)[63] provided a conceptual analysis of the term good by distinguishing different meanings or varieties of goodness, such as the technical goodness of a good driver and the hedonic goodness of a good meal.[64]
In continental philosophy, Franz Brentano (1838–1917)[65] formulated an early version of the fitting-attitude theory of value, saying that a thing is good if it is fitting to have a positive attitude towards it, such as love.[66] In the 1890s, his students Alexius Meinong (1853–1920)[67] and Christian von Ehrenfels (1859–1932)[68] conceived the idea of a general theory of values.[69] Edmund Husserl (1859–1938),[70] another of Brentano's students, developed phenomenology and applied this approach to the study of values.[71] Following Husserl's approach, Max Scheler (1874–1928) and Nicolai Hartmann (1882–1950) each proposed a comprehensive system of axiological ethics.[72] Asserting that values have objective reality, they explored how different value types form a value hierarchy and examined the problems of value conflicts and right decisions from this hierarchical perspective.[73] Martin Heidegger (1889–1976)[74] criticized value theory, claiming that it rests on a mistaken metaphysical perspective by understanding values as aspects of things.[75] Existentialist philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980)[76] said that values do not exist by themselves but are actively created, emphasizing the role of human freedom, responsibility, and authenticity in the process.[77]
References
[edit]Notes
[edit]- ^ This period is given in traditional sources. Some contemporary scholars have suggested later dates or questioned whether there was a single person by that name.[18]
- ^ Clarence Irving Lewis (1883-1964) accepted and further elaborated many of Dewey's insights.[48]
- ^ Ross is primarily known for his deontological pluralism about different types of prima facie duties, which is related but not identical to his axiological pluralism about different types of values.[53]
Citations
[edit]- ^
- Frankena 2006, pp. 636–637
- Li 2014, p. 3
- Chang 2001, pp. 68–69
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 178
- ^
- Sharma 1991, pp. 27–28
- Devettere 2002, pp. 33–34
- Heinaman 2016, pp. 123–124
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 156
- ^
- Honderich 2005, p. 349
- Bahm 1993, p. 112
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 13
- ^
- Hiles 2008, pp. 52–53
- Frankena 2006, p. 639
- Crisp 2005, p. 349
- ^
- O’Keefe, § 5. Ethics
- Gaskin 2005, p. 258
- Frankena 2006, p. 639
- ^
- Durand, Shogry & Baltzly 2023, § 4. Ethics
- Pigliucci, § 3. The Third Topos: Ethics, § 4. Apatheia and the Stoic Treatment of Emotions
- ^
- Bahm 1993, p. 112
- Darr 2023, p. 108
- Emilsson 1998, Lead section
- ^ Borgolte 2019, p. 97
- ^
- Sharma 1999, p. 230
- Bartley 2020, pp. 37–38, 136
- ^
- Ranganathan, § 1a.iii. Puruṣārthas : dharma, artha, kāma and mokṣa
- Sharma 1999, pp. 223–225, 230
- Bailey 2011
- ^ Sharma 1999, p. 230
- ^ Wilson 2010
- ^ Littlejohn, § 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects
- ^
- Ebrey 2010, p. 43
- Sim 2015, pp. 64, 74
- Richey, § 6. Self-cultivation
- Littlejohn, § 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects
- ^ Chan 2018, Lead section, § 2. Date and Authorship of the Laozi
- ^
- Assandri 2021, pp. 70–71
- Boyd & Timpe 2021, p. 64
- Slingerland 2007, p. 77
- Chan 2018, Lead section
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 16
- ^
- Bahm 1993, p. 112
- Frankena 2006, p. 639
- Darr 2023, p. 108
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 185
- ^
- Wieland 2002, p. 59
- Zagzebski 2004, p. 350
- Peterson 2008, p. 235
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 63
- ^ Germann 2021, § 2.1 Happiness and the afterlife
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 19
- ^ McGinnis 2010, pp. 209–210
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 175
- ^ Dalal 2021, Lead section
- ^
- Berthrong, § 3. The Emergence of Neo-Confucianism
- Hartman 1998
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 88
- ^ Hardin 2009, p. [1]
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 91
- ^
- Hardin 2009, p. [2]
- Li 2014, p. 3
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 105
- ^
- Engstrom 1992, pp. 747
- Johnson & Cureton 2024, § 1. Aims and Methods of Moral Philosophy, § 2. Good Will, Moral Worth and Duty
- Direk 2014, pp. 373–374
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 25
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 132
- ^
- Frankena 2006, p. 639
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, § 1. Classic Utilitarianism
- Chenneville 2017, p. 5
- Hearn 1971, p. 2
- ^ Woodward 2015, p. i
- ^
- Sullivan 2023, § 5.3 Value Theory
- Li 2014, p. 3
- Sullivan 1998, § 4. Metaphysics
- Milkov, § 3a. Ethics
- Frankena 2006, p. 636
- ^ Dafermos 2018, p. 20
- ^
- Heis 2018, § 3.1 Conception of Philosophy: Philosophy as Theory of Value
- Kinzel 2024, § 2. From Kant to the Philosophy of Values
- Hiles 2008, p. 52
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 144
- ^
- Frankena 2006, pp. 636, 639
- Li 2014, p. 4
- Anderson 2024, § 3. Value Creation
- Hiles 2008, p. 52
- Direk 2014, pp. 374, 378
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 52
- ^
- Hart 1971, pp. 36–38
- Marcum 2008, p. 192
- ^ Hart 1971, pp. 37–38
- ^ Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 443
- ^
- Findlay 1970, pp. 2, 37–38, 41
- Dancy 2004, p. 165
- Hart 1971, pp. 33
- ^ Kunnan 2020, p. 86
- ^
- Mason 2023, § 1.1 Foundational and Non-foundational Pluralism
- Simpson, Lead section, § 6. Ross’s Ethical Theory: Main Components and Principles
- Findlay 1970, p. 2
- ^ Mason 2023, § 1.1 Foundational and Non-foundational Pluralism
- ^ Anderson 2013, p. 222
- ^ Townsend 2006, p. xvi
- ^
- Hart 1971, p. 31
- Frankena 2006, p. 637
- ^ Edwards & Hartman 2023, p. 173
- ^
- Edwards 2021, pp. 3–4
- Hartman 2011, pp. 105–106
- ^ Tuboly 2021, p. 2
- ^ Hart 1971, pp. 34–35
- ^ Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 406
- ^ Sayre-McCord 1988, pp. 11–12
- ^ Rosenkrantz & Hoffman 2011, p. 332
- ^
- Frankena 2006, pp. 637–638
- Ylirisku & Arvola 2018, p. 53
- ^ Kriegel 2018, pp. 2
- ^
- ^ Kuijper 2022, p. 298
- ^ Zimmer 2017, p. 135
- ^
- Frankena 2006, p. 637
- Hart 1971, pp. 30–31
- ^ Kuijper 2022, p. 298
- ^
- Frankena 2006, p. 637
- Direk 2014, pp. 371–372
- ^
- Frankena 2006, p. 637
- Findlay 1970, p. 2
- Hart 1971, p. 32
- Direk 2014, pp. 371–372
- Løgstrup 2020, p. 105
- ^
- Frankena 2006, pp. 637–639
- Findlay 1970, p. 2
- Hart 1971, p. 32
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 83
- ^
- Direk 2014, pp. 372–373, 384–386
- Findlay 1970, pp. 2–3
- Sullivan 2023, § 5.3 Value Theory
- ^ Dehsen 2013, p. 168
- ^
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 426–428
- Direk 2014, pp. 384–385
Sources
[edit]- Heinaman, Robert (2016). Plato and Aristotle's Ethics. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-351-91076-7.
- Devettere, Raymond J. (2002). Introduction to Virtue Ethics: Insights of the Ancient Greeks. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-1-58901-817-4.
- Sharma, R. N. (1991). Plato an Interdisciplinary Perspective. Atlantic Publishers & Distributors.
- Marcum, James A. (2008). An Introductory Philosophy of Medicine: Humanizing Modern Medicine. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-1-4020-6797-6.
- Ylirisku, Salu; Arvola, Mattias (2018). "The Varieties of Good Design". In Vermaas, Pieter E.; Vial, Stéphane (eds.). Advancements in the Philosophy of Design. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-73302-9.
- Simpson, David L. "Ross, William David". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 September 2024.
- Anderson, R. Lanier (2024). "Friedrich Nietzsche". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Kinzel, Katherina (2024). "Wilhelm Windelband". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Heis, Jeremy (2018). "Neo-Kantianism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Sullivan, David (1998). "Lotze, Rudolph Hermann (1817–81)". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-DC049-1. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Milkov, Nikolay. "Lotze, Rudolph Hermann". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Sullivan, David (2023). "Hermann Lotze". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam (2024). "Kant's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Engstrom, Stephen (1992). "The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant's Moral Theory". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 52 (4). doi:10.2307/2107910.
- Hardin, Russell (2009). David Hume: Moral and Political Theorist. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-161013-4.
- Dalal, Neil (2021). "Śaṅkara". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Hartman, Charles (1998). "Han Yu (768–824)". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-G034-1. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Berthrong, John H. "Neo-Confucian Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- McGinnis, Jon (2010). Avicenna. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-533147-9.
- Germann, Nadja (2021). "al-Farabi's Philosophy of Society and Religion". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Sharma, Arvind (1999). "The Purusārthas: An Axiological Exploration of Hinduism". Journal of Religious Ethics. 27 (2). doi:10.1111/0384-9694.00016.
- Ranganathan, Shyam. "Hindu Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Richey, Jeff. "Confucius". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Assandri, Friederike (2021). The Daode Jing Commentary of Cheng Xuanying: Daoism, Buddhism, and the Laozi in the Tang Dynasty. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-087645-6.
- Sim, May (2015). "Why Confucius' Ethics is a Virtue Ethics". In Besser-Jones, Lorraine; Slote, Michael (eds.). The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-09669-4.
- Ebrey, Patricia Buckley (2010). The Cambridge Illustrated History of China. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-12433-1.
- Honderich, Ingrid Coggin (2005). "Good, Form of the". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Crisp, Roger (2005). "Good, Greatest". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Chang, Jiang (2001). "Axiology and Ethics: Past, Present, and Future". The Future of Value Inquiry. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-49451-0.
- Arneson, Pat (18 August 2009). "Axiology". In Littlejohn, Stephen W.; Foss, Karen A. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Communication Theory. SAGE Publications. ISBN 978-1-4129-5937-7.
- Gaskin, J. C. A. (2005). "Epicurus". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- O’Keefe, Tim. "Epicurus". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 September 2024.
- Pigliucci, Massimo. "Stoicism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Durand, Marion; Shogry, Simon; Baltzly, Dirk (2023). "Stoicism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Darr, Ryan (2023). The Best Effect: Theology and the Origins of Consequentialism. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-82999-9.
- Bartley, Christopher (2020). Indian Philosophy A-Z. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-8084-9.
- Wilson, Jeff (2010). "Saṃsāra and Rebirth". Oxford Bibliographies. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/obo/9780195393521-0141. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Bailey, Greg (2011). "Puruṣārthas". Oxford Bibliographies. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/obo/9780195399318-0044. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Borgolte, Michael (2019). World History as the History of Foundations, 3000 BCE to 1500 CE. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-41508-9.
- Littlejohn, Ronnie. "Chinese Philosophy: Overview of History". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Chan, Alan (2018). "Laozi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Emilsson, Eyjólfur Kjalar (1998). "Plotinus (AD 204/5–70)". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-A090-1. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Wieland, Georg (2002). "Happiness (Ia IIae, qq. 1–5)". In Pope, Stephen J. (ed.). The Ethics of Aquinas. Translated by Kaplan, Grant. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-0-87840-888-7.
- Peterson, John (2008). Aquinas: A New Introduction. University Press of America. ISBN 978-0-7618-4180-7.
- Zagzebski, Linda (2004). "Morality and Religion". In Wainwright, William (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-803158-1.
- Woodward, William R. (2015). Hermann Lotze. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-41848-5.
- Dafermos, Manolis (2018). Rethinking Cultural-Historical Theory: A Dialectical Perspective to Vygotsky. Springer Nature Singapore. ISBN 978-981-13-0191-9.
- Kunnan, Antony John (2020). "A Case for an Ethics-Based Approach to Evaluate Language". In Ockey, Gary J.; Green, Brent A. (eds.). Another Generation of Fundamental Considerations in Language Assessment: A Festschrift in Honor of Lyle F. Bachman. Springer Nature Singapore. ISBN 978-981-15-8952-2.
- Anderson, Douglas R. (2013). "Peirce: Pragmatism and Nature after Hegel". In Schrift, Alan D. (ed.). The History of Continental Philosophy. Vol. 2. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-74049-2.
- Townsend, Dabney (2006). Historical Dictionary of Aesthetics. Scarecrow Press. ISBN 978-0-8108-6483-2.
- Edwards, Rem; Hartman, Robert S. (2023). Poff, Deborah C.; Michalos, Alex C. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-22767-8.
- Tuboly, Adam Tamas (2021). "Introduction: From Spying to Canonizing—Ayer and His Language, Truth and Logic". The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic. Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 978-3-030-50884-5.
- Rosenkrantz, Gary S.; Hoffman, Joshua (2011). Historical Dictionary of Metaphysics. Scarecrow Press. ISBN 978-0-8108-5950-0.
- Kriegel, Uriah (2017). "Introduction". The Routledge Handbook of Franz Brentano and the Brentano School. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-69055-9.
- Kuijper, Hans (2022). Comprehending the Complexity of Countries: The Way Ahead. Springer Nature Singapore. ISBN 978-981-16-4709-3.
- Løgstrup, K. E. (2020). Ethical Concepts and Problems. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-260282-4.
- Zimmer, Alfred (2017). "Christian von Ehrenfels (1859–1932)". In Albertazzi, Liliana; Jacquette, Dale (eds.). The School of Alexius Meinong. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-351-88226-2.